Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Publius on the American Regime and the American State

    June 12, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Publius [Alexander Hamilton]: The Federalist Number 13.

     

    Always, Americans face two questions: the question of regime; the question of the modern state.

    By ‘regime’ I mean four things: who rules; by what forms or institutions they rule; what way of life rulers and ruled will lead; and what ends or purposes the rulers intend to secure by those forms and that way. These four dimensions of the regime intertwine. If, for example, a tyrant rules, he will require such institutions as a large standing army controlled by himself for internal policing as well as for conquest, a judiciary dependent on his will alone, and a legislature without independent powers. If a tyrant rules, the way of life will encourage a moral atmosphere of mutual distrust and self-protective secrecy among neighbors, habits of fear punctuated by moments of terror. The ends served by these institutions and this way of life may range from the safety and pleasure of the tyrant to the remaking of human nature itself.

    If the people rule, the same thing might happen. The popular majority might tyrannize as well as—maybe worse than—a ‘majority of one.’ Hence republicanism or representative government, a republic (in the American model) of extensive territory and population wherein no one faction may obtain a ruling majority.

    The first fourteen numbers of The Federalist address the crucial question of regime—whether a people can truly govern themselves non-tyrannically, by reflection and choice, not accident and force. But they equally address the question of statism.

    Modern political philosophers—in England, such men as Francis Bacon and Thomas Hobbes—sharply criticized feudalism. A feudal society structures itself politically rather like a cinnamon roll: Ruling authority organizes itself into swirls and morsels—an aristocrat here, a city there, with a king mixed in and a network of churches and law courts throughout, each with more or less independent sources of financial support and military power, sometimes overlapping one another but none simply superior to the others.

    The statists did away with this. Statesmen organize states along the lines of a wagon wheel, with a central hub of authority and spokes radiating out to the border. Along these institutional spokes resides administrators or bureaucrats, beholden to the center for their appointments and salaries, exerting control over the population, now reconceived as the nation organized into the nation-state. From the center of the state commands and force flow out; to the center, recruits and revenues flow in, far more efficiently than under the feudal order. Wherever a state appeared, neighboring political communities more or less needed to imitate it, lest the wheel roll over them.

    For Bacon and Hobbes and their royal sponsors, the best regime for the modern state was monarchy, giving unity of command to the powerful state. Having felt the pincers of monarchic statism, the Founders disagreed, with muskets.

    But the defense of the natural rights enunciated in the Declaration of Independence via institutions of political liberty required the strength and unity that only a modern state could provide. Only a state could muster the economic and military strength to defend itself against the surrounding European empires, contemptuous of republicanism.

    Publius therefore puts the matter of federal union front and center in his introductory essays. The Founders propose to solve the problem of republican self-government in a dangerous world of centralized, monarchist, imperial states by gathering military powers in a national government under popular control, with carefully enumerated, balanced, separated powers while leaving most domestic authority firmly in the hands of the governments of the several smaller states, where citizens can more readily govern themselves—states equally represented in one house of the national legislature.

    In the thirteenth Federalist, Publius warns against disunion by appealing to Americans’ sense of economy. Were we to divide into separate confederacies, the two or three new governments would nonetheless rule extensive territories, larger than those of the British Isles. Instead of one federal government, we would have at least two, with unnecessary duplication of ruling institutions and commensurately heavier expenses per capita. If jealousies arose between these confederacies, commercial tariffs and larger militaries would further degrade prosperity. North America would look more and more like the Europe from which Americans had declared their independence. To those who look askance at a national government, Publius replies, one such thing is better than two or three. To undertake to found thirteen such sovereignties would involve Americans in “a project too extravagant and too replete with danger to have many advocates.”

    But can one government—even a carefully limited government—truly govern one such large territory? Publius answers this question in his fourteenth essay, concluding his introduction to the new Constitution.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    The Intellectual Life and the Social Life: Imperfect Together

    June 12, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Thomas Sowell: Intellectuals and Society. New York: Basic Books, 2009.

    Originally published in Social Science and Modern Society. Volume 47, Number 6, November/December 2010.

     

    The respected conservative economist Thomas Sowell writes too gracefully and, well, economically to offer a more precise title for this book, such as Modern Intellectuals and Modern Democratic Regimes. But that’s his topic.

    By “intellect” Sowell means “the capacity to grasp and manipulate complex ideas.” Intellect forms only part of “intelligence,” a term encompassing “judgment and care in selecting relevant explanatory facts and in establishing empirical tests of any theory that emerges.” A bright college sophomore’s intellect ought to metamorphose into intelligence by the time he starts his doctoral dissertation. He probably has a way to go before he achieves “wisdom”—”the rarest quality of all,” combining intelligence with experience and self-discipline. With wisdom he will understand the limitations of his “own experience and of reason itself.” If, however, our sophomore goes wrong he may come to use his capacity to manipulate ideas cynically, in which case he will turn out a sophist or, if gifted with oratorical flair, a demagogue. Quite as likely he may let his wishes be horses, in which case he will be a fairly typical specimen of the intellectual in modern democracy.

    “Intellectuals” grasp and manipulate complex ideas. Their work “begins and ends with ideas”; they produce ideas instead of material goods (an economist would usually say ‘widgets’) or actions (‘services’ in econo-speak). Being “intellectuals,” “Adam Smith never ran a business, and Karl Marx never administered a gulag.” The concrete objects intellectuals do produce—manuscripts—serve merely as vehicles for their primary products.

    The “penumbra” surrounding intellectuals consists of purveyors of the ideas intellectuals produce: teachers, journalists, social activists, political aides, judges’ clerks. Along with intellectuals themselves, these comprise the “intelligentsia.” Although Sowell claims that “the demand for public intellectuals is largely manufactured by themselves,” this strikes me as improbable. Human beings have wanted explanations of the world for a long time. (The Bible will serve as empirical evidence of this, and I can see social-scientific heads nodding in nearly universal agreement with my methodology.) What is more, rulers have usually wanted justifications of their rule. Intellectuals aspire to the functions of the ancient prophet, priest, or sage. Sowell is right to say that widespread literacy and education generally, along with mass media—all features of the regime of modern democracy—have increased the audience for intellectual services. Modern bureaucracies—impersonal, scientistic if not exactly scientific—also augment demand. Both the characteristic modern regimes—democratic republicanism and democratic despotism—and the characteristic modern political organization—the Machiavellian/Hobbesian centralized state—afford intellectuals heady opportunities for prestige and authority.

    The associations of intellectuals with ruling, with political life, leads to difficulties well known to Socrates and his enemies. But these difficulties take a new direction in modern regimes because modern regimes valorize ideas, abstractions, more than they esteem such personal relationships as reverence and deference. Unlike material products and services, Sowell, observes, “no external test” can validate an ideational product. This leaves the producers of ideas vulnerable to circularity of thought or even to outright solecism. The conservative politician Newt Gingrich has decried the fact that social democrats persist in their socialism despite socialism’s real-world failures; Sowell would answer that real-world failure does not exactly disporove an idea in the mind of him who lovingly holds it. Like Brooklyn Dodgers fans of old, the intellectual can always recur to his battle-cry, “Wait till next year.”

    Insulated politically by the freedom of speech and academic freedom of modern liberal democracy, intellectuals fortify their never-say-die persistence with the social and political armature of status. At best tenured and at least unmolested by outraged bearers of hemlock, intellectuals form a sort of aristocracy within democracy. With that measure of the acerb he has cultivated over the years, Sowell calls them “the anointed.” Their heads drip with the soothing balm of security from serious harm, no matter what they say or write, and no matter what they say or write about one another. This confidence easily overextends to the habit of ranging outside their field of knowledge, as literary critics pronounce on the latest war and sociologists ‘deconstruct’ literature. (I exempt my fellow political scientists from this stricture, inasmuch as Aristotle rightly describes politics as the architectonic art, but I hesitate to claim that Sowell would concur.)

    Intellectuals thus test the limits of human knowledge but have few if any empirical constraints on that test. Given the obvious limits of human knowledge, however, “the population at large may have vastly more total knowledge” than the new aristocrats. This becomes clear when intellectuals propose, and bureaucrats attempt, the governance of vast economic markets characteristic of the revenue-hungry modern state. No amount of rational planning can match the massive, daily, empirical operations of a relatively free market, with its “innumerable features on which no given individual can possibly be expert.” Should this not put practical limits on the rule of intellectuals through the bureaucracies and bureaucrats that adopt and adapt their ideas?

    Unfortunately not, Sowell observes. “Modern, expansive government—the centralized, administrative state—”tends to magnify the influence of the intelligentsia, since government as a decision-making institution means essentially legislators, judges, executives and bureaucrats, non of whom is constrained to stay within the area of their own competence in making decisions.” Although the American Founders took care to separate and balance the powers of the central government and also to establish a federal state that would keep most governing decisions in municipalities, counties, and states, the centralizing state-builders of the twentieth century—beginning with the Progressives and continued by the New Dealers and their progeny—deliberately compromised these institutional/structural boundaries in the name of attaining desired economic and social goals. Animated by “a vision of themselves as a self-anointed vanguard, leading toward that better world”—”a huge investment of ego in a particular set of opinions”—members of the intellectual-political complex effectively re-founded the American regime. What had been a commercial and federal republic now incorporates a permanent if non-hereditary aristocracy. Unlike the aristocrats of feudalism, the new aristocrats inhabit a centralized state dedicated both to leveling all other social groups and to dividing those groups into newly-invented social categories—famously, ‘race,’ ‘class,’ and ‘gender’—the better to rule the new ‘multicultural’ society.

    Sowell substantiates his critique with chapters describing the arguments the new aristocrats make in defense of their claims to rule. He groups these arguments into five policy areas: economics, social relations, the information and opinion industries (the media, academia), law, and foreign relations (particularly as they relate to war).

    Not surprisingly, one of Sowell’s most trenchant chapters addresses intellectuals’ characteristic economic fallacies. For example, intellectuals make much of the widening income gap between rich and poor, a Marxist theme that renews itself periodically, lending weight to calls for the political authority to redress injustice. True in itself, this claim ignores the fact that the actual members of the several economic classes constantly change, as does the relative prosperity of all classes. So, for example, a 22-year-old college graduate may begin her working life as a low-income worker, but likely will not remain one for more than a few years. “Low-income” is itself a relative term, as the poor of 2010 in the United States enjoy better lives than the poor of 1960.

    These facts notwithstanding, the ‘income gap’ performs usefully when described as a social problem that cries out for a solution. As one might expect, the solution does not involve the workings of a free market so much as economic and social planning conceived by the intellectuals and carried out by the intelligentsia—neo-aristocrats armed by intellect supplemented with compassion. To the question, ‘So what?’ Sowell replies: “The crucial distinction between market transactions and collective decision-making is that in the market people are rewarded according to the value of their goods and services to those particular individuals who receive those goods and services, and who have every incentive to seek alternative sources, so as to minimize their costs, just as sellers of goods and services have every incentive to seek the highest bids for what they have to offer. But collective decision-making by third parties allows those third parties to superimpose their preferences on others at no cost to themselves, and to become the arbiters of other people’s economic fate without accountability for the consequences.”

    Planners in a government bureaucracy differ from planners in a corporate bureaucracy because they have far less responsibility for ‘making the payroll’; if the government’s numbers don’t add up, they raise taxes, inflate the currency, blame the banks. Insulated from the consequences of their actions more than their counterparts in the market, they need not know, and may not want to know, how difficult running a business is.

    As an economist, Sowell has always avoided that simplistic abstraction, Homo economicus. He unfailingly points to social customs, habits of mind and heart that shape the economic choices of individuals. This makes him alert to the repercussions of the intellectuals’ “social vision,” as he calls it. Following a line of thought as old as the Enlightenment, intellectuals assume the malleability of social customs and institutions. Born free but everywhere in chains, with no intractable natural flaws or original sins, mankind can and should break their mind-forged manacles. Social visionaries “are in a sense defending their very souls” as perfectible by the reform of social institutions, a reform movement they step up to lead.

    Accurate so far as it goes, Sowell’s account of social visionaries overlooks the historicism of social visionaries ‘Left’ and ‘Right.’ Rousseau’s teaching on the malleability of society and indeed of human nature itself served as a mere prelude to the relocation of moral and political authority from God and nature to the ‘march of history,’ which such thinkers as Hegel and Marx took to be a course of dialectical progress toward a perfected end state. This usefully allowed the intelligentsia to define as ‘reactionary’ any one and any thing that impeded progress, as defined and guided by the progressives—i.e., themselves. Because he overlooks this major refinement of the intellectuals’ line of attack, Sowell can praise Oliver Wendell Holmes, whose supposed realism and pragmatism merely underwrite yet another exercise in the social-historicist construction of truth. Sowell writes, “The exceptional facility of intellectuals with abstractions does not eliminate the difference between those abstractions and the real world.” True enough, but that’s the problem historicism, whether in ‘idealist’ or ‘realist’ mode, was designed to solve, and failed to solve. Historicism attempts to make the real ideal and the ideal real; might is right, and vice-versa. On this, there’s not a dime’s worth of difference between Holmes and someone like Woodrow Wilson, and a world of difference between either of them and Washington or Lincoln.

    Sowell puts his most important chapter squarely in the middle of the book. Apparently a discussion of the intellectuals’ doings in academia and the media, it really addresses the fundamental problem of epistemology. No mean analyst of statistics, Sowell shows how the intellectuals avoid serious criticism of their projects by “filtering out information contrary to their conception of how the world is or ought to be.” Sometimes this gets done crudely, as when Stalinist or Maoist genocides simply proceed unreported. More subtly, an intellectual might select statistics that support his argument and ignore the others, as when numbers on violent crime are manipulated to ‘prove’ that gun control cuts homicide rates. On the verbal level, re-labeling can sanitize a soiled term; thus did self-described ‘progressives’ start calling themselves ‘liberals’ in the 1920s, when Wilsonianism lost its luster, then went back to being ‘progressives’ in the early 2000s, after ‘liberalism’ got loaded, courtesy of conservative radio talk show hosts.

    Sowell remarks the limits of such manipulation of knowledge. The truth cannot be subjective, he observes, or else no one would survive very long. Yes, a goldfinch perceives reality differently than humans do, but members of both species demonstrably make mistakes due to misperception of their surroundings. The principle of radical subjectivism, supporting moral and cultural relativism, must be wrong.

    Sophistry impedes perception of reality (for humans, at any rate). Media and academic deployment of melodrama, conspiracy theories, and ‘just-so’ stories—appeals to satisfying but delusive emotions—supply the energy for what might otherwise strike most people as rather dry theories cooked up by geeky scribblers and policy wonks. The true appeal of historicist progressivism (one might add) is the universal lure of the happy ending at the end of all our hardships and sorrows.

    In the modern world intellectuals claimed the law as their domain early on. Sowell argues that when judges stop saying ‘what the law is’ in the sense of saying what the language of the law in front of them meant to the lawmakers, and when they start saying what the law is in the sense of making the law themselves, they effectively contravene the Constitutional prohibition against ex post facto laws. By becoming legislators they make the characteristic modern-intellectuals’ move: “going beyond one’s expertise.” Following a number of scholars, Sowell takes note of such phrases as “the elastic Constitution” (Wilson) and “the living Constitution” (Roscoe Pound)—wide roadways through which many a pseudo-interpretive truck may be driven. Such formulations serve “the sociological jurist”: the member of “a progressive and enlightened caste whose conceptions are in advance of the public and whose leadership is bringing popular thought to a higher level,” as Pound put it in 1907. Judges so styled look to effect a result instead of applying the law to a case. Having no training in social analysis, they frequently get their sociology wrong, too.

    War is a topic quite far from the expertise of an economist. Unlike many economists in the liberal camp—liberal in the Bright-and-Cobden sense, not in the progressives’—Sowell looks at war with a steady gaze, never supposing that peaceful economic competition will entirely replace it. He makes good sport of deflating the unthinking rhetorical antics of many pacifist intellectuals. In his two chapters on intellectuals’ pronouncements on war, Sowell does best when he avails himself of the writings of a statesman long experienced in war: Winston Churchill. Using Churchill as his guide, he recalls the follies of the 1930s intellectuals who, mixing their fears with hope, called Hitler a moderate while espousing a doctrinaire pacifism that the Nazi leader never professed to share. Sowell also does well on the Vietnam War, relying in large measure on the writings of Korean War veteran and experienced war correspondent Peter Braestrup. He goes off the rails on the First World War, precisely because he does not consult his favorite Churchill or (to give but one example) Charles de Gaulle’s brilliant and pity first book, The Enemy’s House Divided. As a result, he criticizes Wilson for entering the war at all, arguing that the “ostensible cause” of Wilson’s action, German submarine attacks on American shipping, served merely as a cloak for that inveterate intellectual’s “ideological aggrandizement.”

    Sowell’s argument here is worth unpacking, and refuting, in more detail, not the least for its illustration of one of his own principal theses—the danger of intellectuals ranging beyond their area of expertise—but mostly because he misses a subtler dimension of the intellectuals’ influence upon the intelligentsia, a dimension that adds resonance to his own insights. The Germans, he begins, sank passenger ships with Americans on board. “But these were ships entering a war zone in which both the British and the Germans were maintaining naval blockades, the former with surface ships and the latter with submarines—and each with the intention of denying the other both war materiel and food.” The Lusitania “was, years later, revealed to have been secretly carrying military supplies.” Further, submarines simply cannot “give warnings and pauses to let crews and passengers disembark before sinking passenger ships.” To Sowell, the fault lies not with the Germans in deploying a class of warships utterly wrong for the task assigned them, but with Wilson, for asserting “a right of Americans to sail safely into blockaded ports during wartime.” But maybe he wanted to court murderous attack in order to fight to make the world safe for democracy.

    As I have often asked myself while contemplating a large pizza, where to begin? The war supplies in question, listed on the ship’s manifest and therefore no remarkable secret at all, consisted mostly of rifle ammunition and other items allowed under U. S. law at the time. American statesmen had claimed the right to undertake neutral shipping in wartime since the founding. If the Germans had wanted to exercise the right to block military supplies to their enemies, they needed to deploy the surface ships that would have enabled them to board and inspect the ships of the neutral powers. If they lacked such ships, they had two decent options: to forego the blockade, treating it as a handicap in fighting that particular war; or, better still, to refuse to fight the war in the first place, to avoid signaling Austria to move against Serbia. That would have saved everyone, including Wilson, a great deal of trouble.

    As Churchill and de Gaulle show, the German military commanders and civilian rulers understood that unrestrained submarine warfare—attacks on commercial vessels—could very well bring the Americans into the war. Wilson got in only after some two years of such attacks—the Lusitania having been sunk in 1915; during those two year, the Germans themselves ratcheted the submarine attacks up and down, as the internal debate raged—a debate fundamentally centered on the character of the German regime itself, and in particular whether it would be ruled by civilians or soldiers. Wilson described his reluctance to make war not in ideological terms but in light of his memories of the Civil War; his father, a Presbyterian pastor, had opened his churchyard in Augusta for use as a field hospital, and the boy saw the wounded soldiers there. There were very few Americans who did not regard the repeated German depredations, taken together, as a casus belli. Wilson didn’t lead public opinion this time, he followed it. As far as making the world safe for democracy went, Wilson merely responded to one of the principal war aims of the German militarists, namely, to make the world unsafe for democracy. This had been the aim of the Holy Alliance powers in the previous century, as well. The fact that those militarists tried again, two decades later, speaks not against the war but against the peace settlement—Churchill’s point in his great book, The Aftermath.

    As de Gaulle shows, it was not so much Wilson but the Germans who were in the thrall of ideology during the war. Considering the military chieftains who finally ruled Germany, de Gaulle writes, “Perhaps one finds in their proceedings the imprint of the theories of Nietzsche on the Elite and the Superman”—theories valorizing “the will to power, the taste for risk, the contempt for others that one sees in Zarathustra, who appeared to these impassioned ambitieux as the ideal to which they should aspire.” In his excellent introduction to his English translation of de Gaulle’s book, Robert Eden explains that Nietzsche did not give the German warriors a doctrine—one might search a long time for a usable war plan in the philosopher’s writings—but rather generated a climate of opinion and sentiment that made such rashness as they exhibited seem admirable, a sign of vitality, a path to domination, to nobility. Reading Nietzsche, breathing in the moral atmosphere Nietzsche and his intellectual epigoni fostered, a generation of spirited warriors learned not to moderate and discipline their spiritedness but to let it run free—disastrously, for themselves, their country, and for Europe. An instance of intellectuals’ unwisdom, indeed.

    One thus concludes that Sowell is often right even when he is wrong—that is, more right than he knows. And he very well knows the most important thing about his life’s work: In the end he is an economist who looks beyond the often-dismal science to an economy of the spirit.

    Filed Under: Manners & Morals

    Self-Government and Its Discontents

    June 12, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Robert K. Faulkner and Susan Shell, eds.: America at Risk: Threats to Liberal Self-Government in an Age of Uncertainty. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2009.

    Originally published in Perspectives on Political Science. Volume 39, Number 1, January-March 2010.

     

    Collections such as this raise suspicions in anyone over the age of, say, twenty-five. When has the American regime not been “at risk”? From its beginning, a regime conceived in liberty and dedicated to the proposition that all men are created equal has struck many as a dubious bet. Self-government is hard enough for one person to achieve—but a whole people? In the immortal words of television comedienne Roseanne Barr, “Get real.”

    If an enduring regime of popular self-government seems unlikely, books such as this have proven a far safer bet, so long as the regime lasts. Self-government aims at security of life and happiness, but it achieves these good through perpetual insecurity—ceaseless takings of political pulse and social temperature. As Tocqueville said of Americans long ago, suicide is rare, but madness is common as we chart our malaises, real and imaginary.

    Then add ambition to the mixture. A new presidential administration has arrived! Will it perchance attend to the counsels of political scientists, a class of citizens whose sagacity and eagerness to advise rivals economists? If anyone points to an “age of uncertainty,” never fear; academia knows what to do and will point the way.

    If books such as this one generally illuminate little more than the vanity of human wishes and fears, how might one redeem the genre? Only by assembling writers who can see the perennial through the ephemera. For that task, Robert K. Faulkner and Susan Shell have the proverbial jeweler’s eyes.

    “The purpose of this book can be simply stated,” they write, “to set forth and examine the most important dangers confronting America today” (1). The contributors consider a “central theme,” namely, “the corrosion of the liberal constitutional order that has for so long guided the country at home and abroad” (1). The editors organize the book in four layers, beginning with the outer layer, American foreign policy. After that come internal politics or partisan factions; such social divisions as family, class, ethnicity, and religion; and, finally, the core of the matter, the question of political self-government itself.

    On foreign policy the editors have selected two eminent foreign scholars who happen to represent two of America’s earliest ‘significant others,’ France and England. Both attempt to describe America as an empire that has failed adequately to moderate itself or to rule its imperial ambitions.

    With his characteristic suave goodwill, Pierre Manent addresses “the transatlantic predicament” (15)—the division in geopolitical purpose between Europe and the United States. For its part, Europe has lost its former “prodigious vitality” (18), which derived from the rivalry of nation-states. By the beginning of the last century, European vitality overwhelmed its prudence, with Germany in the lead; by mid-century, a less vital but more sober Europe began to make peace with itself and to frame international institutions intended to tame the continent’s undeniably vital but also life-threatening animal spirits. In some respects, Europeans succeeded too well, and now “approach the world from the standpoint of Doctors Without Borders” (19)—animated by a sort of therapeutic humanitarianism that does its best to avoid the rough but invigorating give-and-take of political life. Manent notes, “The higher legitimacy of Europe has been built on the delegitimization of nations” (19).

    Meanwhile, Americans remain political, alert to the toughness it takes to rule, but they have also taken on an imperial mindset. Paradoxically, though, they may be insufficiently political in a capacious, Aristotelian sense. Having won two wars in defense of the regimes of political liberty, America has inclined to think of foreign policy as preeminently a military problem. That is, not only the Europeans, but also the Americans have lost to some degree what Aristotle calls the genuinely political way of life—of ruling and being ruled, of reciprocity. If Europeans tend toward ruling themselves by the peaceful and humane commands of mild-mannered technocrats, Americans rule others by the harsher commands of soldiers, treating longstanding allies rather like noncommissioned officers. Manent does not so much oppose the American policy of regime change—that is, of promoting commercial republicanism as a means of securing greater peace in the world—as he objects to an excessively impatient and ham-handed way of undertaking that policy. He writes, “Neither the conviction of Europe that everything will be fine if only we do nothing (except, that is, for ‘building Europe’), nor the conviction of the United States that everything will be fine if only we follow the American lead, seems to me to be conducive to durable success” (28). For Europeans, self-government will require overcoming complacency (and perhaps timidity); for Americans, self-government will require, more straightforwardly, greater self-restraint.

    Niall Ferguson calls America an empire in a more institutional sense. The United States is imperial not only in its willingness, or over-willingness, to deploy troops, but also in exporting its “institutions and culture to foreign peoples” (28). Americans “may or may not aspire to rule; but they do aspire to have others rule themselves in the American way” (34). He asserts that “the very act of imposing ‘freedom’ simultaneously subverts it” (34) and, even when it does not, Americans lack the funds, the manpower, and the attention span necessary to bring it off. The regime of commercial republicanism itself adapts badly to imperialism, as shown by the failure of the Defense Department to implement the State Department’s plan to set up workable civil institutions in Iraq after the successful completion of the 2003 conquest.

    Ferguson’s analysis will not do, simply on historical grounds. To start, he defines “empire” too loosely. Empire means rule. This means that the great period of American imperialism occurred before, not after, 1898, when Americans went from sea to shining sea, acquiring vast lands from Amerindians and Mexicans while getting rid of European claims. That was imperialism, albeit the Jeffersonian “empire of liberty”—that is, of republicanism. Americans had no difficulty in seeing that imperialism through to its conclusion. Americans also began to see that real empires need limits; more crucially, they saw how to set their limits, and they did so in the Mexican War. The United States took Mexico City but did not want it. Rather, Americans wanted a friendly regime ruling what they did not want of Mexico, in order to put an end to border disputes and wars. Drawing on Montesquieu’s well-known argument that commercial republics do not fight one another, they installed such a regime in Mexico. This practice has been at or near the core of American postwar policies ever since, including the attempt to reconstruct the former Confederate States of America.

    Therefore, it is historically and analytically inaccurate to claim that imposing freedom subverts freedom. It does so only if you do not achieve the right political settlement. Freedom needs a regime to secure it; it needs imposition, or rule. Manent’s France and Ferguson’s England should be happy that the Americans did stick things out in the years following 1945, despite the moderate European advice most memorably on display in that zithering ode to dithering, The Third Man. As for Iraq, the initial failure to move toward a better regime had everything to do with complacency originating in progressivist and historicist assumptions about democratic transition and very little to do directly with the character of the regime of democracy itself.

    The section of the book on political factionalism, “Creeds and Parties,” features essays by William A. Galston, James W. Ceaser, and Alan Wolfe. Galston reminds readers exactly of the need for ruling, ruling of a certain kind, in order to secure liberty. “A free society is not a suicide pact,” he writes (71). This does not vindicate Carl Schmitt’s tyranny-justifying claim that, in effect, everything is political. However, everything does need the political as a framework for thriving. Galston observes, “In the contemporary United States…the denigration of politics and the retreat toward private life are far more pervasive and troubling than is the opposing threat of totalizing politics” (72). As Tocqueville noticed, Americans can decline into individualism—a pupating, cocooned life led almost entirely inside the home and workplace, but one from which a mature political organism never quite emerges.

    Ceaser’s essay, the most valuable in the book, criticizes the most impressive of recent philosophic attempts to evade the need for rule, the branch of so-called post-modernism that he calls “political non-foundationalism.” Names associated with this doctrine include Richard Rorty, Jacques Derrida, (the later) John Rawls, and Jürgen Habermas. Political non-foundationalism hold that liberal democracy is best maintained by renouncing public reliance on a first principle, or foundation, that claims to embody an objective truth—something, for example, along the lines of the laws of nature invoked in the Declaration of Independence. Political life (they contend) should either be neutral toward such principles or exclude them altogether. Tocqueville called Christianity a precious legacy of aristocracy precisely because its claim to truth comes from on high. That, non-foundationalists maintain, is exactly its problem, and the problem with all such claims. Even if, as Tocqueville also argues, Christianity supports the principle of equality, and therefore of democracy, it does so in an undemocratic way and so must be discarded as a source of public judgment, along with much else.

    Ceaser ably traces non-foundationalism to historicism, a form of foundationalism. In contrast to the natural-rights and Biblical principles upheld by the American Founders, some Americans in the first half of the nineteenth century began to adapt Hegelianism to democracy. The prominent historian and Democratic Party speechwriter George Bancroft wrote, “The voice of the people is the voice of pure Reason” (81). However, the Democrats before the Civil War rejected a main component of Hegel’s political philosophy, statism. It remained for the Progressives, most notably Woodrow Wilson and John Dewey, to wed progressivist historicism with statism in America. At the same time, Dewey began to decouple historicism from foundationalism by maintaining that foundationalism inclines toward authoritarianism. In Dewey’s formulation, the modern state will become the locus of pragmatic reasoning, eschewing the deductive reasoning implied in taking the laws of nature and nature’s God for one’s guidance. If nothing else, Rorty’s admiration for Dewey is well founded.

    Ceaser identifies five defects in non-foundationalism. He does not find these defects in arguments that assume foundationalism to be true but instead raises doubts about non-foundationalism in its own terms, particularly in terms of pragmatism. First, non-foundationalism claims to generate non-authoritarianism, but in fact it has not. Such decidedly illiberal sorts as Heidegger, Jünger, and Foucault reject foundationalism as surely as Rawls ever did. Second non-foundationalism overpromises, claiming that its adoption will lead to social peace. Why, though? Would conflicts over political authority somehow become less bitter if no one believed them grounded in permanent things? Third, for all its alleged pragmatism, non-foundationalism ignores the test of real political life, providing no proof that moral and political foundations cause illiberal practices. Fourth, although non-foundationalism professes neutrality concerning religion and other fundamentalisms, its proponents really “make no secret of their support for secularism over the promotion of religion” (92). If religious people cannot make mention of their own principles when they enter the public arena, does that not disadvantage them fundamentally? Ceaser concludes, “Finally, the doctrine of political non-foundationalism would promote listlessness in the American public” (93). It is hard to imagine Rorty or Rawls risking his life for his country, if “country” is only a term in a language game.

    In the last essay on political factionalism, Alan Wolfe warns against “the dangers of conservative populism,” a phenomenon he regards as self-contradictory (96). “Conservatism in power is conservatism without conscience, and since conscience is what conservatives do best, conservatism in power is hardly conservatism at all” (98-99). One must ask, Why not? Why does power preclude conscience? Indeed, Wolfe also taxes recent conservatives in power for their Wilsonian foreign policy without explaining why Wilsonianism lacks conscientiousness, much les why such progressivism is either conservative or populist. He writes, “In contrast to the more whimsical conservatism of William F. Buckley, Jr. [conservative populism] has lost whatever sense of ironic detachment I once displayed as it confronted the paradoxes and problems of modern political life” (113). Wasn’t it Buckley, however, who said he preferred being governed by the first two thousand persons listed in the Boston telephone directory than by the two thousand faculty members of Harvard University? That sounds rather populist to me. It is hard to resist the suspicion that Wolfe likes his conservatives out of power, permanently. Leave the ruling to him, and to people like him, he implies.

    The book’s third part consists of four essays: Susan Shell’s discussion of the family in liberal theory and practice, an analysis of the relationship between socioeconomic class and political participation by Kay Lehman Schlozman and Traci Burch, Peter Skerry’s piece on immigration, and a very sensible account of America’s continued success in the management of religious divisions by James Q. Wilson. Of these, Shell digs deepest, describing the transformation of families effected by the arguments of Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. Locke makes the fundamental break with tradition, replacing the aristocratic and Christian patriarchal marriage with natural-rights-based contractualism. This move weakens the powerful families that resist statist centralization of authority while also preventing absolute monarchy in two ways. First, Locke makes the family private, largely beyond state control. He also makes the family “a little laboratory of republican self-government,” wherein the husband, “like CEOs,” make the daily executive decisions, but the wife, “like members of the board,” may “select or fire him” (123-124). In this model, “[t]he essence of marriage, in other words, is not linked to ‘coverture,’ the traditional doctrine that cancels the wife’s separate legal personality on the grounds that man and woman are of ‘one flesh’ of which he is the ‘head'” (124). Parents educate their children with a view toward equal citizenship in adulthood, whereupon parents and children become “civic siblings.”

    Not Locke but Kant unintentionally undermines the family, Shell argues, by making autonomy his central moral principle. If, in Kant’s indelible (if indelicate) phrase, marriage is only a “contract for the perpetual use by each party of the other’s sexual faculties” (130), neither Lockean sobriety nor Rousseauian romanticism will survive. Shell calls for reasserting the civic purpose and dignity of marriage—without which, she asks reasonably, what is the point of marriage at all?

    Shell makes two dubious moves, both subsidiary to her larger argument. First, she leaves unchallenged Locke’s description of Aristotle’s father as “Cycloptic,” that is, tyrannical. But Aristotle distinguishes fatherly rule from tyrannical rule, the latter being a command-obedience model for the benefit of the ruler and the former a model for the benefit of the ruled. This decision seems like an instance of the modern tendency to collapse distinctions of good and bad rule into one category. Moreover, because the marital relationship serves as Aristotle’s model for reciprocal or political rule, it has much more potential for the regime of republican self-government than Locke admits. Also, Shell describes Tocqueville’s account of the American family as an adaptation of Rousseauian marriage to American “commercial society” (128). However, the clear-eyed and somber young wife Tocqueville portrays owes more to Locke than does anyone seen in La Nouvelle Heloise or Émile. For this reason among many, I tend to resist any very Rousseauian reading of Tocqueville.

    The editors save the most comprehensive matter for last. Self-government remains the American theme, and this book culminates with considerations of three aspects of it. Peter Rodriguez considers Americans’ failure to govern themselves, seen in their failure to save their money—”the great risk to the American economy” (220). Indebtedness has not hurt investment because many foreigners who do save invest their savings here, now owning “more than half of the outstanding stock of U. S. Treasury securities” (225). If foreigners refused to lend, however—in response to a steep decline in Asian economic growth, for example—interest rates would go up, or the dollar would decline in value, reducing long-term investment.

    Who today manages to combine the lives of gentleman and philosopher with more élan than Harvey C. Mansfield? Here, he contemplates an even humbler thing than political economy—the automatic flush toilet. Political scientists of a certain age will remember the washroom attendant at the Sheraton Hotel in Washington, D. C., where, a couple of decades back, the American Political Science Association held its meetings in even-numbered years. This cheerful man would welcome visitors to “the only place in Washington where everybody knows what he’s doing.” The installation of the automatic flush toilet in most public washrooms ensures that such knowledge will be without any possibility of exercising the modest virtue once associated with it, namely, remembering to flush. As designed by the technocratic followers of Machiavelli, who preferred not to rely on human virtue as traditionally conceived, we need little or no self-government because systems designed by technocrats superintend us so minutely. The technocrat or modern scientist thus embarks on an adventure in which he aspires to replace the providential God with a new, human empire. The rest of us get to sit back and be ruled, for our own good, as defined by the new rulers in consultation with our bodily desires. In satisfying our desires, our rulers deprive us of only one thing: “any satisfaction proceeding from the activity of virtue as formerly understood, done for its own sake” (246).

    If bureaucracy becomes overbearing, modernity has more indirect, distracting means of rule. The free market, for instance, “does not prevent you from getting what you want but merely compels you to pay for it”; in so doing, it invites you both to take risks and to minimize them, and thus your virtue, by “using the science of economics,” replete with statistics, graphs, and accounting techniques (247). Representative government, too, “is a fundamental device of rational control,” a form of government that “claims merely to represent the people, never to rule them” (247). Without the responsibilities of real ruling, some virtue remains in the people, but not much.

    This means that, insofar as the American Founders wanted to resist Machiavellianism by such structures as representative government, federalism, and laws guaranteeing property rights, they set themselves up for failure. Such devices either augment the modern project or cannot stop it forever.

    Hugh Heclo wishes this were not so. The “transaction between the body of the citizens and their governing representatives” has disintegrated (250). The Founders saw that “nothing about the new nation would succeed if the people and their representatives were incapable of relating to each other in a basically wise and virtuous way” (251). Without that, both the people and their representatives will hear “only what they want—rather than what they need—to hear,” and thus fail “to learn about and act on their true interests” (253). In Heclo’s view, “This would mean a self-governing people…losing touch with reality” (253).

    With the “massive exception” of the Civil War, the Founders’ architectonic political science worked very well until “roughly the middle of the twentieth century,” when “a new way of doing politics” arose, one “fundamentally destructive of the deliberations hoped for in the republican leadership transaction” (254). this new science of politics at its core consists of “the professional management of political power” (255): the use of marketing techniques in political campaigns through the new media of communications, particularly television; the rise of issue activists; procedural openness, demanded by the activists in order to defeat the old-style ward politicians or bosses; the extraordinary increase in the scope of government operations and concomitant increase in sweeping campaign promises; the political organization of economic and other interest groups that hire professional lobbyists; and, of course, the need to raise substantial funds to pay for all these things.

    Initially, Heclo too generously says that “this new system developed gradually, inadvertently, and without malice of forethought” (259), but to me it looks very much like what Progressives and their heirs in the New Deal wanted, although the policy results might not uniformly please them or their successors. “By design”—Heclo writes, generosity fading—”the modern system works at avoiding public interchanges that would lead anyone to a closer approximation of the truth of things,” issuing in “a regime of nondialogue” (259). In this regime, “ordinary citizens learn that being politically knowledgeable consists of being able to unmask the sales pitches to which they are permanently subjected” (262). For their part, our pseudo-representatives act like spoiled children, “both desperate for approval and preoccupied with getting [their] own way” (263).

    Only a crisis will break down such a systemic structure. “Only then will we see how many Americans succumb to populist simplicities to wreck the republic and how many behave like the grown-up citizens our Founders hoped for in order to keep the experiment going” (263). No harm in making those the last substantive words in this review. I believe the term of art is ‘formally unfinished….’

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 133
    • 134
    • 135
    • 136
    • 137
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »