Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World
  • What’s So Funny About the Law?

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Marxism in Crisis

    August 16, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe: Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics. Second edition. London: Verso, 2014.

     

    First published in 1985, reissued with a new preface a decade after the collapse of the Soviet empire derailed Marxist ‘praxis’ in Central and Eastern Europe, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy has become a touchstone for the newer iterations of the New Left, the Left that departed from many if not all of the tenets of ‘scientific socialism’ as formulated by Marx and Engels, and especially as it had been propounded by V. I. Lenin. Precisely because Marxism attempts to unify theory and practice, the initial success of Leninist Marxism in Russia and its failure elsewhere (notably in Germany), funneled socialists into Marxism-Leninism. Prior to the Bolshevik revolution, the authors contend, Marxian thought had become “increasingly diversified,” but after it this “creative process” was derailed. Initially, the divergent voice of Antonio Gramsci, raised in the 1920s, received no fair hearing from mainstream socialists. This is no longer so, as “the problems of a globalized and information-ruled society are unthinkable” within the frameworks of either the idealist-Hegelian or the Marxist-materialist versions of historicism.

    Marxist materialism, especially, centered on socioeconomic classes as the drivers of ‘history,’ i.e., the course of human events. Socioeconomic classes are sub-political groupings. Laclau and Mouffe vindicate a political understanding of socialism, and of modernity generally. Modern political life, even in commercial republics, isn’t simply dominated by economics and by the ‘capitalists’ who enjoy considerable sway within them. Politics has its own integrity as an independent variable, as it were, in the course of events, influenced by but also influencing social and economic life. Marxism additionally suffers from an epistemological deficiency, “the illusion of immediacy.” That is, its proponents assume that reality presents itself to our minds, through our senses, very much as it is, with little regard to the filters imposed by language and other ‘cultural’ phenomena. This is reminiscent of Socrates’ criticisms of the Greek natural philosophers and his turn to political philosophy, but Laclau and Mouffe are Socratic in no other way. They cite such philosophers as Wittgenstein, Heidegger, the structuralists, and the deconstructionists as the relevant critics of epistemological “immediacy.”  Behind them all is Nietzsche with his doctrine of the will to power, oriented as it is not to seeking truth but to enhancing life, very much in opposition to Socratic inquiry. Nietzsche follows Machiavelli and subsequent ‘moderns,’ who reduce politics to power, a motif the New Left has continued. Laclau and Mouffe borrow the term ‘hegemony’ from Gramsci; for him, the heart of ‘politics’ is power, not only physical but ‘cultural’—the power intellectual frameworks exert upon our thoughts, and through thoughts our actions. To understand politics as hegemony “retriev[es] an act of political institution that finds its source and motivation nowhere but in itself.” Human beings can choose their political actions; those actions are “contingent,” not simply determined by sub-political forces that drive it on. “This privileging of the political moment in the structuration of society is an essential aspect of our approach.” If politics is to some important degree self-determining, one of the most important ‘scientific’ predictions of Marxism-Leninism cannot be true; there can be no “withering away of the state,” as Lenin claims in The State and Revolution. 

    Further, the fundamental cause of ‘history,’ the famous dialectic of class conflict Marx posits, cannot account for what Laclau and Mouffe call “social antagonism.” “Antagonisms are not objective relations,” susceptible to scientific explanation and prediction, “but relations that reveal the limits of all objectivity,” limits seen precisely in the importance of free choice, of ‘subjectivity,’ in class conflict and politics alike. “There is no ‘cunning of reason'”—whether guided by Hegel’s Absolute Spirit or Marx’s dialectical materialism—which “would realize itself through antagonistic relations.” Social antagonism is quite real, and political conflict registers that reality, but it doesn’t work the way Marx said it did, and it therefore should not issue in a regime of the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’—in practice the dictatorship of a political party, often itself dictated to by a tyrant. The authors favor not tyranny or oligarchy but a regime of “democratic socialism.” It will remain to be seen if that is not itself a contradiction in terms.

    However that may be, the authors wish “that the collapse of the Soviet model would have given a renewed impetus to democratic socialist parties,” instead of discrediting socialism itself and empowering “neo-liberalism,” as seen in the administrations of Margaret Thatcher in Great Britain and Ronald Reagan in the United States. As of the turn of this century, socialists themselves had retreated, “redefining themselves euphemistically as ‘center-left'” parties. Consistent with their political approach, Laclau and Mouffe demand regime change, revolution, “the establishment of a new hegemony,” a new power structure. “No doubt it is a good thing that the Left has finally come to terms with the importance of pluralism and of liberal-democratic institutions, but the problem is that this has been accompanied by the mistaken belief that it meant abandoning any attempt at transforming the present hegemonic order.” What is needed, then, is a regime of “liberty and equality” that extends “the democratic struggles for equality and liberty to a wider range of social relations,” as Left elaborates “a credible alternative to the neo-liberal order, instead of simply trying to manage it in a more humane way.” This will require, among other things redefining the adversaries of the Left. There is no such thing as “a non-exclusive public sphere of rational argument,” since regimes always define what is just and what is unjust, including and excluding as they go. “We will never be able to leave our particularities completely aside in order to act in accordance with our rational self.” But socialists should nonetheless strive to approximate “a harmony that we cannot attain” in practice. More egalitarian distribution of economic goods, yes; more egalitarian distribution of social ‘recognition’ (older writers would have said, ‘honors’), yes to that, as well. “Our motto is: ‘Back to the hegemonic struggle,”” the regime struggle that socialist preoccupation with sub-political causation and ’causes’ had obscured.

    In constituting a new socialist strategy, socialist organizers have a much more complex task than that envisioned by Marxists. Feminism, ethnic and national ‘movements,’ demands for ‘gay rights,’ environmentalism, anti-nuclear protest, struggles “in countries on the capitalist periphery,” all “imply an extension of social conflictuality [sic] to a wide range of areas, which creates the potential, but no more than the potential, for an advance towards more freed, democratic and egalitarian societies.” The proletariat can no longer serve as the central organizing point for socialists, as it now stands exposed as “the illusory prospect of a perfectly unitary and homogeneous collective will that will render pointless the moment of politics.” Today’s social struggles are too “plural and multifarious” to make such a simplistic conception of society plausible in theory or useful in practice. ‘History’ as conceived by the Left, ‘Society’ as conceived by the Left, as intellectually comprehensible and practically ruled as if rational and transparent, susceptible to “a founding act of a political character,” a ‘social contract,’ can no longer be sustained. “Today, the Let is witnessing the final act of the dissolution of that Jacobin imaginary.” Marxism’s “monist aspiration to capture with its categories the essence or underlying meaning of History,” seen in its bestowal of an “ontologically privileged position of a ‘universal class,'” the proletariat, must be abandoned. But Marxism in its several permutations formulated between the death of Engels and the ascendancy of Lenin must be understood, as its theorists at that time already understood many of the problems inherent in the original theory. As early as the 1890s, a century before the failure of the Marxist-Leninist regimes and indeed some two decades before the founding of the Soviet Union, these theorists understood that Marxism was in crisis.

    The key concept of hegemony arose as the response to that crisis—again, well before Gramsci, although he would articulate it better than his predecessors. The authors begin with Rosa Luxemburg and her book, The Mass Strike, the Political Party and the Trade Unions. Published in 1906, it addressed the violent labor conflicts that has wracked Europe for the past ten years or more. Luxemburg believed the mass strike a means of uniting the working class on the road to revolution in Europe. She therefore needed to connect economic struggle with political struggle. In Germany, unlike Russia, the working class was fragmented, thanks to parliamentarism, which reflects the ordinary “course of bourgeois society,” in which “the economic struggle is split into a multitude of individual struggles in every undertaking and dissolved in every branch of production.” This fragmentation could only be “overcome in a revolutionary atmosphere.” Social democrats, she wrote, must show the proletariat “the inevitable advent of this revolutionary period, the inner social factors making for it and the political consequences of it.” The workers will then see the part their actions take in the larger “struggle against the system,” “the revolutionary process as a whole.” The spontaneous, contingent character of these events (it contemporary equivalent being the ‘flash mob’) exceeds the control or planning of trade union or political ‘leaders,’ many of whom are already compromised by the commercial and parliamentary life within the Kaiser Reich. 

    Laclau and Mouffe applaud Luxemburg’s attempt to link economic and political struggle. But she failed to understand that economic and class struggles do not automatically cohere. Economic class partakes of necessity; spontaneous political action partakes of freedom. Each is “the purely negative reverse of the other.” Political subjects do not necessarily act in their economic-class interests, and the failure to see that this blinds socialists who are too committed to the determinist theory orthodox Marxism. The struggles against imperialism, the fights against fascism, the complexity of meeting the challenges posed by bourgeois reforms intended to perpetuate capitalism—all of these reveal not determinism but indeterminacy. All raise questions that require “a socialist answer in a politico-discursive universe that has witnessed a withdrawal of the category of ‘necessity’ to the horizon of the social.” 

    Luxemburg was reacting to the passive, more or less apolitical democratic socialism of Karl Kautsky. If ‘History’ marches on, whatever human beings say or do, Kautsky, writing in the 1890s, assumed that socialists need only wait, propagandizing and organizing, reinforcing working-class identities without much political action at all. As he put it, “Our task is not to organize the revolution but to organize ourselves for the revolution; not to make the revolution but to take advantage of it.” In this “war of attrition,” allies beyond the working class are useless, or even worse than useless, because they must, as per Marx, become increasingly ‘reactionary’ as the revolutionary crisis nears. Capitalism will change and eventually collapse, “but this change is nothing more than the unfolding of its endogenous tendencies and contradictions.” 

    But by the end of the decade, the Czech parliamentarian Thomas Masaryk called Kautsky’s complacency into question, announcing “the crisis of Marxism.” “This crisis,” the authors write, “which served as the background to all Marxist debates from the turn of the century until the war, seems to have been dominated by two basic moments: the new awareness of an opacity of the social, of the complexities and resistances of an increasingly organized capitalism; and the fragmentation of the different positions of social agents, which, according to the classical [Marxist] paradigm should have been united.” “Marxism finally lost its innocence at that time.” Kautsky himself attempted to ‘save’ Marxism, admitting that trade unionism alone could not “guarantee either the unity or the socialist determination of the working class.” These ends could only be achieved in a frankly political struggle, subordinate trade unions to the socialist party. Nonetheless, the part should maintain its own unity, and thereby working-class unity, by making itself “the depository of science, that is, of Marxist theory.” Determinism remains, under the formula that the “sole freedom consists in being the consciousness of necessity,” a consciousness “guaranteed by Marxist science.” Kautsky would redeem Marxism by giving it a slightly ‘Hegelian’ inflection. Still, Laclau and Mouffe deem this an advance toward acknowledgment of a dualism between a “logic of necessity” and a “logic of contingency.” 

    Another socialist who diverged somewhat from Marxism was Max Adler, a key figure among the Austro-Marxians. Given the Austro-Hungarian Empire’s dual monarchy and the many nations within it, Adler saw that working-class unity “depended upon constant political initiative.” “In this mosaic of social and national situations, it was impossible to think of national identities as ‘superstructural’ or of class unity as a necessary consequence of the infrastructure.” The Empire’s political economy was obviously too complex to be conceived in terms of Marxian dialectic, at least in the straightforward, not to say stark form that Marx and Engels gave it. Further, Adler grounded his philosophy not only on Marx or on Hegel but on Kant. The universality of Kantian ethics “broadened the audience for socialism and also broke with determinism. In sum, Marxian historicism did not seem plausible. All this notwithstanding, the Austro-Marxists never completely broke with the dichotomy of the logic of necessity and the logic of contingency, reluctant as they were to give up on at least some degree of confidence that the workers ‘must’ win, in the end.

    The Marxian ‘Revisionists’ took things a step further, carving out some “particular spheres” of political initiative, spheres undetermined by economic forces, for socialists to undertake. Like Adler, the German social democrat Eduard Bernstein questioned Hegelian-Marxian historical determinism, but he also pointed to changes that had occurred within capitalist civil societies, beginning with the monopoly firms that had begun to dominate the economic landscape in the second half of the 19th century. The middle classes and the peasantry were not sinking into poverty; no serious economic crisis loomed. Even the modern working class was “not the dispossessed mass of which Marx and Engels wrote in the Manifesto.” This being so, “socialism had to change its terrain and strategy, and the key theoretical moment was the break with the rigid base/superstructure distinction that had prevented any conception of the autonomy of the political.” What, then, can be done to unite socialists? Only a political party founded on “the general interest of those who depend on income for their labor” could be sufficiently broad to wield any real political power. Organizing such a party, however, “escapes the chain of necessity.” “History was not a simple objective process: will also played a role in it.” As with Kant, “the autonomy of the ethical subject was the basis of Bernstein’s break with determinism.”

    Bernstein’s analysis had weaknesses of its own, however. He clung to the Marxist claim that the working class would lead the socialist party. And although he abandoned historicist dialectic, he retained a faith that history’s general trend was evolutionary; he was a ‘progressive.’ And each step in the progress toward democratic socialism was irreversible. He optimistically assumed that the modern state itself would become “increasingly democratic as a necessary consequence of ‘historical evolution.'” Even as Bernstein sat in the parliament of the Weimar Republic, Mussolini ruled Italy and Hitlerism gathered strength in Germany. Laclau and Mouffe argue that socialist advances are “always reversible.” Moreover, if the ‘law of progress’ isn’t really a law at all, and if “the worker is no longer just proletarian but also citizen, consumer and participant in a plurality of positions within the country’s cultural and institutional apparatus,” then the eventual regime form that issues from a party led by workers may not be socialist at all. Under those circumstances, “democratic advance will necessitate a proliferation of political initiative in different social areas,” and “the meaning of each initiative comes to depend upon its relation with the others.” 

    Still another, and much more dramatic, response to the crisis of Marxism was formulated by Georges Sorel under the term, ‘revolutionary syndicalism.’ Sorel rejected historical determinism entirely, taking from Marx only the recognition that the proletariat could become the agent with the moral fervor needed to “supplant declining bourgeois society,” constituting itself “as a dominant force and impos[ing] its will on the rest of society.” That is, Sorel took as much or more from his contemporary Henri Bergson’s élan vital as from Marx. Sorel’s version of class warfare derives from Bergsonian élan and, behind it, Nietzsche’s will to power. Initially, Sorel democratized Nietzsche, urging the proletariat to grasp the “heroic future” he wanted it to realize. But as socialism in his native France, and neighboring Germany, became increasingly unheroic, content with parliamentary jockeying, he began to invoke not the practice but the “myth” of the general strike, writing that “strikes have engendered in the proletariat the noblest, deepest and most moving sentiments that they possess.” Their violence “is the only force that can keep alive the antagonism described by Marx,” even if this force is no longer primarily literal, as it was for Luxemburg, but, well, literary, poetic—a spur to spiritedness to be set against middle-class tepidness. This led some of his followers to the supplementary myth of nationalism, which they regarded as the best sentiment to bring about the triumph of “heroic values over the ignoble bourgeois materialism” of present-day Europe. Sorel himself welcomed the Bolshevik Revolution, not nationalist myth, as the sort of violent upheaval that could spread across Europe and wreck the bourgeoisie.

    In Russia, Lenin and Trotsky stayed within the framework of Marxian determinism, but the Social Democrats had developed “the concept of ‘hegemony.'” It was Antonio Gramsci who combined this with Sorel’s concept of the socialist historical ‘bloc,’ not as a material-economic entity (which partakes too much of modern-bourgeois self-interest) but as a bearer of heroism in the all-too-mediocre modern world. Russian social democrats (for example, Alexander Plekhanov) introduced ‘hegemony’ “to describe the process whereby the impotence of the Russian bourgeoisie to carry through its ‘normal’ struggle for political liberty forced the working class to intervene decisively to achieve it.” That is, the working class in Russia wasn’t impelled by material conditions; it chose to enter the political struggle. Whereas in Europe the move from economic conditions to political action occurred within the proletariat and was directed against the bourgeoisie, in Russia the bourgeoisie hadn’t won its own liberty, and so the proletariat took up that fight on its own. If “the bourgeois class cannot fulfill its role…this has to be taken over” by the workers. The “democratic tasks remain bourgeois, even when their historical agent is the working class.” This is what the Russian social democrats meant by ‘hegemony.’ 

    Lenin also saw that “hegemony involves political leadership within a class alliance,” but despised political liberty. He would mouth the principles of ‘bourgeois democracy’ in order to establish useful alliances with useful idiots before the revolution, but after his victory he would abolish the liberties prized by his erstwhile allies. Lenin “transferred” the “ontological privilege granted to the working class by Marxism” from the workers to “the political leadership of the mass movement”—that is, to himself, as the leader of the vanguard party of the vanguard class. The Communist Party “knows the underlying movement of history, and knows therefore the temporary character of the demands uniting the masses as a whole.” The Party becomes “the seat of epistemological privilege,” the “depository of science,” establishing “a rigid separation between leaders and led within the masses.” This “possibility” of what Laclau and Mouffe rather delicately call an “authoritarian turn” was “in some way, present from the beginnings of Marxist orthodoxy.” “Leninism evidently makes no attempt to construct, through struggle, a mass identity not predetermined by any necessary law of history,” a law “accessible only to the enlightened vanguard.” And “because the real working class is, of course, far from fully identifying with its ‘historical interests'” as defined by Marxist-Leninist rulers, “the dissociation” between leaders and led “becomes permanent,” and an ossified oligarchic regime develops, within a couple of generations. “The roots of authoritarian policies lie in this interweaving of science and politics,” the authors observe, weakly; throughout the book, the mass murders of ‘Left’ tyranny/totalitarianism remain scrupulously unmentioned. The closest they come is to allow that “a martial conception of class struggle…concludes in an eschatological epic.” A few pages later, we learn of “the great merit” of Mao Zedong’s “analysis of contradiction,” which transcended class struggle, narrowly conceived. Under Mao, this did indeed broaden the killing field.

    The lesson Laclau and Mouffe would rather draw is much more benign. The variety of egalitarian “agents” needs “political construction and struggle” to realize revolutionary potential; unity is “not the expression of a common underlying essence” that crystallizes of its own accord, like the chemicals in a children’s chemistry demonstration. This is where Gramsci intervened, “broaden[ing] the terrain of political recomposition and hegemony, while offering a theorization of the hegemonic link which clearly went beyond the Leninist category of ‘class alliance.” In one way, Gramsci re-Hegelianizes Marxism by insisting that political organizing requires not only “a coincidence of interests” that make alliances possible—alliances that are likely here today, gone tomorrow—but shared moral and intellectual principles. (Not without reason: the long list of Communist betrayals eventually made prospective allies rather wary of any coalition. Principled collaboration likely provides a strong bond.) “Thus, everything depends on how ideology is conceived.” For Gramsci, “ideology” is neither a mere epiphenomenon, reflecting the material interests of a given class, nor a pattern of abstractions. It is “an organic and relational whole, embodied in institutions and apparatuses, which welds together a historical bloc around a number of basic articulatory principles.” Nor is ideology the result of “ideological inculcation by a hegemonic class of a whole range of subordinate sectors,” relieved of their ‘false consciousness’ by an enlightened vanguard. All the partners contribute. “For Gramsci, political subjects are not—strictly speaking—classes, but complex ‘collective wills’.” That is, many “dispersed wills with heterogeneous aims are welded together with a single aim, on the basis of an equal and common conception of the world,” and many of those wills have little or nothing to do with the economic class of the ones who will. Politically, this means that Gramsci, unlike Lenin, does not recommend seizing the power of an existing state but the formation of a state ‘from below,’ within a civil society; this new-formed state will displace the ruling state. 

    The authors demur on one point. Gramsci retains the assumption that the working class is the fundamental driver of egalitarian revolution. “This is the inner essentialist core of Gramsci’s thought, setting a limit to the deconstructive logic of hegemony.” That is, taking a social entity to have an essence, and indeed to take society itself to have one, puts a limit to the capacity to deconstruct it in a sufficiently radical manner, preparatory to making it thoroughly egalitarian. As a result, Gramsci also retains the Marx’s military metaphors, with the “war of position” only partially displacing “class warfare.” True, Gramsci’s “war of position” runs deeper and wider than that of Marx and Lenin, working toward “the progressive disaggregation of a civilization,” not a mere economic system, “and the construction of another around a new class core.” This means that “the identity of the opponents, far from being fixed from the beginning” (capitalists) “constantly changes in the process”—civilizational opponents in what would later be called a ‘culture war’ are numerous and diverse. Gramsci would unify a diverse Left, which would then divide, and eventually defeat, a diverse but increasingly disunified Right. Yet Gramsci’s insistence on valorizing a working-class core for the Left leaves his dilution of Marxist militarism incomplete. What is needed is a genuinely radical historicism (it must be said, likely drawn from Heidegger, not Hegel or Marx), in this case one that remains true to egalitarianism of a certain kind, namely, “democratic plurality.” The authors evidently expect this combination of democracy with pluralism, thoroughly institutionalized, to prevent both tyranny and eventual bureaucratic ossification— a vindication of democratic socialism against Bolshevism and its imitators. Institutionalized pluralism will block any tyrant from dominating the state while bringing contestation into the state apparatus itself, making bureaucracy political, not ‘scientific’-geometric, liable to rigidity.

    Social-democratic parties after the First World War exhibited a “narrowly classist mentality,” incapable of “hegemoniz[ing] the broad range of democratic demands and antagonisms resulting from the post-war crisis.” They became “a mere parliamentary instrument of trade unionism.” Such classism made the tyrannical regimes and parties of the Left strong, bringing one of them to power in Russia and threatening the ‘bourgeois democracies’ elsewhere. Lacking the tyrannical devices of the ‘hard’ Left, democratic socialists remained weak. They lacked the political heft needed to achieve regime change, revolution. This left them with alternatives: “either to participate in bourgeois cabinets in order to obtain the maximum number of social measures favorable to working-class sectors; or else, to enter into opposition and thereby to double [their] impotence.” Further, their continued faith in the ‘iron laws of history’—specifically, economic determinism—inclined them to neglect the serious political organizing needed to forge the needed links to groups outside their own milieu. 

    Mugged by the reality of the Great Depression, democratic socialists changed strategy. The Depression put the working classes under pressure, making the ‘classism’ of socialists more cogent and politically effective. The ‘planned economy’ began to seem a sensible alternative to the increasingly sharp ups and downs of capitalism. “The ‘planism’ of the 1930s was the first expression of the new type of attitude,” an attitude known as Keynesianism in the Anglosphere, but which Mouffe in particular understandably associates with her fellow Belgian, Henri de Man. President of the Belgian Labor Party and eventually Minister of Finance from 1936 to 1938, de Man successfully implemented the nationalization of bank credit while retaining capitalist enterprises—much to the fury of his fellow social democrats, who accused him of fascism, a charge his collaboration with the Nazis after the 1940 invasion did nothing to deflect. The authors prefer to point to de Man’s “attempt to recast the objectives of the socialist movement in a radically new, anti-economist” direction.” “He was one of the first socialists seriously to study psychoanalysis”; he criticized “class reductionism” and understood “the necessity of a mass bloc broader than the working class,” the “need to put forward socialism as a national alternative” (again, raising the then-lively specter of fascism in the minds of his colleagues), and the need of a Sorelian “myth” as a means of “cement[ing] the diverse components of a collective socialist will.” “The ‘Plan’ was, therefore, not a simple economistic instrument; it was the very ais for the reconstitution of a historical bloc which would make it possible to combat the decline of bourgeois society and to counter the advance of fascism.” If so, Nazism, to say nothing of de Man’s own shortcomings (of which the authors do in fact say nothing), aborted the effort.

    Democratic socialism remained self-handicapped in the decades following the Second World War. “Planism’ remained very much in vogue, aiming “to establish a mixed economy in which the capitalist sector would gradually disappear”—a “road of transition to socialism.” This aim was vitiated by “a more technocratic variant” aiming at “merely to create an area of State intervention which would correct—particularly through the control of credit—the imbalances inherent in the course of capitalism,” with no intention of eliminating capitalism itself. In both variants, “social democracy became a politico-economic alternative within a given State form, and not a radical alternative to that form.” 

    In all of this, economic life remained, “the last redoubt of essentialism” on the intellectual map of the Left, the last driver of a supposed march of ‘History’ toward socialism. Along with other economic determinists, Marxists posit laws of socioeconomic motion which “exclude all indeterminacy resulting from political or other external interventions.” Further, “the unity and homogeneity of social agents, constituted at the economic level, just result from the very laws of motion of this level.” And finally, “the positions of these agents in the relations of production must endow them with ‘historical ‘interests,’ so that the presence of such agents at other social levels…must ultimately be explained on the basis of economic interests.” The problem with this is simple enough: the Greek word economia means the management of the household but ‘the economy’ in the modern sense means political economy, the way goods and services are managed within a state. But political life is, as the authors like to say, contingent, subject to public choices. Indeed, Aristotle remarks that the three fundamental forms of ruling—husband-wife, parents-children, master-slave—are already easily discernible within the household, which forms the basic unit of the political community. 

    Marxism takes these assumptions and draws from them three “theses”: the noncontingent “neutrality” (politically speaking) of productive forces in the economy; the inevitability of increasing “homogenization and impoverishment of the working class”; and that class’s “fundamental interest in socialism.” All of these claims are false. Labor-power isn’t politically neutral because it isn’t a commodity. “The capitalist must do more than simply purchase it; he must also make it produce labor.” He must rule the workers in the workplace. This makes the labor process “the ground of a struggle,” in which the vigilance, technical control, and (in larger firms) bureaucratic control of the bosses confront workers who do not necessarily want to be watched and controlled. At the same time, the workers “of the world” do not necessarily unite, as Marx and Engels would have them do, being divided by social conditions having nothing directly to do with labor such as race and sex. Neither homogenization nor impoverishment of the workers has occurred, nor have they universally flocked to socialist parties—themselves divided between social democrats and Leninists. “In our view, in order to advance in the determination of social antagonisms, it is necessary to analyze the plurality of diverse and frequently contradictory positions, and to discard the idea of a perfectly unified and homogeneous agent, such as the ‘working class’ of classical [Marxist] discourse.” 

    “Since Kautsky, Marxism knew that the socialist determination of the working class does not arise spontaneously but depends upon the political mediation of intellectuals.” And with Gramsci, “politics is finally conceived as articulation and through his concept of historical bloc and profound and radical complexity is introduced into the theorization of the social.” It remains to take the final theoretical step, to recognize that “the logic of hegemony,” which, as a political logic requires articulation (speech, especially definition) and contingency or choice, and behind choice, strategy, should result in what socialists now call ‘identity politics’—struggle over the definition of the many social groups itself, and over demands for ‘recognition’ or power broadly conceived not only as physical force but as ideology, ‘myth,’ ‘values.’ As a consequence, “unfixity has become the condition of every social identity,” since identities are self-defined and “relational,” fluid as they interact with other self-identifying groups. Identity politics is genuinely political in the authors’ sense of the word, inasmuch as it consists not of scientifically discernible laws, as if the course of events were like the course of a river, governed and also rationally governable by the laws of physics, but of free wills. Democracy or egalitarianism comes in because such a politics insists that all identities are equal; there are no more “privileged” subjects with superior access to historical laws, inasmuch as no such laws exist. “There are no privileged points for the unleashing of a socialist political practice; this hinges upon a ‘collective will’ that is laboriously constructed from a number of dissimilar points.” This practice cannot be defined at the outset but will rather become defined, and redefined, as the social-group wills whose interaction constitutes the collective will confront opposition forming and reforming political bonds with one another, and with newcomers. Indeed, “the very notion of ‘hegemony’ should be put into question, although the authors will come to affirm it in the ‘theoretical’ chapters that follow.

    In these opening chapters of Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, Laclau and Mouffe thus provide an instructive critical account of the “Crisis of Marxism” that began in the late nineteenth century but continues to this day. Their own theoretical justification for socialism occupies the book’s third chapter.

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    What Has Plato To Do With Modern Europe?

    August 10, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    Jan Patocka: Plato and Europe. Petr Lom translation. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002.

     

    A student of Husserl and a friend of Vaclav Havel, Jan Patocka became one of philosophy’s martyrs, dying of a heart attack in 1977 after a police interrogation. Czechoslovakia was ruled by the Communists in those days, and, as everywhere else, they had little patience with dissidents. His book consists of lectures delivered in friends’ homes; barred from teaching in Czech universities, he spoke as a citizen in good standing in what Havel famously called “the parallel polis.” Is a philosopher fully a citizen only in a parallel polis? 

    Patocka contends that “philosophical reflection…should somehow help us in the distress in which we are; precisely in the situation in which we are placed, philosophy is to be a matter of inner conduct.” Under the tyrannical Communist regime, it can hardly be a matter of outer conduct; for decades, Athenian democrats tolerated Socrates in the agora, but Czechoslovakia’s ‘totalitarians’ were hardly so patient. Patocka concurs with Aristotle’s judgment, that “our reality is always situational.” The simple act of reflecting upon our situation changes it, although one might then ask “whether by reflection reality is improved.” It is, at least, clarified. Any human situation begins with opinion; those who reflect upon it may be moved to a critique of it, in the hope of approaching the truth of the matter. How, then, shall we reflect? First, look at the situation—the “reality in which I am, in which others are, and in which things are.” “The most interesting and most characteristic thing about situations is precisely that we have not given them to ourselves, that we are placed into them and have to reconcile ourselves with them.” They may in part be humanly made, but not, at least initially, by us. These givens include material things, our mortality (“We are a ship that necessarily will be shipwrecked,” and the universe itself is entropic), consciousness, and the overall “human situation,” the situation not only of ourselves and of those we know but of our species. “To philosophize, I think, means to meditate within the entire situation and to be its reflection.” Contra Marxism, philosophy “is not established in the way that scientific truths and scientific systems are: philosophy is not established objectively.” This includes the social sciences. 

    This is because “the situation is not totally an objective reality.” It consists of our reflection upon it, as well as its reflection in us. It also comprehends not only the present but the non-present, namely, the future. “A situation is a situation precisely because it has not yet been decided.” True, to think is to objectify; “we do not have any other means, we cannot even think otherwise,” since we always think about something. But this is not yet knowledge. For example, in thinking about “the times” in which we live, one might consider the art of the time, “the sense of life” portrayed in, say, a novel by Milan Kundera or a speech by Eugene Ionescu. In so considering, we will need to attend “to what is new in contrast to what used to be, something that is not just repetitive, that expresses something that is its very own.” Ionescu “tried to put into words this entire spirit of the times,” arguing that helplessness and alienation characterize it most distinctively. He refers to lack of human control over human affairs, the sense that large forces carry us along and away, explained by “contradictory prophets” who by their contradictions give us no firm guidance. Impersonal and unstoppable, these forces resemble the “will to power,” but it is a ‘will’ without a subject. In this situation, art is no longer joyful, as it was for Mozart or for the builders of Chartres Cathedral. Such a situation, such a “spirit of the times,” invites philosophic reflection, as thinkers long for the clarification such reflection might bring. 

    “But the question is, when we go to the roots of our contemporary disequilibrium, whether we do not need to go to the very origins of Europe and through these beginnings to the very relation between mankind and its place in the world; or rather, whether the disequilibrium we are positing today is not something that concerns solely European man in a particular historical period, but rather regards man sui generis today in his relation with the planet.” Why the planet? Because not very long ago, “Europe was the master of the world,” bringing it to capitalism, “the network of world economy and markets,” controlling world politics thanks to its “scientific-technological” power, developed by its uniquely rationalistic or modern-scientific civilization. While Europe “wrecked itself” in the world wars, the rest of the war inherited its powers and “will never allow Europe to be what it once was.” Europe arrived at this condition because it combined such “enormous power” with political disunity, leading to wars among its sovereign states. “The internal logic of the European situation” played out in modern technology being deployed in massively destructive wars, wars made possible by political disunion. This Europe of sovereign states in turn arose from the ruins of the Roman empire, destroyed by the estrangement of the people from the Roman state—a point that neither Patocka’s friends in the “Underground University” nor his enemies outside of it would have failed to connect to the prospects of the then-regnant Soviet empire. Medieval Europe maintained a less worldly union, “the project of the kingdom of God,” which Patocka associates with Hellenistic Greece’s universalism; when that spiritual-civilizational source of union crumbled under the assault of modern philosophers and the statesmen they instructed, Europe was set both to conquer the world and to lose it. But it must nonetheless be said, Europe under its several iterations lasted a long time, and it survives, if in truncated form, today.

    Having identified the sources of Europe’s disequilibrium, Patocka asks two questions: How did the longstanding equilibrium arise, “keeping humanity at the same time in a state of spiritual elevation and in balance with the natural ecological situation on this planet”? And could a new equilibrium come about, “so that we could again find hope in a specific perspective, a specific future,” unlike that of Europe in the ongoing ‘Cold War’? 

    It is true that “in a certain sense,” the world is always in decline. Things come into being, then pass away. “But philosophy says: no, the world is not in decline, because the core of the world is being, and being has no beginning and will not perish, being can neither begin nor end—it is eternal.” From “the perspective of modern science,” this “discovery of eternity” is “incomprehensible,” inasmuch as modern science experiments, examines changing and indeed effects change as the means examining those things. But the metaphysics of the philosophers resists modern-scientific claims. In resisting the ‘inevitablism’ of modern science, its claim to discover natural-historical laws that are not only irresistible but all-encompassing (Marxian ‘dialectic’ being a specimen thereof), Greek philosophers exert human freedom. They did so by thinking about the human being, the being who thinks, insisting that, as philosophers, as lovers of wisdom, they must attend to “the care of the soul,” care of the thing that thinks, the distinctively human thing. 

    Why care for the soul? “Because man, or the human soul—that which knows about the whole of the world and of life, that which is able to present this whole before its eyes, that which lives from this position, that which knows about the whole and in that sense is wholly and in the whole within this explicit relation to something certainly immortal, that which is certainly eternal, that which does not pass away beyond which is nothing—in this itself has its own eternity.” Animals perceive parts of the whole, but not the whole, not Being. Philosophers justify care of the human soul as the way to fulfill the good of that distinct human nature, even as animals seek to fulfill the good of their own, quite unreflective, natures.

    Beyond the formidable powers of modern science, then, “Can the care of the soul, which is the fundamental heritage of Europe,” prior to modern-scientific Europe, “still speak to us today? That is, “speak to us who need to find something to lean on in this common argument about decline, in this weakness, in this consent to the fall?” Why is it necessary to care for the soul? What is its significance?

    He begins with a discussion of Husserl’s Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology. Husserl begins with a discussion of appearance. To appear, something must be ‘here’; and it must not only be present, but it must show itself to us. Appearance is preliminary to knowing. It is also preliminary to acting, and when we act, we want to know what is good and what is evil. Whatever a person “marks as good and evil has to show itself to him.” Since “good and evil are something that regards us, at the same time we show ourselves to ourselves.” If Satan says, “Evil, be thou my good,” he is showing himself to himself (and to others, if they hear him say that). “Phenomenon, then, in this sense means the showing of existence: things not only are but also they are manifest.” Notoriously, however, appearance is not necessarily reality. How are appearance and reality related to one another? “How are they distinguished and how to, do they overlap, how do they meet?”

    Evidently, if something manifests itself “it manifests, appears to someone.” Mind usually occupies itself “with something other than itself,” but is “also an existing thing,” a part of being. For ordinary purposes, we have a sense of knowing them so long as we perceive them with “something like clarity,” that is, without confusion. “We work with the concept of appearing; yet at the same time this concept itself is not clear to us.” In knowing a thing, in this modest way, we also sense that there are things that are not present, not manifest. “The nonpresent also shows itself here,” sending us from our immediate surroundings to more distant ones,” “further and further away,” finally “encompass[ing] everything there is.” To see a part is to acknowledge, implicitly, the whole. Any particular thing “is within the framework of this universal showing,” and every “individual thesis” or opinion “is a part of the universal thesis”—of my more or less certain opinion of the character of the whole. “All our life takes place within the very showing of things and in our orientation among them.”

    “We have two theses before us: on the one hand, in what manifests itself we always have, in some way, the whole, and manifesting itself equally constantly points to some kind of whole.” These two kinds of manifestations are given; we did not choose them. “The manifesting world in its whole has always already engaged us and has always already imposed its law upon us” “existence shows itself, something that is not our creation, a matter of our free will.” Because we have minds, themselves parts of the whole, we judge the things we perceive, telling ourselves “whether they are or are not, that they are probable or doubtful and so on,” and moreover “every judgment of this kind takes place within the framework of the general thesis, the thesis of the whole.” If, for example, the framework or thesis of the whole that orients you excludes the possibility of angels, if an angel appears before you, you will be inclined to judge it to be illusory. “All our cognitive activity takes place in systems of judgment and is thus the product of our conscious action, directed toward an end.” 

    Returning to manifestation at the simplest level, the situation in which “I have things at the tip of my fingers, here, in their sentient actuality,” it is the case that if I go away from those things, when I no longer see them, except in ‘my mind’s eye,’ I have no reason to suppose that they have changed. They are still what they were when I left them. They are the same, but in a different way. This means that manifestation itself, showing, is not “any of those things that show themselves.” Manifesting itself “forms a certain solid interconnected system,” unifying our experience of sense perception and memory of things perceived. This unity of experience is prior to experience; it structures experience. 

    In ordinary life, we don’t concern ourselves with this point. “We are interested in things after all. They interest us in what, which, and how they are.” To know in the sense of ‘science’ is to know the things. “Showing, phenomenon, that on the basis of which things are for us what they are, is itself constantly hidden from us.” Science tells us nothing about manifesting. Yet “nothing has been such a cause and axis of human questioning about the nature of things as manifesting.” How do we distinguish appearance from reality? Here is where ‘Europe’ comes in—specifically, ancient Greece, and even more specifically, Greek philosophy. “The conception of the soul in philosophy from its Greek origins consists in just what is capable of truth within man, and what, precisely because it is concerned about truth, poses the question: how, why does existence in its entirety, manifest itself, how why does it show itself?” Although philosophy originated in ancient Greece, it is neither a narrowly Greek or European, since “manifesting, light in the world,” is “something that distinguishes man from all else”: a tortoise does not think of the whole. This being so, this “human privilege” also “places duties before man,” endows him with responsibilities that go with his capacity to think of the whole. If the human soul is unique, distinctive, in this way, “care of the soul,” the human soul that so thinks, “follows from the proximity of man to manifesting, to the phenomenon as such, to the manifesting of the world in its whole, that occurs within man, with man.” 

    Husserl argues that this means that our thoughts are not merely instrumental, “ready-made tools to acquire more and more experiences.” We are interested in the things, in the experiences of them, but we are also interested in “determining how various manners of givenness are connected,” the “structure of the phenomenon as such.” If, for example, I think of the present, I see that “the present is possible only so long as there is also the past and the future,” things “present as not-present.” “In the presence of the past…the past is present like that which no longer can be present: and the future is present as such, like something which has not yet gotten to presence in the eminent sense of the word.” There is, then, “the world of existent things” but also “the world of phenomenal structures,” the “world that is” and “the world that shows itself.” Phenomenology “looks for the presuppositions of the structures of individual showing.” Science knows the human being “from the natural development of this physical universe.” Phenomenological philosophy investigates “something that is the proper concrete base of the physical universe.” It seeks to understand “the nature of the fact that things in their entirety manifest themselves to us, and what this means.” Contrary to Marxian historicism, “this is not a matter of some kind of immanent teleology or some kind of real factor that the phenomenon would realize with some kind of immanent purposiveness.” 

    The moral dimension of this human capacity to investigate, to care for this “phenomenological domain,” this “awareness of man as a creature of truth,” is presented in what Patocka calls myths. In “the biblical myth of the tree of knowledge,” man is damned by his attempt to seek knowledge of good and evil; so too in the Sumerian myth of Gilgamesh and Enkidu, in the Greek myths of Hercules and of Oedipus. “All these myths have the same meaning: man is at the same time a creature of truth and this truth is damnation for him” because “it shows his own precariousness, his place in the universe, which is overpowering in his regard.” But “the greatness” of Greek philosophy, what “made Greek philosophy what it is” and what “made it the foundation of all European life” is that it “developed a plan for life, one that stated” that knowledge “is not damnation, but human greatness.” Philosophers contend that the man who makes clarity, truth, “the law of his life, and with the help of this law in every domain in which man is involved,” can point the way to “make at least the human world a world of truth and justice.” Thus, the soul, the thing that “is capable of truth on the basis of a peculiar, untransferable, only-in-man-realized structure of the phenomenon as such,” deserves the utmost care. “Man can either capitulate and degenerate into mere existence,” or he can “realize himself as a being of truth, a being of phenomenon.” “The history of Europe is in large part, up until, let us say, the fifteenth century, the history of the attempt to realize the care of the soul.”

    Given his task of understanding the situation of Europe now, in the mid-1970s, Husserl concerns himself not “with the Platonic ascent from the cave,” which would entail a further investigation of manifestation, but “with that second Platonic act—the return back down to the cave.” We want to understand “our reality.” That reality has been “deeply determined by philosophy.” We are philosophizing within the cave, and the modern cave has philosophic markings engraved on its walls. 

    This means that Europe as it now exists partakes of the philosophic ascent from the cave, its departure from a pre-existing “mythical framework.” Myth is manifestation that has yet to be reflected upon. It is therefore truthful, in a sense. The truth of myth is the fact that human beings live in a world that both accepts us and “crushes and constantly threatens us.” This latter, “horrible” reality is not only outside us but “within all of us.” Madness “can break through in life everywhere. Like Oedipus, “we are left to blind wandering.” Like Adam and Eve, we are punished in our quest for knowledge. Like Gilgamesh, we would build a city in the face of “everything instinctive and elementary,” which must be “broken and tamed” if the city is to be built and sustained. “This duality is at home in all myths,” this “polarity of that other, the strange, belonging to the night,” in contrast to “the domestic, held fast, the daily.” The myths register “the natural world as the world of good and evil.” They make us aware of both good and evil. Myth does not console, it does not support; it is the “harsh revealing of our revealedness/nakedness.” 

    Oedipus, “this two-sided creature, of dual-meaning, a creature who is both damned and sacred,” is truly human, a human presented mythically, poetically. “The uncovering of the whole world by Greek philosophy is the continuation of this myth,” at attempt to “penetrate behind the ordinary blind wandering, or behind the ordinary unclarity and unawareness in which we move.” The execution of Socrates by the Athenians is itself a sort of sacrifice of the one who, like Oedipus, looked in, sought and found truth. At the same time, Socrates is also the philosopher of The Republic, the philosopher of ‘The Regime,’ the just regime, the one in which “those like Socrates can live and do not need only to die.” Europe “grew out of this” quest for a just regime.

    The mythical framework in which Plato and his Socrates philosophize “both helps and hinders [philosophy’s] origin and development.” But “it hinders before it helps.” This is because to question, as philosophers do, “means precisely to find an explicitly empty space, to find something that in a certain sense is not there.” Myth gets in the way of that because it is already there. It presents itself as “something like a picture of the world in its entirety,” “occup[ying] in some manner the whole world.” Those who accept the myth do not see the need for, do not like the practice of, questioning. They already have the answer. At the same time, “philosophy does not begin ex abrupto.” It needs something to question, and myth is that something. Philosophers need myth, opinion, to get started in their philosophizing, even as myth or prevailing opinion restrains them, threatens them with punishment if they look at it with a questioning eye. In myth, “man is the being that dares to penetrate into the domain that is not his, it breaks into somewhere, where from its origins it was not really at home.” The philosopher dares to compare one myth to another, seeking the meaning beneath the meaning each myth imposes. Myths are enunciated by prophets. A prophecy gives a people “clarity about what is,” representing “that which reality is,” revealing what “is not the domain of man but rather of the gods.” Unlike man, the gods know everything. They know what blindly wandering man knows not. Myth or the revelation of the gods is a kind of founding, drawing out a system of morals from nature, morals that are a part of that reality but need accentuation, emphasis, in order to serve as guides to blindly wandering man. Myth founds “a certain custom, a way of life,” a pattern by which it tells us to live—a regime, as the political philosopher, Socrates, would say. The myth “determines the meaning and the path of this wandering in a way that is for us at first unfathomable.” Philosophy attempts to fathom it.

    In doing that, philosophy brings “an entirely new possibility of the human spirit” to light, “a possibility that also did not have to be realized and in fact the majority of peoples, even the highly cultured, do not know it at all.” Myth takes “the manifest” as “the sphere of the gods,” related to human beings in the past by their prophets, and makes it present but only in imagination, “a deficient form” of presence. Philosophy wonders; it “asks its question face to face with the amazing primeval fact of the manifestation of the world.” It looks not to manifestation as image but to the archē, the principle of things. There is no wonder or amazement in myth, which provides answers ‘not to be questioned.’ Philosophy begins with “amazement” “not about particular real things, but rather about this primeval reality,” seeking clarity “about the fact that things are,” seeking their existence and structure. “Myth does not even dream that it would be possible to justify something, explain it, answer the question ‘why’ in any other than through some kinds of stories.” Fundamental to philosophy is that it sees two things: “something shows itself” and “this showing itself.” “Philosophy can begin to look for the structure of things only as long as the question of the structure of discovering has already first emerged.” The structure of discovery exists within the soul, which must be cared for, for that reason.

    Patocka notices this care in the thought of the earliest philosophers, the ‘pre-Socratics.’ Aphoristic Heraclitus, he of the ‘dark’ or hard-to-understand sayings, imitates the Delphic oracle, “tak[ing] on the function the god had” at Delphi: “he is the one to whom belongs the function of manifestation in its entirety,” dividing each thing “according to [its] nature.” His “lightning” or “fire” means “the flash, manifestness.” Once thig have been divided, logos or reason collects them, putting them together in order to see them as parts of a whole. ‘Everything moves,” he famously says; motion is the passage of objects through spatial and temporal phases; at the same time, “motion is also manifesting,” of “approaching and receding, coming into presence and leaving from presence.” Philosophy “from this primeval beginning” bears “a dual movement of thought,” as seen in two philosophers, the ‘nature-philosopher,’ Democritus, and the political philosopher, Plato. 

    Democritus “set out on a quest for the whole, that means after what is eternal,” by means of mathematics and especially geometry. In so doing, “Democritus erected the concept of philosophy as science,” as a set of “scientific explanations.” He discovers two principles; “the unlimited”—empty, homogeneous geometric space—and “the indivisibles”—the atoms, which move within that space but “in themselves are completely unchangeable, eternal, and for this reason form the foundations for possible constructions.” In so doing, he “penetrate[s] beyond the region of what is visible in the ordinary sense of the world,” thanks to one form of reasoning, geometry, which shows us the characteristics of the space in which the atoms move, and another form of reasoning, which shows us that the infinitude suggested by geometry cannot be the whole of reality because geometry would take the matter that is manifestly present in the world and keep on dividing it forever. Hence the need for atoms, which cannot be divided. 

    None of this seems to leave any place for care of the soul. If the soul is an unusually refined structure of atoms in space, why care for it? Democritus begins by noticing that “the human spirit thirsts after explanation,” an explanation of the divine, the eternal, begging the question, “Where does this thirst originate?” It originates in the soul, and in his soul more than in most. The soul “wants to see the truth,” wants to see “the unconcealment of things.” It can only succeed if it “maintain[s] absolute purity of sight and purity of its internal substance. This “impulse to the eternal leads in Democritus to the discover of one’s soul, to the care of one’s soul.” Such purity, he contends, requires shedding the bonds of family and polis, turning away from the passions that lead the soul to becoming preoccupied with ‘one’s own.’ In the tradition, in myth, the soul appears as a form—as seen, for example, in Egyptian tomb paintings. That is, it is seen from the outside, “from the other’s point of view.” “Form is something I see, it is the soul for the other, not the soul that I am.” Democritus understands his soul from within, as that which “lives in contact with the eternal.” True, it lives briefly, it is not an immortal soul, “but this does not matter, because this contact with the eternal is the same in man and in god”; “that is why the soul is in its own way eternal, even if dissolves into atoms” in death. 

    “For this peculiarity, there is created something in European life that has never been created anywhere else in the world,” a new “human possibility” that “steps into the radius of all other human possibilities.” “Europe as Europe arose from this motif, from the care of the soul.” “It became extinct” when “it forgot about it.” Its decline into dogmatism—so evident in the fascism of Patocka’s youth and the communism which prevailed in his country after the Nazis were expelled—also betokened the extinction of the philosophic quest for the concealed “something upon which stands” the unconcealed. The soul must remain awake; to remain awake, it must be cared for; if not cared for, it is no longer fully human, it no longer undertakes the philosophic quest; and Europe is no longer Europe. 

    To recover the practice of caring for the soul, Patocka explains “the method of care.” The soul is not a thing to be cultivated in the way one cultivates a garden. It discovers itself only in seeking the truth about what it does not know and being truthful, whether or not truthfulness happens to be to the advantage of the person whose soul it is. “In Democritus, to care for the soul means to care for it so that it might be able to live near what is eternal, so that it might be capable of a life in that grand presence”—that “will naturally be a life of thought.” Knowledge is “the presence of what is,” as distinguished from what he calls “bastard knowledge,” which is obscure and unclear—hence its ‘illegitimacy’ or ‘bastardy.’ 

    Plato, too, cares for the soul, but he reverses Democritus’ intention. Plato commends care for the soul “not so that the soul might journey through the universe just as what is eternal,” but “so it will be what it is supposed to be.” The quest for understanding, rightly undertaken, improves the soul, makes it “what it can be.” Plato is a political philosopher, not a natural philosopher. He considers, first and foremost, not the cosmos but his fellow Athenians, “invit[ing] people to think.” In so doing, he reveals their ignorance; in revealing their ignorance, he reveals “their secret dispositions for tyranny,” despite their purportedly freedom-loving affection for the regime of democracy. The soul achieves its best condition, its right order, not in contemplating the heavens but in dialoguing with fellow citizens. “The soul that really cares for itself takes on a solid force, just as every though worthy of the name is a defined thought, specifying ideas, having a specific thesis about those ideas.” This is no “pallid intellectualism” but an “attempt to embody what is eternal within time, and within one’s own being, and at the same time, an effort to stand firm in the storm of time, stand firm in all dangers carried with it, to stand firm when the care of the soul becomes dangerous for a human being”—not only in ancient Athens but in modern Prague. “The care of the soul in a lawless city endangers a human being,” the “kind of human being that stands for the care of the soul, just as that being endangers the city,” which is built on ignoble lies, not truth. The “whole existence” of Socrates “is a provocation to the city,” as he “is the first who, face to face with =secret tyranny and the hypocritical remains of old morality, poses the thought that the human being focused on truth in the full sense of the word, examining what is the good, not knowing himself what is the positive good, and only refuting false opinion, has to appear as the worst of all, the most irritating.” Philosophy begins in wonder, but there can be very little wonder at the effect Patocka’s talks must have had among his listeners, gathered in someone’s apartment, in a city under the rule of a Communist oligarchy which based its claim to rule on having ‘all the answers.’

    The regime of Plato’s Republic is the regime “where Socrates and those like him will not need to die.” “This is that singular thing about Europe”: “only in Europe was philosophy born in this way, in the awakening of man out of tradition into the presence of the universe.” From Greece to Rome, where “the Stoics really did educate mankind about the universal human tasks of a universal empire,” philosophy took its way. Rome fell, like the Greek polis, because it could not “convince its public that it was a state of justice.” Europeans regrouped and continued their quest, attempting “to bring the city of justice into reality, a city to be founded not on the changeability of human things as Rome was, but rather on absolute truth, so that it would be the kingdom of God upon earth.” The Roman Catholic Church “would not even be possible” without the Platonic thought. Nietzsche was right to say that Christianity is Platonism for the people, but right in the wrong way. He said it with a sneer because he “overlooks what is most fundamental about the phenomena of Socrates and Plato, that is, the care of the soul.” Christendom fell, not because it was too weak and unworldly but because the care of the soul “became pretty much unrecognizable under the weight of something, something that might be deemed a concern, or care about dominating the world.” That is, in turning from Plato and Christianity to Machiavelli, Europe stopped caring for the soul. And “is not Nietzsche’s search for eternity, his attempt to leap from history into what is beyond time proof that it is absolutely necessary to reiterate care for the soul even under new circumstances?”

    “Philosophy is the care of the soul in its own essence and its own element.” Political philosophy undertakes this care in dialogue among citizens. Patocka understands the philosophic stance as zetetic—not “the suspension of all judgment,” much less an endorsement of the dogma of moral relativism, but as the quest for truth with the knowledge that one knows one doesn’t know. So understood, philosophy proceeds from one way station of “provisional hypothetically fixed opinion” to another, more coherent way station. “In the end we want only what we can answer for in this manner, what we either see with such clarity that it withstands every kind of imaginable inquiry.” This implies that philosophy never rests in one soul only, or in “some kind of system” (Hegelianism, Marxism, utilitarianism, pragmatism) but continues on, among many thinkers, dialoguing with one another, over space and time. The philosophic quest requires more than intelligence; it requires courage, moderation, justice, and wisdom. Courage, because the philosopher puts himself at risk in the city; moderation, because the passions interfere with clear thinking; justice, because it remains true to itself, rejecting sophistry, especially self-sophistry; wisdom, “in knowing not knowing in the form of temperate and disciplined investigation, because it submits all other human affairs to this thinking struggle.” Philosophy gives itself “a certain standard for its own being,” one that is “unified, constant, and exact,” and therefore almost surely to be at odds with the standards of the city, which are seldom well-reasoned and may well resist the provisional character of philosophic opinion, being based on law, which accepts provisionality at its own risk. The city knows a rival regime when it sees one.

    If philosophy is “living in the truth,” how much truth can a city, a political community, withstand? After all, the city’s population consists mostly of non-philosophers. They can surely see through the blatant lies of, say, their communist rulers, but to what extent can they live in the truth? Christianity teaches that they can, but only with God’s grace to guide them. Can modern Europe, post-Christian Europeans, do any such thing?

    If they were to attempt this, Europeans would have human nature on their side. Man is “by nature a being to whom the world shows itself” and in attending to the world we “form ourselves in some kind of way.” Patocka identifies “three currents of care of the soul.” He calls the first current “ontocosmological,” that is, ontological and cosmological. He is thinking of Plato’s theory of the ideas. The philosopher looks at the many opinions in light of the principle of non-contradiction, the principle of logos or reason, seeking the “unity” behind those opinions. An idea is free of contradiction; ideas “serve to give us clarity about things,” show us the shape of things, enable us to think of nouns. Tom, Dick, and Harry are seen to be men, and therefore a certain kind of human being. “Things cannot manifest themselves to us other than on the basis and through the mediation of the ideas,” and “that manifesting is something other than what manifests itself,” an “entirely different kind of structure.” “Men” and “human” are other than Tom, Dick, and Harry, yet they group those guys into discernible categories, clarifying our thought about them, showing them to be of a different nature than, say, Fido, Rex, and Spot, a trio of dogs. The word ‘trio’ suggests number, but the ideas are “the most fundamental, most elemental numbers,” as they do not ‘add up’: indivisible (and more so than atoms, which turned out to be quite divisible, and with interesting consequences), “they are accessible only to our logos.” ‘Ontocosmologically,’ being has limits, seen in the ideas. Logos, which perceives the ideas, is the core of the human soul. To live in terms of logos is to be most distinctively human, to be caring for the soul in the right way.

    To live in those terms “poses the question of the lawful arrangement of life in the community from the point of view of the thought of the just life,” since human beings live in political communities. Each polis has a set of beliefs held in common by those who live within it, part of its regime. “The common way of seeing and the way of seeing of the philosopher are inevitably in conflict.” This is the second “current” of care for the soul, “the care of the soul in the community as the conflict of two ways of life.” To say that the care of the soul forms “the essential heritage of Europe,” what “in a certain sense made European history what it is,” does “not mean that these thoughts were realized here,” but only “that they were a certain ferment, without which we cannot conceive of European reality.” Hence the other sense of ‘political philosophy,’ namely, the need for a ‘politic’ or prudent philosophy. 

    “The community itself does not see that the philosopher, who is the thorn in its side, is in reality—mythically spoken—the envoy of the gods.” (Ironically enough, Socrates’ accusers call him an atheist, but not so ironically inasmuch as they mean the gods citizens worship.) To kill the envoy of the gods is “the peak of injustice” which “at the same time…always seem[s] just.” Socrates “performs the constant task of unselfish caring for the community, in the sense that he is constantly thinking only about its good,” and takes the hemlock as his reward, while a perfectly unjust man, one who conceals the tyrannical longings of his soul throughout his life, “will succeed in life.” From appearance, then, the unjust man is better. This brings Socrates to induce his dialogic partners to construct a ‘city in speech’ that accords with reasoned speech, with logos, as an illustrative parallel of the soul, which is much harder to see than a city, even one made only of words. Socrates takes Adeimantus and Glaucon up a rational ladder, from the subhuman ‘city of pigs,’ which aims at satisfying the needs and desires of the body, to the courageous city of the guardians, their spiritedness moderated by careful education so that they guard, rather than attack, their fellow citizens. The educators of the guardians are the philosophers, citizens of “the sharpest insight,” the ones “who decide what the community will do.” Reason ruling, spiritedness guarding, the appetites obeying: “Here we have a picture of what each of us individually is within himself”—what each of us is ‘in idea,’ insofar as we conform ourselves to the idea of ‘human.’ Reason discovers the ideas, which are defined, limited, and therefore limiting if heeded by the spiritedness that has the capacity to overcome the appetites. Without the rule of reason, spiritedness and appetites have no limits, incline to swell “into infinity.” “Care of the soul is that which Socrates does, constantly examining our opinions about what is good,” keeping them within the limits of the ideas. 

    This leads back to the third “current” of care of the soul, which flows in the individual. Why would an individual care for his soul? In other words, why philosophize? Because “the soul that is cared for is more, it has a higher, elevated being.” It is more—what? More what it should be, more what its nature is, more fully satisfied in its own being. This is why Socrates says that a philosopher must be compelled to return to the ‘cave,’ the polis, the community ruled by unexamined opinion. In so returning, he will not want to rule, as philosophers do in the city in speech, but he may want to find a way to reform the city in some modest but crucially important way, making it a place both safe for philosophers and from philosophers. (Philosophers, too, need to reform themselves, as a part of their ongoing soul-discovery and concomitant soul-reform, their philosophizing.) If no one in the city does this, they city declines, and “we”—we Europeans, we humans—are “responsible for our decline.” Decline usually wins because the “general tendencies of our mind and all our instinctive equipment” incline toward materialism, toward caring for our bodies instead of our souls. To fortify the reasoning part of the soul against its powerful appetites, and especially to tame the spirited part of the soul, to make it into reason’s guardian, not its enemy, Plato’s Socrates proposes a religion, but a new kind of religion, the world’s first “purely moral religion.”

    What is a moral religion? Judaism has moral elements; the Decalogue contains “moral precepts.” “But the Jewish God is the wrathful god who punishes in a manner beyond all human measure.” His thoughts are not your thoughts, He tells His prophet. Unlike the ideas, he partakes of infinitude, spiritedness without limit, or at least without humanly measurable, humanly understandable, limit. To reach Christianity, Judaism “passed through Greek reflection,” thereby becoming “the ferment of the new European world.” “In Christianity, the moment of insight occurs in that Christian dogmas are not considered as something to be accepted blindly.” [1] In rejecting Christianity, modern Europeans turned toward materialism, toward a science animated by “quantitative progress,” toward a ‘mass’ society in that sense, and in the sense of ‘mass’ or majority rule, democracy without rational limits—the sort that worried Tocqueville, thrilled Stephen Douglas, repelled Abraham Lincoln. Morality implies freedom. “We are free because we always stand between…two alternatives, in the question of good-evil, truth-untruth.” Hence Lincoln’s argument, that Douglas, in saying he ‘didn’t care’ whether slavery was voted up or down in the territories, was “blowing out the moral lights around us”—first and foremost the unalienable rights of liberty and equality.

    “Philosophy today, in today’s world, is nothing” because “the world is still obsessed by the thought of seizing reality, as far a possible, the most intensive, and as far as possible greatest extent, and to draw from it as much and as quickly as possible.” We do not adequately care for our souls, concentrating our minds instead on our machines. Science, technology, “and this whole modern, emancipated an enlightened world” has “an enormous significance and its own justification,” but “who is going to reflect upon this justification and its limits?” Thomas Masaryk called this condition “discouragement in the field of philosophy,” the confinement of academic philosophy to modern positivism and linguistic inquiry, “where the task of philosophy consists in showing the impossibility of traditional philosophical questions and answers.” The merit of Heidegger is that he at least concerns himself with the “ancient thinkers like Aristotle,” again, philosophers who thought about nature, “the foundation of existence, what makes existence existence.” The “guiding theme” in Heidegger’s philosophy is manifestation, of Being “showing itself,” of things “dis-covering themselves.” Also like the ancients, he looks inward, considers how it is that the soul cognizes, “why interpretation is interpretation in the light of being,” how we attempt to discover the “internally meaningful structure” of things and of Being. “I can only get to the problem of being through the problem of showing,” “put[ting] together what belongs together in the thing and separat[ing] what does not belong together.” Heidegger differs from Plato, Patocka sees, in his historicism: “In Plato being is the great whole,” which “unfolds in a kind of grand topography,” whereas “in Heidegger it is such that being in its own essence is the surfacing of something hidden and coming into manifesting into the manifest” in an unending dynamic. Nonetheless, they share one important thing: both philosophers want “to live in truth.” 

    As indicated, Plato develops the principle of the care of the soul in three directions: a “systematic ontology,” which “brings the soul into connection with the structure of being”; a “teaching about the state,” whereby “the care of the soul is both possible and is the center of all state life and also the axis of historical occurrence”; and “the individual fate of the soul,” the soul’s confrontation with death and the question of the meaning of “individual human existence.” Without Platonic philosophy, including Platonic political philosophy, “Europe would have an entirely different form” than it has. Platonic philosophy isn’t only logic, dialectical thought; he also maintains that “philosophy begins where something begins to be seen, where meaningful speech leads us to the thing itself,” an intellectual eros for understanding what is, seen in the ideas, “the measure of what is.” Plato is “the philosopher of radical clarity,” even as he knows that “the cave does not cease to exist,” that no comprehensive ‘enlightenment’ is possible for human beings. The soul “stands at the boundary of the visible and the invisible.” It thinks; it judges. “Judgment means to say something else about something,” to ascend from the cave of opinion, the visible, into the realm of the ideas, invisible in the cave, to discover “the internally meaningful structure” of nature. The philosopher cares for the soul because the soul, “that which moves by itself,” which “constantly lives the [erotic] impulse to get to existence either through thinking, to unity with it itself, or through irrationality to fall into not-existence.” In thinking, in the life of thinking, the soul seeks “to be in unity with one’s own self”—the “work of a whole life.”

    Aristotle retains a suggestion of the Platonic ideas in his ‘formal’ causes. Human life, including philosophy, moves not so much ‘up’ from the cave of political life and its conventional opinions as ‘horizontally’ toward the human ‘end’ or telos. That is, man remains a political animal, at home in the cave; the political philosopher finds a place in the polis. “The movement of the human being—qua human—lies in the human capability to comprehend the movement of all other beings, that he can take them into himself and give them, in his own mind, in his own proper existence, a certain place.” Properly placed within the polis, the human soul is the place in which “things show themselves to be that which they are.” This, too, requires care of the soul. In this, despite his disagreements with Plato, he is also “the continuator of the path of philosophical movement.” At the same time, he puts more emphasis on human action, which “is also comprehension of its own kind,” a prudential understanding which is not clarified by the Platonic ideas. “For the Platonic idea regards what is always, what already is, but we need principles for the realization of something that is not yet, that does not exist.” Human beings aim at happiness, which is not bliss (“this is utterly false”) but “doing well.” Doing well consists not of experiencing pleasure (animals do that) nor even of honor (which depends upon others’ opinions, which may be mistaken). In practice, happiness or doing well, fulfilling the distinctively human nature, inheres in political life, in ruling and being ruled by deliberation, whereby persons decide “what people in the whole, everyone together, is permitted and is not permitted, how their life goals are to be harmonized.” This is not the highest human life—the philosophic life is even more self-sufficient, closer to the divine, the permanent, the finest harmony. “It is the life of constant spiritual discernment.” 

    “Aristotle’s thinking is that against which the European tradition leaned and from which it nourished itself for one thousand years.” Marx dismisses all that as “ideologists’ illusions.” Within the Marxist cave, in the apartments where his Underground University met, Patocka dissented. “What is at stake and what was at stake for philosophers from the very beginning—and this we are trying to comprehend—is to analyze the very ground upon which human acting unfolds as the acting of a being that understands itself—even in deficient modes.” Contra Marx, “Aristotle sees that human action is not blind causality.” In moral insight—insight attained in the course of exercising human freedom—what is “uncovered” is “that which I am.” 

    Just as this core of European civilization differs from Marxist (and other forms of) determinism, it also differs from the character of other civilizations. Paraphrasing Husserl, Patocka remarks that all other civilizations uphold myths, traditions “with which a human being has to identify with his life, essence, [and] custom; that they have this peculiar stamp that you must immerse yourself in them, step into the continuity of their tradition.” Europe differs from this because “everyone understands European civilization”; “the principle of European civilization is—roughly spoken—two times two is four.” That is, European civilization is general in its particularity, capable of becoming universal, “while those others, should they be generalized, would signify the swallowing up of all others by a particular tradition, but not by the principle of insight into the nature of things.” In Europe, “all human problems are defined from the perspective of insight.” European civilization “cannot be understood except from this point of reference that we call the care of the soul,” cannot be understood without ‘Plato,’ without the philosophic quest and especially the thoughtful care which makes that quest possible and inheres in that quest. “I maintain that history in this understanding—not history as the substantial history of man in every civilization and every tradition formed by peoples somewhere—is the history of Europe.” The tension between “the tradition of insight” and European traditions that are conventional gives rise “to the sentiment that something is not quite right” with Europe, a sentiment Romanticism, among other movements, has registered. “This problem is not any less urgent than it has always been, indeed, it is more urgent now.”

     

    Note

    1. It is true that Christianity includes provision of eternal, infinite, punishment, a point Patocka overlooks.

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    How Communists Conducted Regime Change in Hungary

    August 2, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    Jósef Mindszenty: Memoirs. Anonymous translation. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2023. Introduction by Daniel J. Mahoney.

     

    Defamed in life by Communists throughout the world and their dupes, Cardinal Jósef Mindszenty stands as witness to the character of the Communist regime in Hungary and such regimes elsewhere, inasmuch as the Party employed essentially the same strategies and tactics, worldwide. Communists used both national institutions and religious organizations whenever they could, preparatory to ruining and replacing them with their own ‘operatives,’ corrupting, torturing, and killing as they proceeded. Given the grim “destinies of my country and its Church,” Mindszenty “will not be able to speak merely of edifying and joyful things. I must tell about life as it is, filled with suffering and grace. In short, I must speak of reality.” He had witnessed more than a regime change.

    Born in 1892, Mindszenty was ordained as a priest in the Roman Catholic Church in 1915, as the Austro-Hungarian Empire fought alongside Germany and the Ottoman Empire in the Great War. His mentor in the priesthood, Father Béla Geiszlinger, led him to work to understand the lives of all classes of people in the parish and to consider both the spiritual and the material needs of each person he met. “I owe a great deal to this remarkable man.” “I was especially happy when—even in cases of those who seemed to have hopelessly fallen out with God, the Church, and themselves—I was able to revive faith by persuasion and guidance.” 

    The war only began the sufferings of Hungarian Christians, the Church in Hungary, and Hungary itself. Hungary’s founder, King Stephen, an aristocrat and Christian convert from the local paganism, began his reign in 1001, defeating pagan chieftains to gain and to keep the throne. His legitimacy recognized by Pope Sylvester II, Stephen faithfully, and forcefully, brought Christianity to his compatriots in the next four decades. He also fought to maintain Hungary’s independence from the Holy Roman Empire. On his deathbed, Mindszenty writes, he “dedicated the land of Hungary to the mother of Our Lord,” giving the Hungarian Catholic Church its Maronite inflection. After his death, the country fell into disunity once again, but he remained a symbol of Roman Catholic Christianity and the Hungarian nation throughout the subsequent centuries, canonized by the Church in 1083.

    At the end of the Great War, Mindszenty writes, “the disintegration of St. Stephen’s country seemed to be proceeding inexorably, as the reigning king, Charles IV, “withdrew” and a republican government under Michael Károlyi took over. Károlyi proved a foolish and weak statesman. A wealthy aristocrat, he detested the Hapsburg Monarchy and admired the revolutionaries of 1848. Nor did he much esteem the Church, esteeming the Enlightenment and looking to technology, not God, for the salvation of mankind. His pacifist sentiments proved beneficial at war’s end, as he had opposed the now-loathed war itself and the Empire’s alliance with Germany. Once his republican regime was in power, however, he refused to defend the country against rival states, losing seventy-five percent of pre-war Hungarian territory. 

    Mindszenty opposed “the new regime” in his sermons, writing in a newspaper he helped to edit, and as the local leader of the Christian Party, which stood for election in municipal and regional offices. He was arrested in February 1919, and a month later Károlyi, who by then shared power with the Marxist Social Democratic Party, “let the Communists seize power from him and proclaim the dictatorship of the proletariat.” In his usual incompetence, Károlyi had not known that the Social Democrats had allied themselves with the Communist Party. The Communist, Béla Kun, took over and launched a terror campaign against his many enemies. Quite rightly deemed “incorrigible,” Mindszenty was expelled from Zala County, in which he had served as an assistant parish priest and returned to his home county (both located on the eastern border of the country), only to return when the Communist regime in turn collapsed in August 1919. He replaced the now-retired priest. 

    Wondering why Zala County, unlike his native, neighboring Vas County, had such a high rate of illiteracy and poor Church education, he began to study its history. He learned that it “was still suffering from a heritage of the period of Turkish rule,” which dated from the sixteenth century conquests. Many Hungarians had fled the area, fearing enslavement and death, and the Catholic churches and rectories had been burned. Although the Turks were pushed out a century later, the depopulated and desperately poor county had no funds to rebuild. Little had changed in the 150 years that followed. “My aim was to create a contemporary parish life.” 

    Mindszenty proved a capable organizer. The parish was large; Catholics had difficulty traveling to attend religious services and schools. He increased the number of Sunday Masses in the existing churches and chapels, built a new monastic church in one of the working-class districts, and instituted “an energetic program of visiting people in their homes,” whereby “we created closer relations between the clergy and the flock.” He eventually established twelve new parochial schools. He took a seat on both the county council and the municipal council of Zalaegerszeg, the county seat; this was a common practice in Europe at the time, when priests often sat in national parliaments. Mindszenty stayed on the local level of government, however, having “never thought very highly of the role of priest-politician.” “I was all the more determined to fight the enemies of my country and Church with the written and spoken word and to support all Christian politicians by giving clear and decisive directives to the faithful. But I myself wanted simply to remain a pastor. I regarded politics as a necessary evil in the life of a priest. Because politics can overturn the altar and imperil immortal souls, however, I have always felt it necessary for a minister to keep himself well informed about the realm of party politics…. It would certainly be a sign of great weakness if a priest were to leave vital political and moral decisions solely to the often-misled consciences of the laity.” 

    Interwar Hungary afforded many instances of such misled consciences, as the decade of the 1920s saw violent civil strife between the Hungarian Right and the Left. The Hapsburgs failed to regain power and no new royal dynasty was established, so the parliament designated Admiral Miklós Horthy as regent of the “Kingdom of Hungary.” Horthy ruled as a quasi-constitutional strongman for more than two decades, attempting to steer a relatively moderate course domestically by banning both the Communist Party and the fascist Arrow Cross Party. In foreign policy, however, he steered into ever-closer ties with the Axis Powers in the 1930s. In 1940, Hungary entered into formal alliance with them and joined their invasions of Yugoslavia and the Soviet Union in 1941. Within Hungary itself, Horthy collaborated in the policy of genocide against European Jews, quite possibly not so much out of racialist anti-Semitism as out of his conviction that Hungarian Jews had aligned with the Left throughout his lifetime. He was nonetheless an unenthusiastic ally of the Axis, directing his prime minister to enter into peace negotiations with the United States and Great Britain in autumn 1943. Hitler’s informants were vigilant, however, and German forces rolled in by the next spring. arresting Horthy and installing their own puppet, a member of the Arrow Cross. “The hour of darkness was descending upon Hungary. From the West the brown peril threatened us; and from the East, the red.”

    Mindszenty says almost nothing of the politics of Hungary during the interwar years. It is likely that the regime left him to his clerical duties, unmolested. In March of 1944, at the age of 52, he was appointed Bishop of Veszprém, a city-county located immediately to the west of Zala and Vas. The area had been occupied by the Nazis, but by then Mindszenty was free to undertake the traditional bishops’ confirmation tour. “Already well aware that the war would end badly for Hungary and that breakup of the large landed estates would follow hard upon the defeat,” he hoped to sell ten thousand of the twenty-four thousand diocesan lands and to distribute among the peasants, “with the idea of improving societal conditions among a sizable portion of the population.” This also would have tightened the bonds between the peasantry and the Church; needless to say, the Communists had other plans, and his plan was never realized. Unlike the doomed Rightist regime, Hungary’s Catholic bishops protested the confinement of Hungarian Jews. In a strongly worded pastoral letter, they reaffirmed that all human beings enjoy “innate rights,” including the rights to life, personal freedom, and “the free exercise of religion,” rights endowed “not by individuals, not by associations, not even by representatives of the government, but by God Himself.” This protest saved some lives, spurring Christians to protect Jews—as best they could. [1]

    By Christmastime, Mindszenty found himself arrested by the Arrow Cross government, having had the temerity to write them a letter, signed by other bishops, begging it to try to prevent a Nazi-Soviet battle in the heartland of the country. He held Christmas Mass in the prison chapel, attended not only by Catholics but men of the Left—even “atheists whose praying and singing deeply moved me. The peril of death had brought them close to God.” “Never again, and nowhere else, has a Christmas Mass moved me as did this one.”

    A few months later, retired Bishop János Mikes visited him in his cell, offering to help him to escape to the Soviet-held territories. Bishop Mikes naively imagined that the Soviets “had changed and no longer threatened the people of the Church”—as did many Hungarian politicians, who “did not know how to judge Soviet intentions correctly.” Mindszenty knew better, having seen the double-dealing of the Communists after the First World War. Hungarian politicians hadn’t studied the writings of Lenin and Stalin, nor had they attended to “the practices of Bolshevism.” “I had always noted the lack of public education on this score—even under the Horthy regime.” Mindszenty, however, “had “early realized what kind of enemy the Church was confronting, what sort of terrorism awaited us.” Not merely atheistic but contemptuous of Christian humility, intent on combatting individuality and private property and on “reshap[ing] the family and marriage in their own terms,” ready to liquidate their enemies, the Communists were worse than Neronian. “Historical studies had taught me that compromise with this enemy will almost always play into his hands.” As for Bishop Mikes, he died of a gunshot wound inflicted by Soviet troops, when he tried to prevent rapes in his village. In addition to rapes and murders, Soviet plundering showed that “the passion for private property shattered Communist collectivism.” When asked by a couple of priests to write a letter thanking the Red Army and its leaders “for our liberation,” Mindszenty declined. 

    The Soviets brought with them a set of exiled Hungarian Communists whom they installed as the proximate rulers of the country. The Communists did not abolish the Church; they undertook to hollow it out, gouge by gouge, suppressing the substance of its teachings while leaving the forms of worship intact. Proclaiming “religious freedom,” they meant only the Church services; Catholic education, Catholic associations, and Catholic charities were strictly curtailed. “They also declared that in all disputed questions between Church and state, a solution would be sought in the spirit of true democracy,” “true democracy” meaning the rule of the Communist Party. [2] This rule began mildly, following the Leninist recommendation that “the battle against religion must in certain cases be so waged that religious groups do not take alarm.” Hungary was such a case, as so many Hungarians adhered to Catholic or Protestant Christianity. “If possible,” clerics “were to be enlisted in the service of Communist goals” and Communist agents attempted to infiltrate religious congregations. Soon, “the Communists inflicted three severe blows on the Church”: agrarian reforms transferring farmlands which supported many Church institutions to collectives controlled by the Party; harassment of the Catholic press, aimed at “driv[ing] the Church out of public life, to diminish her influence as a source of information, and to paralyze her activities”; and regulation governing the formation of political parties, including Church-affiliated parties. On the educational front, August 1945 saw the beginning of a campaign to re-write national history, “reevaluated from the Communist standpoint.” “Teachers were required to make Marxism the basis for their educational work instead of ‘the outmoded Christian ideology.'” St. Stephen himself was denounced, in one Communist youth newspaper. In a November 1946 radio address, Mindszenty warned that “the first three centuries of the Christian era, the French Revolution, and the Hitler regime all teach us one lesson: those who restrict religious liberty will soon deprive citizens of all their other human rights.” The Church has always “insisted on maintaining her independence from secular authority.” [3]

    Backed by the Vatican (Pius XI had elevated him to the primateship of Hungary that summer), Mindszenty continued speak against the Communists, delivering a nationwide radio address adjuring “every Christian believer” to “exercise his civil rights in accordance with his religion, disregarding all attempts at intimidation.” Still moving slowly, the Communist regime had not yet ended real parliamentary elections, but “were preparing for them with a great deal of political cunning and equivocation.” In speaking against them, Mindszenty followed the example of previous Hungarian primates, who had rebuked any king who violated the constitution and “demand[ed] that he obey the law of the land.” This practice had continued under the constitution enacted after the First World War. “The nation expected that of its primates,” and Mindszenty had no intention of disappointing them by shirking his duty. He drafted a pastoral letter on the elections, citing Communist abuses of power and calling “for a political program on the Christian foundation.” It worked. The Smallholders Party, which had “committed itself to the defense and pursuance of Christian principles, received a firm majority of the votes, while the Communists limped in at seventeen percent. But votes are one thing, military occupation another. The Red Army remained firmly in control, and some Smallholder Party men distanced themselves from the Church. The resulting coalition government gave the Communists control of the police.

    Mindszenty shows why Communism proved such a formidable enemy. It was itself “a kind of religion,” “with dogmas and a hierarchical leadership.” According to Marxist ideology, “matter is the sole reality,” uncreated, but self-moving. Although the consequence of “a dialectical movement,” the world’s “order and purpose” obey not a Hegelian ‘Absolute Spirit’ but evolution or progress resulting from “the contradictions inherent in matter itself.” One might recall the ‘swerve’ Epicureans attribute to atoms, except that the Marxist dialectic is teleological, not cyclical. This “constant motion gives matter the ability to evolve and change,” moving from simple chemical reactions to biological life and human consciousness. The dialectical character of these evolutionary changes makes them abrupt; “accumulated quantitative change suddenly spills over into qualitative change.” In human societies, this accounts for the violence of revolutions. If asked to prove their claims, Communists regard them as “incontrovertible axioms which need no proof,” “amply supported by science.” Mindszenty permits himself to observe, drily, “in this respect they do not ask for much by way of proof.” He is sufficiently astringent to suggest that “the spokesmen of Communism have learned the nature of human wishful thinking and turn it to good account.” And they appeal to compassion, drawing in many of those “who take the side of the poor and the suffering and who desire a just social order.” “Such people often become unwittingly the henchmen of the Communists.” They also appeal to Christians whose beliefs have weakened, those “on the lookout for new and stronger premises.” Communists carefully “concealed their plans for seizing control and maintained that they had no intention of imposing the Marxist doctrines on everyone,” contenting themselves to speak “of human rights and freedom of conscience quite in the tone and style of Western bourgeois politicians.”

    In view of conditions in Hungary, “I decided to prepare our people for a difficult time of oppression and want.” Penance, prayer, replies to Communist accusations against the Church would all “intensify the religious life of the whole nation.” He coined a phrase that carried throughout the country: “The harder the hammer, the tougher the anvil.”

    In fall of 1946, the pope elevated him to the rank of cardinal. Upon returning from his ordination in Rome, he held Holy Mass two days before Christmas in the factory town of Csepel, which the Communists regarded as “their citadel.” To their “bitter surprise,” the Mass and his visit was well received, Mindszenty’s message of Christian love, contrasted with the interclass hatred fomented by the Party, striking a core among Hungarians who detested the military occupation and its agents more than they resented ‘capitalists.’

    But a more lasting, institutional counter to the Communist regime ideology and hierarchy was needed, especially in answer to the regime’s planned takeover of the schools. Mindszenty didn’t trust the Smallholders Party to defend Hungarian schools with steadfastness, so he “mobilized the parents to defend our schools.” Lectures, conferences, courses for parents and teachers, mass meetings “to answer the charges of the parties and the press,” all “forced the Communists to change their tactics.” Instead of appealing to ‘the masses,’ whom they couldn’t sway, they appealed to the leaders of the rival political parties to meet with Communist Party leaders, circumventing parliamentary debate with negotiations in private. In these, collaborators within the ranks of the non-Communist parties could exert outsized influence. The Smallholders Party leaders didn’t know who the collaborators were and lacked the experience to match “the machinations of the politically skilled Marxists,” who had been carefully trained in Moscow during their years of exile. The voters, especially the parents, weren’t fooled, however, “calling public attention to the dangers threatening the church schools and the Christian education of their children.” Bypassing the corrupted political process, they simply enrolled their children into the Church schools. For a time, at least, Communist policies stalled.

    Communists used the schools, first, “to alienate the youth from religion,” and second, to alienate them from their families. “Inexperienced boys and girls were taught in school that their parents were backward, were prisoners of old superstitions, and were altogether reactionary.” In this way, the regime could exploit children’s natural restiveness under parental authority by making their habituation to a real tyranny seem as if it were an act of liberation. “The modern family is exposed to many temptations,” beginning well before children go to school. “An unborn child has just as much right to live as a child lying in the cradle or in its mother’s arms; it has as much right to live as you or I.” Even married couples who use contraceptive methods forget that “all rights,” including conjugal rights, “involve responsibilities,” and “those who attempt to avoid the responsibility of conceiving a child turn the sanctuary of marriage into a den of iniquity” in which “the marriage partners become companions in sin.” [4]

    By 1947, however, the Soviets had worn down the Smallholders Party, seizing more power within the government for themselves in a cabinet reshuffle. The next year, they seized power outright in Czechoslovakia. Mindszenty protested and the Communists “began preparing the way for my arrest.” And not a moment too soon, from their point of view. The Cardinal had seen how the Communists in the Soviet Union had “destroyed the Greek Rite Catholic Church in the annexed territories of the western Ukraine and in the sub-Carpathian region, which had once been part of historic Hungary.” And Mindszenty evidently had read his Tocqueville, understanding the moral and political importance of civil associations. “To me it seemed that the most effective defense against atheistic materialism was a deepening of the religious life throughout the country,” which he undertook to accomplish in a series of talks with priests and laymen throughout Hungary. These visits “strengthened cooperation between the flock and the clergy in defense of the faith and of institutions of the Church.” Against the Communists’ charge that the Church “had been little concerned for the people and had always stood on the side of the exploiters,” Mindszenty could cite historical facts to the contrary, given the Church’s extensive charitable efforts throughout the centuries. But he also understood that “in the struggle of ideas abstract reasoning and dry theory are of little use”; steadfastness goes farther. “Especially when dealing with determined Communists, a hesitant, irresolute attitude could prove disastrous. And I think to this hour that our position is seriously weakened by those Christians whose primary concern seems to be worrying about whether any of the charges brought against the Church may not sometime, someplace have been justified. The excesses of modern ‘self-criticism’ often serve only the interests of our bitter enemies.” Precisely so. “Christianity and Communism were about to measure their strength in a decisive contest,” a Kulturkampf. “We could not ask whether the Christian spirit would win,” but only insist that the Church must bear witness to the struggle and to engage its enemy in such a way that hope would not fade out within the Church itself. 

    “Religion is not in fact the private matter it is often said to be.” That is because “no power exists that can more deeply affect human life, can more deeply stir the souls of men.” [5] Not only does religiosity affect social and political institutions, those institutions also “can influence…religious life for good or ill”—a point pastors need to recognize. Although in countries with relatively settled commercial-republican regimes this might easily be overlooked, not so “when [political] parties are competing and fighting on the ideological front,” when they contend over the type of regime itself. In Hungary, public schools had long required students to attend classes of religious instruction. Needless to say, the Communists moved to abolish that, and some “so-called progressive Catholics” advocated accommodation “for the sake of ‘peace.'” Mindszenty understood that there would be no peace between the Church and the Communist Party.  Under severe public pressure, the government backed down, temporarily. “The Church’s resistance had plainly shown how deeply rooted religion is in the souls of the Hungarian people.” But thanks to several electoral machinations, “Parliament became a docile tool in the hands of the totalitarian Communists”; sooner or later, the new regime would renew its pressure on the Church, Hungary’s principal resister to their ‘totalizing.’

    In the meantime, since the Communist Party wasn’t the only ‘international’ organization in the world, Mindszenty made sure “that the Catholic press in the West obtained documentary evidence of what had really happened,” giving the world “a truthful view of the methods employed in Bolshevist persecution of the churches.” This “gave the anti-Communist movement in the free world a tremendous impetus,” and as a result “both Hungarian and foreign Communists came to look upon me as one of their chief enemies, who had to be gotten out of the way.” It began with ad hominem attacks in speeches and newspaper articles by Party operatives. This was accompanied by the charge that the Hungarian Church “was guilty of spiritual terrorism when in fact she was merely the anguished witness of spiritual terrorism.” In November 1948, the Communists accused Mindszenty of conspiring against the Hungarian State. 

    The story of his arrest, interrogation-torture, show trial, conviction, and imprisonment amounts to an account of the way the regime ruled the Hungarian nation and the Hungarian Church. More, Mindszenty’s imitatio Christi parallels Christian life as such, renewing the example Christ Himself set for Christians in His regime, that is, His Ecclesia or assembly. “I would have to go this route to the end, and so too would they.”

    Beatings with truncheons, sleep deprivation, and food mixed with drugs were administered with caution, as the Party needed to keep Mindszenty alive for the fraudulent public trial they planned. They needed him to be strong enough to make a false confession before the world. The strategy behind these tactics “was to pound the charges into the prisoner’s mind, so that he gradually became convinced he actually had fomented a plot” against the Communist regime. As one torturer shouted, “Your business is to confess to what we want to hear.” If so, Mindszenty replied, why bother to extract a confession at all?—a piece of disrespect to socialist authority that earned him another truncheoning. 

    One thing can be said for such tactics: they work. “My powers of resistance gradually faded. Apathy and indifference grew, More and more the boundaries between true and false, reality and unreality, seemed blurred to me. I became insecure in my judgment,” and “now I myself began to think that somehow I might very well be guilty.” He was almost literally dehumanized, as “my shaken nervous system weakened the resistance of my mind, clouded my memory, undermined my self-confidence, unhinged my will—in short undid all the capacities that are most human in man.” 

    “We are the masters now.” His torturers were right. “Without knowing what had happened to me, I had become a different person.” After four weeks of torture, however, the written confession he signed still had to be forged by his captors. At the subsequent show trial, “the prosecution went so far as to characterize my stand against the Communist Party as a crime against the democratic system,” which was upheld as being identical to Communist Party rule. The attorney designated by the Party to mount his ‘defense’ argued that the accused “must be regarded as a victim of the Vatican,” which obviously was the larger target of the Soviet Union, ruler of Hungary. He assured the court that his client had repented of his sins against democracy, so defined. This enabled to court to avoid sentencing a cardinal of the Catholic Church to death, which the Party fully understood would have made him a bit too much of a Christian martyr to suit their purposes. He received a life sentence, instead. 

    Prison conditions themselves were designed to precipitate death, anyway, by disease. His first cell was in “an unheated dungeon,” below ground level, with water seeping in through the walls. It was not his last, however, because policy required that political prisoners be shifted from one place to another—a “Soviet invention,” intended to further disorient the prisoner and to ensure that he could form no “lasting relationships with any of the individuals in his environment.” After all, the Bolsheviks themselves had plenty of experience in jails; they knew that prisons can be excellent places to ‘network.’

    After months of this, the prison’s rulers permitted Mindszenty to read. As he understates it, “choices were very limited.” Secular novelists on the Left were available—Hugo, Balzac, Zola, France—as of course were Marx, Engels, Lenin, Stalin. “The library’s accent was as distinctly Russian as it was Communist.” That is, after the physical torture came the attempt to change the regime of the soul—exactly paralleling the tactics of regime change imposed upon the Hungarian nation, and in all the nations ruled by the Communists. And, as in those regimes, even ‘totalitarianism’ wasn’t quite total: “As I read, I felt amazement that the Communist censors had shown mercy to such writers as Dante, Zrinyi, and Sienkiewicz.” Gogol and Dostoevsky, too, escaped the censorious net, perhaps on the grounds that they were Russians.

    “Those outside prison walls might think that doing nothing can have no history. But it can.” He took notes on his readings, wrote critiques of the Communist materials and an essay “on philosophy and its responsibility”—which, one might surmise, included some stringent observations of the Encyclopedists and Herr Marx. He assembled an anthology on apologetics, a subject with which he had more than passing familiarity, and also brought together “material for a book on the lives of the Hungarian saints,” continuing his interest in the strong link between Hungarian patriotism and Christianity. He worked in view of the regime question, spiritually posed. “I thought over my decades of struggle, the achievements of which were now being extinguished. I also asked myself what were the faults and sins of our country. How could all this have come about? What form should the rebuilding—with God’s help—take? How could so many wounds be healed? Where would the work have to begin?”

    He lived Dante’s Commedia. “Faith alone helped me to get through this foretaste of Purgatory.” Imprisonment “can direct men’s minds toward God, as “solitude often revives memories of long-forgotten religious truths.” Not that the Communist regime failed to persecute religious practice, even there, closing the chapels and converting them into cells for the growing prison population. Although, “for decades the political Left has been given to hero worship of prisoners,” now that Leftists were in charge of the jails their esteem for them ended. “In the peaceful atmosphere at the end of the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries, we in the Church tended to think that the age of the martyrs was over. But it will never be over.” Nor is martyrdom in the end a thing to be regretted, since “in prison you learn to feel with every fiber of your being that this world in its essence is not a place of joy but a vale of tears.” Mindszenty recalls Augustine’s prayer, “It was in mercy thou didst chasten me, schooling me to thy obedience”; now, one might also call Solzhenitsyn’s sentences in The Gulag Archipelago: “Bless you, prison, bless you for being in my life For there, lying upon he rotting prison straw, I came to realize that the object of life is not prosperity as we are made to believe, but the maturity of the human soul.”

    Mindszenty would have perished, had the regime not feared “the reaction of the outside world if, after the deaths of so many priests and loyal Catholic laymen, the head of the Hungarian Church were also to die in prison.” He credits, also, the prayers of his mother (herself “the most wonderful gift of Providence,” throughout the years they both lived) and of so many other Catholic faithful. Released in 1955, he witnessed the Hungarian uprising of the following year. He had not anticipated this, but finds it understandable, since “the Hungarians had never been a herd people; for them the individual, the family, the clan were always what counted.” Hungary’s “urge for freedom and her pride were not broken by oppression.” When the Soviets crushed his people physically, in November, he sought asylum in the U. S. embassy. “The moral force, the solidarity, the tenacity of the Hungarian people were sublime and the sympathy of the outside world was a great solace to us. But what became of the seed that had been sown?” Verbal expressions of sympathy poured in but “our cries for help met with no response in deeds.” Even as the nations captive within the Soviet empire intensified their detestation of Moscow, the influence of the Soviets in the Western countries “steadily grew” in subsequent years. 

    Even more discouraging to Mindszenty was the capitulation the regime had forced upon the Hungarian Church while he was imprisoned. The religious orders were dissolved, a move justified by saying that the useful Church functions had been assumed by the socialist State, while the teachings of the Church were worse than useless. Threatened with further persecution, the episcopate accepted a proffered concordat in August 1950. This “profound humiliation” was intended to undermine the prestige of the Church and to turn it to regime purposes. “The regime, which had objected to my pastoral letters as improper interference in political affairs, now demanded that the clergy throw its weight behind all those political and economic measures that it hated—collectivization, forced deliveries to the state, and so on.” The “peace priests,” once marginalized, now rose to prominence, as “all episcopal offices became mere executive arms of the Bureau for Church Affairs,” receiving orders from the minister of the interior and its officers from the state security police. But “the servility, wickedness and irresponsibility of the peace priests naturally made it all the more debasing,” not only in Hungary but internationally, when they ‘represented’ the Hungarian Church at conferences abroad.  

    The library at the U. S embassy, where he lived in exile, afforded him the chance to learn much more than he had ever done about the Anglo-American world and especially “to appreciate the nature of Catholicism in the United States,” which proved sounder than he had supposed it to be. He was touched by a church in Connecticut, whose parishioners set up a statue of Our Lady of Hungary, having it modeled on a photograph of his mother, who had died in 1960. “My mother was a gleaming star in hard and confused times. My gratitude for having had her in life had to be greater than my sorrow at her passing.” In this, Mindszenty’s family life embodied his understanding of Hungary. On his deathbed, King Stephen had dedicated “our land and people to the mother of our Lord, Hungary’s ‘Great Lady.'” The first country to pledge itself to the Virgin, Hungary “since that time…has been officially known as ‘Mary’s land.'” At those times when Hungary “forsook the protection of Our Lady, an abyss opened wide to swallow us, and the battlefield became our common grave”; when Hungarians have freed themselves, they devoted themselves to Mary as their savior. This was true before and after the rule of the Tartars and the Turks. “In recent times, anticlerical and liberal ideas have sown the seeds of atheism in our land, the morals of our people have decayed,” and still “the grace and prayers of the Virgin have enabled our country to survive its many afflictions.” [6]

    Although grateful for the asylum the United States had extended to him, the foreign policy of the United States, and of the West generally, was another matter. “‘Coexistence’ and ‘detente’ had become magic words in international politics,” and the Communist regimes played along, “chiefly so that public opinion in the West would not oppose the forthcoming disarmament and economic and trade conferences with the Soviet bloc.” By the time the Nixon Administration took charge, “I knew quite well that I had become an undesirable guest in the embassy not only because of my illness but also because I stood in the way of the policy of detente.”

    In September 1971, he left Hungary and took up residence at the Vatican, but found little sympathy there, either. Indeed, the Vatican, now under papacy of the unimpressive Paul VI, “lifted the ban on the excommunicated peace priests two weeks after my departure” and evinced “general indifference to my affairs.” After regaining some of his physical strength, he departed for a seminary in Vienna. There, “as primate of Hungary,” he intended “to take the many hundreds of thousands of homeless Catholics”—i.e., his fellow exiles—under “my episcopal care; to warn the world public of the peril of Bolshevism by publishing my memoirs; and perhaps now and then to concern myself with the tragic fate of my nation.” The Vatican blocked the first initiative, fearing to “vex the regime in Budapest.” The Vatican also attempted to induce him to cease criticizing that regime, demanding that he submit all his future public statements to its staff. He refused.

    He did send the manuscript of his memoirs to the Pope, who praised it while worrying that it might spur Budapest to “punish the entire Church of Hungary.” Mindszenty scarcely let such an attempt at moral intimidation go unanswered, replying that “the history of Bolshevism, which already goes back more than half a century, shows that the Church simply cannot make any conciliatory gesture in the expectation that the regime will in turn abandon its persecution of religion,” since “that persecution follows from the essential nature and internal organization of its ideology.” Communism is the Church’s enemy in principle. Further, given the corrupted character of the Hungarian Church, now controlled by the regime, why would the regime punish its own puppet? At this, the Pope requested his resignation as archbishop of Esztergom, which Mindszenty declined to do. The Pope then declared the archiepiscopal see of Esztergom vacant, venturing to issue a press release that Mindszenty had retired. Mindszenty then issued a correction: “Cardinal Mindszenty has not abdicated his office as archbishop nor his dignity as primate of Hungary. the decision was taken by the Holy See alone.” With this, “I arrived at complete and total exile.”

     

    Notes

    1. See also Mindszenty’s pastoral letter in the aftermath of the war, in which he blamed Hungarians’ wartime sufferings on “the failure of our leaders to observe our traditions and our ancient faith” and their consequent violation of divine law. “This kind of thinking caused innocent people to be interned in concentration camps, robbed of all their possessions, exiled, or murdered outright.” But rulers who choose “to place themselves above the laws of God” undermine “the foundations of their own authority,” since God is the one who ordains rulers, expecting them to rule in accordance with His commands, aligning their own commands with His. Mindszenty thus intended to focus Hungarians’ blame where it belonged, assuring that “women who were raped by violence…are without sin.” Similarly, Hungarian prisoners of war should not be greeted “with reproaches and contempt, but only with love and respect.” This is the Christian law of love: “Long ago our nation was conquered by the sword,” wielded by Tartars, and again by the Turks; but” it was preserved and nourished by the Cross.” (Pastoral Letter, May 1945).
    2. In an article in the Catholic publication Uj Ember, Mindszenty called democracy “the modern watchword.” In the Church, he remarked, “there is no predominance of any particular class.” In appointing its officials, it “has always looked for quality and personal character,” not “social standing.” Further, “in opposition to the claims of the totalitarian state, the Church proclaims the right of the individual, human rights, and the rights of the family.” (September 23, 1945). In a pastoral letter several weeks later, he wrote that “the world has suffered long enough under the various forms of tyranny,” one of which “caused this insane and murderous war and forced it to drag on and on,” treading “underfoot the most sacred rights of mankind.” The Hitler regime now defeated, the democratic nations do not “wish to exchange the totalitarian rule of a Führer for the equally totalitarian rule of some other dictator,” namely, Josef Stalin. “True democracy is based on the recognition that every human being possesses certain inalienable rights—rights which no power on earth may wrest from him.”
    3. In this address, Mindszenty details the steps by which the Nazi regime undermined the German churches. Those steps were conspicuously similar to those currently employed by the Communists in Hungary, a point no listener there and then could have missed. Further, “Religious persecution has two faces, just like Janus. One of its faces may shine brightly and promise us liberty; but its other face glares at us with the grim gaze of a tyrant.” He immediately cited a law passed in January 1946, guaranteeing “all Hungarian citizens certain inalienable civil and human rights,” including freedom of worship,” a law supported by Marxists in the parliament which passed it—the smiling face of Janus. In a 1947 article, “Communism and the Russian Orthodox Church,” he showed the parallels between the tactics of the Soviet Communists in the first decade of Soviet rule and those seen in Hungary today. These included separation of Church and state, expropriation of Church property, secularization of schools, banning of the religious press, placing the head of the Church under arrest, collaboration “of certain liberal-minded priests bent on reforming the Church,” deceptive promises to the Orthodox clergy, and collectivization of Church property. “All the [Orthodox] Church’s efforts at peaceful coexistence and humiliating cooperation were in vain. For Communism in s an atheistic doctrine which is by nature the enemy of religious faith. A kind of inner compulsion something akin to fear of the spirit and the soul, drives it to struggle against religion. It merely conceals its fundamental hostility to religion only when concern for the preservation of its power forces it do so.”
    4. See “A Sermon in Szentendre, n.d., delivered shortly after Pius XII had designated him a bishop. In a contemporaneous sermon, he identified four “fortresses” of Catholicism: the parish churches, Catholic schools, family homes, and consecrated churchyards and cemeteries. “What his heart is to a man, the church is to a town.” (Sermon in Szentgottárd, n.d.).
    5. People who separate religion from the rest of life are trying to get rid of religion altogether; for they do not want it to interfere with the way they live.” This being so, “societies which regard religion as a personal matter, unrelated to the conduct of public life, will soon be swallowed up in corruption, violence and sin.” To proclaim, with Nietzsche, that God is dead, that “we must all pass beyond the antiquated concepts of good and evil,” is to risk the eventual disposition of the Europeans to whom he proclaimed those teachings. 
    6. See Mindszenty, “Brief Survey of Hungarian History,” n.d.

    Filed Under: Nations

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 26
    • 27
    • 28
    • 29
    • 30
    • …
    • 225
    • Next Page »