Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Tocqueville the Mediator

    April 30, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Sheldon S. Wolin: Tocqueville Between Two Worlds: The Making of a Political and Theoretical Life. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000.

    Originally published in The Washington Times, November 4, 2001.

     

    Comprehensive, fascinating, seemingly diffuse, Alexis de Tocqueville’s writings have long needed a guide both philosophically informed and philosophically-tempered. Ideologues and partisans ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ have mined them for insights, or at least for usable quotations. Sheldon S. Wolin does not entirely abandon his own ideological predispositions, which remain New-Leftish. But he is too intelligent and honest not to push beyond political-sectarian bickering, and his book results from the need to see Tocqueville in the manner Tocqueville tried to see the politics of his time—whole, and without blinders. It is a need many of us share, as Tocqueville remains one of those writers who can teach us as if he were our wiser contemporary.

    As a man of the ‘Left,’ Wolin wrestles his way to Tocqueville through the usual heavyweights and middleweights—Marx first of all, Foucault, Derrida—with a chivalrous gesture or two for feminists. Though a bit tedious for we who are not habitués of that arena, this wrestling has honed Wolin’s reflexes even as it’s inflicted some scars. The Left reads so many bad books, taking so many too seriously. Wolin reads, and invites his political friends to read, a really great writer for a change.

    Politician and political theorist, Tocqueville lived between the old “world” or social order of aristocracy and the new social order of democracy. Aristocrats such as Tocqueville had been bred to rule, to be political men; democrats Tocqueville observed and worked with had been bred for middle-class lives of family and business. The human soul—or at least some souls, in every generation—wants more than hearth, home, and money; it craves the wider scope of public accomplishment. Tocqueville’s soul could not fit into bourgeois life. He saw that even the richest country could not afford to ignore such souls, which, if unsatisfied and ignored by a merely pragmatic majority, might overturn decent life in order to strike at banality.

    Democracy consists of social equality, the stern hierarchy of the aristocratic world having declined. This occurred through the slow action of human nature itself, which finally lets excessively artificial distinctions rot. The number of natural aristocrats generated in any generation is too small, the distribution of them too scattered, to rule effectively without merely conventional props. Even by Aristotle’s time, just kingship, the dominance of one naturally superior man, had been made obsolete by the natural advance of civilization among the Greeks. A similar civilizational growth, spurred initially by Christianity, had rendered aristocracy precarious by Tocqueville’s time.

    But increased social equality does not guarantee a republican political regime. As Tocqueville saw and foresaw, socially equal persons with no vigilance or spine might readily succumb not so much to the harsh tyranny of a Napoleon (thought they had done that, too) but to the soft tyranny of social-welfare bureaucrats who use weak-willed parliamentarians as camouflage for a political science conceived as a sort of engineering instead of the exercise of prudence and justice. This new ‘science of administration’ imposes a political practice to match: homogenizing and minutely controlling, and finally not so much political as despotic.

    To defend a political life for whole-souled human beings in the modern world, Tocqueville looks away from scientistic materialism and toward political forms and practices that engage citizens in deliberation and spirited participation in the public sphere. He finds such forms first in small places—township halls and political clubhouses, churches and taverns—wherever citizens meet to talk and to learn from each other. He finds such practice also in the high politics among democratizing nation-states. He finds it in his special project: persuading a weakening aristocracy to accept democracy, aiming to refine and enlarge its way of life.

    Wolin is especially alert when showing how Tocqueville’s experience in French politics in the tumultuous yet somehow tedious and small-souled milieu of the second quarter of the nineteenth century illustrated his theories while disappointing his hopes. With much reluctant huffing, Wolin brings himself to admit that socialism did have the potential for despotism that Tocqueville saw in it. And, moving to a more congenial target, Wolin has no trouble at all in acknowledging the fecklessness of the bourgeois parliamentarians of the day: “The lack of political intelligence and moral courage at critical times was not due to the accident that feckless politicians happened to be in power but to an atrophied political sensibility that was a direct consequence of a long process of depoliticization.” Wolin does not go so far as to suggest that social democratization and “depoliticization” easily mesh, inasmuch as the demos inclines somewhat toward comfortable self-preservation and not so much to the rigors of citizenship, but he might. Without a specifically political or aristocratic class in place, crises still occur, but without an adequate core of strong-souled men to respond. As for Tocqueville, he died on the eve of the American Civil War; he might have explained Lincoln, that natural yet also self-made aristocrat, as an anomaly, but he would have had a harder time explaining the soldiers who fought on both sides. If human nature has produced democracy, human nature has also at times produced formidable defenders of democracy from the ranks of commoners.

    In striving to give us Tocqueville whole, and in doing so better than any one writer in English, Wolin puts us so far in his debt that any criticism seems as small-souled as the political hacks who fumbled their way through French history between the Revolution of ’89 and de Gaulle’s founding of the Fifth Republic. But even this splendid book has its flaws, and they happen to be instructive.

    Chief among them is Wolin’s failure to appreciate the Aristotelian dimension of Tocqueville’s political science. He sees that “Tocqueville’s new [political] science” has “numerous points of contact” with Aristotle’s ‘old’ political science, but he does not see one of the most crucial of those points. In calling Tocqueville’s criticisms of democracy “anti-democratic,” Wolin misses what Aristotle and Tocqueville both teach: Any regime that attempts to solve its problems by purifying itself will destroy itself in the end. This goes for both the oligarchy whose rulers assume that they will strengthen themselves by subordinating the poor ever more rigorously and the democrats who tell themselves that the cure for the ills of democracy is ‘more democracy.’ To strengthen a democratic republic a legislator might fuse some undemocratic elements into it, an alloy being tougher than any pure metal. Like so many of the ‘Left,’ Wolin sees this when it comes to the virtues of social diversity but doesn’t see it when it comes to institution-building, that is, hierarchy or rule.

    To misunderstand, ignore, or reject this insight leads to a certain impatience with, an insufficient appreciation of, the statesmanship of the American Founders. The Founders are just too undemocratic for Wolinian sensibilities. He goes so far as to claim that they advocated what Aristotle called a ‘mixed regime’—an attempted balance of democratic and oligarchic classes in the structure of the government. There is something to this, as Paul Eidelberg argued several decades back, in his The Philosophy of the American Constitution. But of course the America of 1787 lacked the class structure Aristotle saw; if they founded a mixed regime, it was one in which the people at large formed the social basis of every branch of government, including the Supreme Court. The Founders remained dedicated to popular sovereignty, striving to make their democratic republic just by establishing such ‘undemocratic’ devices as an independent and unelected judiciary, an executive who could act with firmness and dispatch without consulting the legislature, and a Senate that represented large and small states equally. Tocqueville acknowledged these devices and admired their intention and design, recognizing their limitations in light of the sectional rivalries that intensified throughout his life, as he watched from Europe, sadly. He scarcely would have blamed the impending (and temporary) disruption of the Founders’ Union on an insufficient esteem for democracy. If anything, the war bespoke insufficient esteem for the natural-rights political theory the Founders sought to put into action in the government they framed. Natural rights affirmed popular sovereignty while limiting majoritarian presumptions. Ever-wider political ‘participation’ alone cannot adequately reinforce democratic republicanism.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers