Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    The Thomas Nomination: The Principles Behind the Polemics

    February 5, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Essay written in September 1991.

    2018 Note: President George H. W. Bush nominated Clarence Thomas to the United States Supreme Court on July 1, 1991. He had previously served on the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia. In effect, he underwent two hearings before the Senate Judiciary Committee. In the first set of hearings, Thomas was questioned closely by senators who did not share his strict-constructionist approach to Constitutional interpretation, Senator Edward M. Kennedy of Massachusetts being one of his leading critics. After these initial hearings were concluded, allegations of sexual harassment of a co-worker at two of Thomas’s previous jobs in the federal bureaucracy were leaked from an FBI report. This caused the Committee to reconvene and call his accuser as a witness, along with Thomas himself, in a dramatic quasi-trial. The ‘case’ boiled down to his word against hers; absent anything more substantial than hearsay evidence, Thomas’s nomination was confirmed. This essay was written before the second set of hearings, when the issue was the more conventional question of how a Supreme Court Justice should ‘read’ the Constitution.

     

    In nominating Clarence Thomas to the United States Supreme Court, President Bush has chosen the right controversy. The polemics of Mr. Thomas’s critics may serve to highlight the real issue that this nomination raises: Whether or not American courts will defend the fundamental principles of United States Constitutional law.

    Opposition to Thomas has centered on his refusal, as Chairman of the federal Equal Opportunity Employment Commission, to promote group quotas in hiring. By so refusing, Thomas stood on firm Constitutional ground. During his tenure, the EEOC has sought to protect the rights of individuals, not groups, because Thomas understands that only the protection of individual rights can enable a people to govern themselves.

    Individuals can govern themselves only as reasonable citizens—that is, as individuals participating with other individuals in a political community. Orwell’s word “groupthink” points to the obvious fact that groups do not, cannot really think at all. Without reasoned thought, without public deliberation as distinguished from demagoguery, no real self-government can occur. The American regime of representative government by the consent of the governed makes no sense unless we accept the Founders’ understanding of it: A means for governing the factional passions political life inevitably provokes by rewarding reasonable deliberation.

    Judge Thomas’s principles differ sharply from those of nineteenth-century individualism. That individualism tended to dissolve into mere self-assertion, making reason the calculation of personal advantage. Thomas avoids this libertarianism in exactly the same way the Framers of the Constitution did, on the unalienable rights enunciated in the Declaration of Independence. Unlike a legion of contemporary law school professors, Thomas affirms that all human beings are “endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights,” and that the Constitution establishes a government whose sole purpose is to protect those rights by the means summarized in its Preamble, elaborated in its main text, and refined in its amendments.

    To understand the vitriolic attacks on Thomas, we must appreciate the extent to which today’s interest groups, ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ (but mostly ‘Left’) have abandoned those Constitutional principles. What libertarians claim for the individual—unrestricted sovereignty with no real moral limitations—’leaders’ now claim for the groups they claim to represent. Whether this is a business lobby demanding preferential treatment or some association based on ethnic or social criteria, these ‘leaders’ reduce the concept of rights to desires. To them, ‘We have the right to what we want,’ really means, ‘What’s right is what we want,’ or even more simply, ‘We want what we want.’ This sort of thing deserves the name of socialist libertarianism, which is as much a contradiction in terms as “groupthink.” It uses the Constitution to further some goal-of-the-moment, while undermining the reasoned deliberation and natural law upon which the Constitution depends.

    Unfortunately, this spirit of unthinking assertion pervades not only the interest groups but the government. Judges and legal scholars step forward rather to eagerly to claim that the law is what judges say it is, that the Constitution is what the Supreme Court says it is. Today’s ideologies compete to replace the principles of the American founding. The first casualty is the rule of law. Judges and interest groups reinforce each other’s power.

    Clarence Thomas will refuse to play the interest groups’ game. They know that. They fear it. They fight to block his appointment.

    To the best of my knowledge, for all the multiplication of political opinions, for all the ramping up of ideological passions, twentieth-century thinkers have yet to discover a single new political principle. The political significance of this century has been almost exclusively practical. We have witnessed a struggle between those animated by ideas popularized in the eighteenth century—particularly representative government respecting the unalienable rights of individuals—and mass ‘movements’ inaugurated in the nineteenth century, led by men and women who spurned natural law for ‘History,’ exalting some group (be it a race, a nation, or a class) over the rest of humanity—always, supposedly, for the good of humanity. Since the 1940s we have learned one simple thing from our many afflictions: The eighteenth-century men were right. They drew nearer to the truth than the men of the nineteenth century did. Philosophically there has been no progress, least of all in ‘Progressivism.’ In our military victory over rightist tyranny in the 1940s, and in our political and economic victory over leftist tyranny today, we have seen the vindication of the principles of justice in practice. As a result, the most formidable enemies of representative government and the rule of law today are home-grown.

    Clarence Thomas defends the truths propounded by the American Founders, truths not relative to the Founders’ time and place but true for all times and for all places human beings live. His opponents merely update the errors of nineteenth-century ideologues. Because this struggle is not over, because one battleground is and will remain the American courtroom, and because we need judges who know how to be warriors for the rule of law, the nomination of Judge Clarence Thomas to the United States Supreme Court deserves confirmation by the United States Senate.

    Filed Under: American Politics