Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Philadelphia, 1787: An Introduction

    December 19, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Charles L. Mee, Jr.: The Genius of the People. New York: Harper and Row, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, September 30, 1987.

     

    To take the profuse, complex details of past events and build a readable narrative with them: popular history is easy to do, hard to do well. Prey to partisanship and pedantry of all kinds, the 1787 Constitutional Convention is no exception. Charles L. Mee, Jr. has a knack for this kind of writing, as he shows here. If accompanied with a few caveats, his book should make a timely gift for the non-scholar (or young student) who wants to know something about what this Bicentennial-of-the-Constitution stuff is all about.

    “The genius of the people” alludes to an assertion of Publius in The Federalist: that only the republican form of government fits “the genius”—that is, the character and situation—”of the American people.” By establishing that form, the United States Constitution reflects our people but is not simply a product of them. Publius does not suggest that we are geniuses in the romantic sense of the word prevalent today; he presupposes decent virtues and ordinary intelligence, both exercised in liberty. But the framing of the Constitution did require exceptional intelligence and virtue of a certain kind, best summarized in the word ‘prudence.’

    Mee more or less understands this. He rejects the once-fashionable contention of reductionist historians, that the Framers merely played for personal and regional economic advantage. Their motives, complicated and various, do not fit any simple pattern. There was James Madison, concerned with balancing central and local governments, uniform national laws with liberty. There was George Washington, convinced that the new country’s economic well-being and military strength depended upon a strong central government. There was Benjamin Franklin, optimistic, more ‘democratic’ than Washington, less troubled by such disorders as Shay’s Rebellion. There was George Mason, advocate of strong local government, a detester of politics, distrustful of politicians, who therefore determined to keep the federal government modestly empowered. Mee writes vivid, telling political character sketches of these and the other principal Framers that form the best section of the book.

    Mee remarks one extraordinary similarity among these diverse, quarrelsome men. They were gentlemen, in the old way. All agreed not to report any of the Convention’s secret proceedings to the public. Except for the garrulous Franklin, who gossiped among friends, none did—proof that the Framers held prudence and honor above popularity and transient advantage. “The newspapers knew nothing,” and as a result, serious candid deliberations could occur, and did.

    Virginia’s delegation put the serous set of proposals before the Convention. Written by Madison, the Virginia Plan called for a strong national government dominated by the large states. Mee recounts Madison’s argument in defense of enlarging the sphere of government: that a federal republic extending over a large territory and substantial population will make it harder for any one faction to dominate the others, thereby controlling the worst effects of faction. But he gives Madison an egalitarian twist, summarizing his claim to be, “The answer to the problems of democracy was more democracy.” This seriously distorts the argument of the tenth Federalist, which calls not for more democracy, more direct popular rule, but a more extensive republic, or representative government. Mees has replaced Madison’s argument with a phrase from the twentieth-century egalitarian philosopher John Dewey, a ‘progressive’ who regarded the United States Constitution as inadequate to the needs of modern life, and who sought to combine increased direct democracy with a bureaucratic welfare state. Madison wanted not “more” democracy but a republic capable of restraining the typical excesses of democracy.

    The local-power or states-rights men were not to be overawed by the Virginia gentry. Mee narrates the debate, and much of what one can know or guess about the bargaining after hours, with accuracy and verve. “Thoroughly practiced in political realism,” the Framers were “neither naïve nor cynical”; the centralist and localist factions “could not be neatly divided along lines of wealth or class.” These were political men, not economic ones. Their final compromises—basing the House of Representatives on population, the Senate on equal representation of the states—demonstrated this prudence. Madison opposed the compromise (which Franklin wrote) making him “the Father of the Constitution” in a strict and traditional sense: initiating, contributing significantly to its genetic makeup, and helping to ensure its care, but not to be credited with the whole baby.

    The book should be read with a few caveats. Mee has a weakness for polemical jabs directly more at the political situation of 1987 than 1787. Thus we learn of his opposition to “secret wars” and of his enthusiasm for gun control. He sometimes lets his sentiments outrun his evidence, as when claiming that Madison’s Senate was for the rich, his House of Representatives for the middle class, and that “the poor would have to hope, as always, that government pledged to justice did not mean to risk the foundation of justice by restricting it to the few.” But in 1787, 1987, and every year in between, the middle class and not the poor has comprised the majority of Americans; if the House is the seat of the middle class, then government has never been restricted to the few.

    More seriously, Mee claims that the great defense of the new Constitution, The Federalist, “promotes a conception of the Constitution that is… more aristocratic than the consensus of those who actually wrote the document.” However, he almost immediately concedes that The Federalist “gave partisans of the Constitution the best arguments they could use in favor of the new plan.” That being the case, then the more “aristocratic” conception must be superior to the democratic one. The most intelligent critique of interpretations of the Constitution in accordance with the Framers’ “original intent” would be that the document is better than the intent.

    Instead, Mee trots out a much worse, though more common, argument. Because the “Great Compromise” between large and small states was a compromise, he denies that any original intention can be found in the Constitution at all. This of course makes no sense. If two people argue and reach a genuine compromise, each comes away with a new, shared intention. The debate over original intent involves some complex issues, and cannot be so simply dismissed as ‘progressive’ partisans of “judicial activism” would like to do.

    The Genius of the People nonetheless serves the intention of its author, who provides a readable account of the single most important event in the course of events in America. Scholars will learn nothing from the book, but they are not its audience. Non-scholars can do worse than to read a book of this sort, especially if they read with that typically American skeptic’s eye.

    Filed Under: American Politics