Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Plato’s “Protagoras”

    January 25, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Patrick J. Coby: Socrates and the Sophistic Enlightenment: A Commentary on Plato’s Protagoras. Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1987.

    Originally published in Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy. Volume 17, Number 2, Winter 1989-90. Republished with permission.

     

    Intellectuals: What to do with them? With one foot in the cave, one foot out, they urge the citizens within to chain-breaking liberation, charge philosophers beyond with uncaring detachment. Neither fully underground nor above, they would rather lead than think, and thus risk a trampling—voilà, historicism.

    In ‘synthesizing’ politics and philosophy, historicism denies that philosophers see beyond their time and place, even as it holds out the prospect of revelations ‘progress’ will bring. Patrick J. Coby demonstrates the falsehood of this denial, showing that Socrates conceived something very like one of the lower versions of modern utilitarianism, commending it lukewarmly to a sophist it might have tamed. Coby thus uses history to refute historicism, showing that Plato’s Socrates both formulated and implicitly criticized a well-known philosophic doctrine, more than two millennia before ‘its time.’

    Coby fits his commentary to the order of the dialogue, beginning at the beginning and working his way through. The dialogue itself fits its topic—Protagoras, or the nature of sophistry—in being “a war of words.” Perhaps alone among commentators, Coby emphasizes the importance of one silent auditor of the conversation—Alcibiades, here a combative young man attracted by Socrates’ combativeness, in whom Socrates may wish to awaken an erotic attraction to wisdom. A combative soul will want to know how to conquer; it may not know, but merely presume, the worth of conquest. “The difference between knowing [a] doctrine and knowing its worth is the difference between —technē [artistry] and sophia [wisdom],” the wisdom Socrates may want Alcibiades to love. The sophist, preeminent vendor of technē, might easily seduce a spirited young man. Socrates would convince Alcibiades that sophistic technique cannot withstand the manly assaults of philosophy, which enables those possessed by it to wield certain superior techniques along with their superior understanding.

    Despite his apparent spiritedness, Protagoras lacks the true conqueror’s soul; he seeks pleasant safety. “Protagoras is both safe and famous”—or so he believes. “It will be Socrates’ purpose in the dialogue to show him why safety and fame are mostly incompatible.” Socrates does this initially by exposing the contradiction between the sophist’s praise for democracy and the undemocratic character of sophistry itself, which offers a technique for ruling the many, a technique that finally consists more of coercion than of persuasion. The ‘virtue’ Protagoras professes to ‘teach’ amounts to a technique of political control.

    “Justice to Protagoras is what human beings declare it to be.” Socrates undertakes to pull Protagoras away from his conventionalism and toward a low-level appreciation of nature, specifically of pleasure. In doing so, Socrates must centrally prove—not by words but by action—that he can walk away from his audience. That is, he shows his independence from his listeners’ desires, even as Protagoras, despite his boasts of control-techniques, betrays his own subservience. Socrates forces Protagoras to accept short speeches, dialectic, and to eschew rhetorical declamation.

    Protagoras accepts the philosophic form of speech, but tries to escape into the thickets of literary criticism—a move that should amuse readers today who’ve seen much the same strategy at work on college campuses. In fairness, the sophistic, posturing Protagoras does have rather more nobility in him than our ‘deconstructionists’; he at least vaguely senses the appeal of tragedy, of heroic struggle. Socrates responds by citing the example of the Lacedaemonians, an example not likely to move many academics today, but effective in ancient Greece. (Historical relativism does apply to rhetorical appeals, shaped as they are to the character of the audience. Does historicism’s desire to lead, which necessitates the conflation of logic and rhetoric, ‘naturally’ incline its devotees to relativism? That is, does not historicism result ‘logically’ from the intellectual’s libido dominandi?) Socrates claims that those admirable citizens the Lacedaemonians secretly partake of philosophy; “what seems to the world like courage is in fact wisdom.” An esotericism so effective none but Socrates ever suspected it: This “elaborate jest” forms one part of Socrates’ thoroughgoing effort to “intellectualize” the virtues. In its most extreme formulation, this means that virtue is knowledge (easy to practice once you know what it is), vice ignorance. This resembles Protagoras’ notions, with a significant exception: Protagoras only knows his techniques, not nature. Perhaps this accounts for the deficiencies of Protagorean technique; a tool designed for the rule of human beings will fail in the hands of one who does not understand human being. Poetry, being imaginative, more easily lends itself to manipulation by clever technicians than does the logical apprehension of nature.

    Protagoras misunderstands human nature not only in the abstract but in the particular. He will teach, or claim to teach, anyone who pays, regardless of the student’s nature. Socrates would redirect Protagoras’ attention to an art whose primary purpose is perception, not manipulation: “The art of measurement,” better known to readers now as the utilitarian calculus of pleasures and pains. The knowledge this art brings does not reach the heights (or the depths) of human nature; intellectuals, in their ‘middling’ circumstance of soul, cannot stretch so far. But the art does induce them to measure man instead of unwarrantedly supposing man the measure. Knowledge, however narrow, and pleasures, however unrefined, will replace the will to power, and the susceptibility to worship power, so noticeable in sophists generally—a will and a susceptibility that finally issued in historicism.

    Socrates prefers a different solution to the problems of political life and heterodox thought present to each other. By exoteric speech, the philosopher “endeavors to protect the body politic rom indiscriminate rationalism while at the same time making it tolerant of philosophy.” Socrates can indeed befriend political men—at one extreme, the flamboyant Alcibiades, on the other, Crito—and they him. Unfortunately, citizens may mistake the philosopher for a sophist and make him poison himself. The prospect of this inconvenience requires the philosopher to “confront his fellow intellectuals,” to help them deplore the closing of the Athenian mind in some way suited to their own capacities and defects.

    Socrates may harbor some sympathy for the sophistic intellectual, in one sense. The sophist, caught between cave and sunlit fields, in his own way imitates human being, with its “in-between, daemonic nature,” bestial and godlike. Like Nietzsche, Socrates sees the difficulty in tightrope-walking; unlike Nietzsche, Socrates foresees no godlike overcoming of this activity, at least not for any other than the rarest of humans. (Too, Socrates conceives of no creativity in godliness, the creativity that intensifies Nietzsche’s ambition.) Socrates and the Sophistic Enlightenment presents or suggests these issues with a sober, thoughtful precision that enables readers to think more clearly about the problem of thinking in regimes in which popular opinion rises to dominance.

    Filed Under: Philosophers