Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Is Kant a Historicist?

    April 12, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    H. S. Reis, editor: Kant: Political Writings. H. B. Nisbet translation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. 

    Immanuel Kant: “Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose.”

    _____. “The Contest of Faculties: A Renewed Attempt to Answer the Question: ‘Is the Human Race Continually Improving?'”

    _____. “Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History.”

     

    By ‘historicism’ I do not mean the scholarly practice of ‘putting things in their historical context.’ I mean the philosophic doctrine that defines ‘history’ not as a literary genre, an inquiry into the course of events, but as the course of events itself, a doctrine that further derives the principles of moral and political right from that course of events (rather than from God or nature, for example). The most comprehensive forms of historicism claim that the ‘history,’ so defined, decisively influences human knowledge and beliefs, that these are ‘relative to the time’ in which a given thought or belief arose and have no necessary validity in some other ‘time’ or epoch. Whereas previous moral and political philosophy had distinguished theory from practice partly by taking theory to provide an account of permanent things—ideas, natural laws—and by taking practical wisdom or prudence to address changing circumstances (‘history’ as latterly defined), historicism made theory, too, relative to circumstances.

    By this definition, G. W. F. Hegel unquestionably qualifies as a historicist. Hegel refutes the central idea of Kantian moral thought, the ‘categorical imperative,’ then proposes his own moral system, founded upon the dialectical permutations of ‘the Absolute Spirit,’ which unfolds in a variety of forms over the course of time. For Hegel, ‘history’ is this process of unfolding. Kant himself wrote extensively about history, but is he a historicist? His moral philosophy suggests not, as the categorical imperative seems timeless, held by him to be true in any age, even if he is its discoverer. How does Kant understand history?

    He titles his first major essay on the subject Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose, published in 1784. Here, “history” means what it had meant traditionally—a narrative of, written after an inquiry into, the course of events. He argues that the manifestations of the human will in the phenomenal world are “determined in accordance with natural laws, as is every other natural event.” History offers an account of these phenomena, “allows us to hope that, if it examines the free exercise of the human will on a large scale, it will be able to discover a regular progression among freely willed actions,” a “steadily advancing but slow development of man’s original capacities,” a “course intended by nature” whereby individuals and nations are “un consciously promoting an end which, even if they knew what it was, would scarcely arouse their interest.” In writing a universal history, a history of the human species, a philosopher (if he is not a misanthrope) will try “to discover a purpose of nature behind this senseless course of human events.” Philosophy remains, as it has always been, an inquiry into nature. Nature remains teleological, as Aristotle (for example) thinks, but for Kant the teleology may consist not only of nature’s manifestation in individual members of a species, a principle of motion and growth seen in each one, but rather as an overall evolution (to deploy a word Kant does not use) of the species itself. Previous ‘universal histories’ (Bossuet’s being a distinguished example) find God’s providence behind the course of events. Not so, for Kant

    Kant sets down nine propositions regarding his “idea” for such a history. The first is Aristotelian: “All the natural capacities of a creature are destined sooner or later to be developed completely and in conformity with their end.” This is indeed “the teleological theory of nature.” “If we abandon this basic principle, we are faced not with a law-governed nature, but with an aimless, random process, and the dismal reign of chance replaces the guiding principle of reason.” Teleology classifies the end or purpose of a creature as one of its ’causes,’ its ‘reason for being’ in the sense of its aim. Its telos is rational both in the sense that it ‘makes sense,’ given the material, formal, and ‘efficient’ or triggering causes for its existence and also in the sense that it is rationally discernible. Pure randomness cannot be rationally understood. In a world of pure randomness, rational thought itself would be impossible or, if it were the only exception to the cosmic randomness, it could not understand what it was trying to understand; it could find no ‘rhyme or reason’ to the rest of reality.

    Second, “In man (as the only rational creature on earth), those natural capacities which are directed toward the use of his reason are such that they could be fully developed only in the species but not in the individual.” Here Kant departs from Aristotle, who might well concede that no one individual, not even a philosopher, has fully developed his rational capacities, but never suggests that the human species has any such capacity. Kant evidently has in mind something along the lines of what Edmund Burke calls tradition. Reason “requires trial, practice and instruction to enable it to progress gradually from one stage of insight to the next.” Although “every individual man would have to live for a vast length of time if he were to learn how to make complete use of all his natural capacity,” and “it will require a long, perhaps incalculable series of generations, each passing on its enlightenment to the next, before the germs implanted by nature in our species can be developed to that degree which corresponds to nature’s original intentions,” this process has occurred and will continue to occur, “or else [man’s] natural capacities would necessarily appear by and large to be purposeless and wasted.” What Aristotle understands to be the practical wisdom of individuals, organized into political communities or ‘cities,’ Kant understands to be a much grander, as it were collective process, albeit just as much a reflection of human nature. Kant offers no proof of this claim, contenting himself with deploring the alternative possibility.

    Third, “nature has willed that man should produce entirely by his own initiative everything which goes beyond the mechanical ordering of his animal existence, and that he should not partake of any other happiness or perfection than that which he has procured for himself without instinct and by his own reason.” That is, although human beings by nature seek the “happiness or perfection” of their nature, they do so freely, unmechanically; Kant numbers among the ‘philosophers of freedom.’ “Nature gave man reason, and freedom of will is based upon reason.” Moreover, “man was not meant to be guided by instinct or equipped and instructed by innate knowledge; on the contrary, he was meant to produce everything out of himself.” Physically weak, the human being has “neither the bull’s horns, the lion’s claws, nor the dog’s teeth, but only his hands.” His greatest natural power to produce what he wants inheres in “his insight and circumspection and the goodness of his will.” In its physical poverty, human nature produces what it needs for survival and pleasure by its theoretical and practical insight, joined to the moral character of a good will. “It seems as if nature had intended that man, once he had finally worked his way up from the uttermost barbarism to the highest degree of skill, to inner perfection in his manner of thought and thence (as far as is possible on earth) to happiness, should be able to take for himself the entire credit for doing so and have only himself to thank for it.” In this, “it seems that nature has worked more with a view to man’s rational self-esteem than to his mere well-being.” The source of man’s rational pride (sharply contrasting with the Biblical humility before a providential God) derives from this naturally governed course of events. “Mortal as individuals but immortal as a species,” this “class of rational beings…was still meant to develop its capacities fully.” Whereas Burkean traditionalism enfolds practical reasoning based upon experience across generations, Kantian naturalism enfolds both theoretical and practical reasoning, along with the refinement of the human will.

    Fourth, “the means which nature employs to bring about the development of innate capacities is that of antagonism within society, in so far as this antagonism becomes in the long run the cause of a law-governed social order.” Here, Kant brings in a touch of Hobbes, but for un-Hobbesian moral and political purposes. Human nature is neither mutually antagonistic, as in Hobbes, nor primarily social and political, as in Aristotle, but something in-between, a thing of “unsocial sociability.” Kant refers to humans’ “tendency to come together in society, coupled, however, with a continual resistance which constantly threatens to break this society up,” a “propensity” that is “obviously rooted in human nature,” which inclines both toward social life and ‘individualism’ or the individual’s tendency “to isolate himself” and more, “the unsocial characteristic of wanting to direct everything in accordance with his own ideas,” a characteristic that leads to “resistance all around.” “It is this very resistance which awakens all man’s powers and induces him to overcome his tendency to laziness.” The human individual seeks honor, power, property “among his fellows, whom he cannot bear yet cannot bear to leave.” Were this not so, human life would be Arcadian—pastoral, peaceful, self-sufficient yet loving, a long afternoon of undogmatic slumber. It would also be non-rational, never in need of thought. “Nature should thus be thanked for fostering social incompatibility, enviously competitive vanity, and insatiable desires for possession or even power,” since “without these desires, all man’s excellent natural capacities would never be roused to develop.” These “natural impulses” are not sinful, as the Book of Genesis teaches, not the work of “the hand of a malicious spirit who had meddled in the creator’s glorious work or spoiled it out of envy,” but the source not merely of Machiavellian virtù but of virtue tout court, virtue as understood by the noble non-Machiavellians, virtue both intellectual and moral. 

    Fifth, and centrally, “the greatest problem for the human species, the solution of which nature compels him to seek, is that of attaining a civil society which can administer justice universally.” The political problem is the greatest, the central, problem. If “the highest purpose of nature,” the “development of all natural capacities,” can “be fulfilled for mankind only in society” but by “his own efforts” within that society, then the good society must give scope to “a continual antagonism of its members, but also,” and crucially, within “the most precise specification and preservation of the limits of this freedom in order that it can co-exist with the freedom of others.” That means “freedom under external laws” backed “to the greatest possible extent with irresistible force” under “a perfectly just civil constitution.” This “most stringent of all forms of necessity” must be “imposed by men upon themselves.” By this means, men freely guard their freedom by setting the terms of their coercion. “Right” means “straight.” Even as “trees in a forest, by seeking to deprive each other of air and sunlight, compel each other to find these by upward growth, so that they grow beautiful and straight,” so “all the culture and art which adorn mankind and the finest social order man creates are fruits of his unsociability.” The ‘enlightenment’ of Man parallels the ‘enlightenment’ of trees; both grow straighter and taller as they seek the light. Human nature compels itself “to discipline itself, and thus, by enforced art, to develop completely the seeds which nature implanted.” Unlike historicists, who associate historical progress with the conquest of nature, Kant associates progress with nature itself.

    Sixth, the problem of attaining a just civil society “is both the most difficult and the last to be solved by the human race.” Since man is an animal who “certainly abuses his freedom,” he is “an animal who needs a master,” one “misled by his self-seeking animal inclinations into exempting himself from the law where he can.” Accordingly, he “requires a master, to break his self-will and force him to obey a universally valid will under which everyone can be free,” as Rousseau had urged in his famous mot. Since man can have no master on earth other than another man, and “this man will also be an animal who needs a master,” “nothing straight can be constructed from such warped wood as that which man is made of.” Further, only “great experience” can bring man even to conceive of a sound political constitution, which is why this problem is not only the most difficult but also the last to be solved. Human beings may grow straighter and taller, over time, but they will remain far from perfectly straight or very tall.

    While the sixth proposition lines up with the trends of modern political philosophy, the seventh represents a departure not only from the ‘moderns’ but from the ‘ancients.’ “The problem of establishing a perfect civil constitution is subordinate to the problem of a law-governed external relationship with other states, and cannot be solved unless the latter is also solved.” No previous political thinker of any consequence had made this claim; all had centered politics on the question of the regime, and many had scanted the question of ‘international relations’ almost entirely. Kant’s seventh proposition shows why he concerns himself with “universal” or ‘world’ history. 

    “The same unsociability which forced men” into civil societies “gives rise in turn to a situation whereby each commonwealth, in its external relations…is in a position of unrestricted freedom.” The resulting “wars, tense and unremitting military preparations, and the resultant distress which every state must eventually feel within itself, even in the midst of peace—these are the means by which nature drives nations to make initially imperfect attempts, but finally, after many devastations, upheavals and complete inner exhaustion of their powers, to take the  step which reason would have suggested to them even without so many sad experiences—that of abandoning a lawless state of savagery and entering a federation of peoples in which every state, even the smallest, could expect to derive its security and rights not from its own power or its own legal judgment, but solely from this great federation, from a united power and the law-governed decisions of a united will.” Kant judges this “the inevitable outcome of the distress in which men involve one another,” suggesting that he is a fatalist with regard to the course of events—basing this fatalism, however, not finally upon the concatenation of events themselves but upon the nature of the beings who concatenate. “Finally, partly by an optimal internal arrangement of the civil constitution, and partly by common external agreement and legislation, a state of affairs is created which, like a civil commonwealth, can maintain itself automatically.” Two interlocking master-machines composed of laws, one internal to each regime, one shared by each, externally, will keep the peace by moderating the unsociable aspects of human unsocial sociability.

    Kant recognizes that some will find this optimistic vision too good to be true. He lists three possibilities for the human species: that states are like atoms, colliding randomly but finally falling into a sustainable formation; that nature develops man’s natural capacities by a regular, rationally discernible process; or that no order will result, and the human species will fall into “a hell of evils.” “These three possibilities boil down to the question of whether it is rational to assume that the order of nature is purposive in its parts but purposeless as a whole.” Kant finds this assumption irrational. International anarchy and its attendant evils “compel our species to discover a law of equilibrium to regulate the essentially healthy hostility which prevails among the states and is produced by their freedom,” a law beyond the unstable ‘balance of power,’ instituting “a system of united power, hence a cosmopolitan system of general political security.” While this international system should not be “completely free from danger, lest human energies should lapse into inactivity,” it does need “a principle of equality governing the actions and counter-actions of these energies, lest they should destroy one another.” In a sense, this amounts to the discovery of a political equivalent to the centerpiece of Kant’s moral philosophy, the categorical imperative, whereby the maxim of one’s action must be universalizable if it is to be acknowledged to be moral.

    Eighth, “the history of the human race as a whole can be regarded as the realization of a hidden plan of nature to bring about an internally—and for this purpose also externally—perfect political constitution as the only possible state within which all natural capacities of mankind can be developed completely.” This is an atheistic millenarianism, one of the earliest of a series of such, including the Hegelian and Marxist versions of ‘the end of History.’ “Philosophy too can have its chiliastic expectations,” expectations that “can be hastened, if only indirectly, by a knowledge of the idea they are based on”—again, an anticipation of the ‘historical consciousness’ that takes an indispensable role in the historicist doctrines to come. “It appears that we might by our own rational projects accelerate the coming of this period which will be so welcome to our descendants.”

    Kant’s confidence in the priority of external relations among states to their internal regimes evidently derives from the course of European events whereby modern states prevailed over feudal communities. “The mutual relationships between states are already so sophisticated that none of them can neglect its internal culture without losing power and influence in relation to the others.” Initially, this meant that once one European monarch had imposed the centralized, regularized features of modern statism upon his political community, the other monarchs quickly needed to imitate him. The modern state simply raises revenues and armies more efficiently than communities organized by feudal institutions do. Feudalism requires the monarch to win the consent of the aristocrats for any common venture; modern states can enforce the edicts of monarchs (or those of any other regime) far more surely and rapidly. Once the modern state was established, other necessities of “internal culture” became apparent: the civil freedom necessary for the commercial dynamism that inter-state competition demands; the religious freedom that prevents states from the ruination caused by intractable civil wars based upon religious disputes; and education in a common language and literature that promote internal cohesion, along with an education in the modern sciences that master nature for the relief of man’s estate by fostering technological advancement. In a word, modern states need the Enlightenment. 

    All of this conduces to more peaceful international dealings. Given modern technology and the overall power of modern states, war “becomes “a very dubious risk to take,” given the uncertainty of its immediate outcome and its effect on the national debt, win or lose. Revenues are further diminished by interruption of international trade. For these reasons, “a feeling is beginning to stir” among all modern states that each one “has an interest in maintaining the whole,” opening the real possibility of “a universal cosmopolitan existence” in the future.

    This leads to the ninth and final proposition, that “a philosophical attempt to work out a universal history of the world in accordance with a plan of nature aimed at a perfect civil union of mankind, must be regarded as possible and even as capable of furthering the purpose of nature itself,” even if “we are too short-sighted to perceive the hidden mechanism of nature’s scheme.” Evidence of this purpose may be seen not in the Bible but first in Greek history, as ‘Classical’ Greece emerged from the Archaic period, the Archaic period from the ‘Iron Age’ of the Trojan War. Once conquered by the Romans, the Greeks set about the shaping and misshaping of the body politic of Rome, which in turn influenced the “Barbarians” who conquered it. In this, “we shall discover a regular process of improvement in the political constitutions of our continent.” Europe in turn “will probably legislate eventually for all other continents,” as in many respects it has done. Such a philosophic history would justify nature, “or rather perhaps…providence.” Nature, revealing itself in the course of events narrated by a philosopher-historian, behaves in a providential manner, urged on, hastened, by the publication of the envisioned “universal history” itself.

    Kant had been disappointed by the attempt at a universal history by his former student, Johann Gottfried Herder, who published his Ideas on the Philosophy of the History of Mankind in 1784. Simply put, Kant found Herder’s philosophy insufficiently philosophic—too religious-transcendental (Herder was a Lutheran clergyman), too literary-poetic, too romantic-emotional-imaginative, too organicist-materialist-vitalistic, too nationalistic. Rightly considered, the Sturm und drang admired by Herder and the young Goethe, Herder’s mentee, belonged strictly in subordination to rationally discernible natural progress, deserving no esteem in and of itself. Philosophy should proceed by rational critique (as indeed Kant does, in his critiques of “pure reason” and of “practical judgment”), not imaginative speculation. “The flow of his eloquence…involve[s] him here and there in contradictions.” [1] Herder is at once too materialist, focusing his attention on human anatomy, the supposed uprightness of the human body as the progenitor of human reason, and too airy. Progress can only be understood philosophically in the consideration of “human actions, in which the human character is revealed.” One should not stray “from the path of nature and rational knowledge.” 

    Envisioning such a history, or any “providential” history, “is possible if the prophet himself occasions and produces the events he predicts.” Such is the argument of Kant’s 1798 essay, The Contest of Faculties: A Renewed Attempt to Answer the Question: ‘Is the Human Race Constantly Improving?’ For example, “the Jewish prophets” foretold the decline of Israel because “they themselves were the architect of their fate,” having “loaded their constitution with so many ecclesiastical (and thence also civil) burdens that their state became completely unfit to exist in its own right, particularly in its relations with neighboring nations.” Our modern politicians, “so far as their influence extends, behave in exactly the same way,” bringing on such disasters as the French Revolution by their own “unjust coercion” and “treacherous designs.” And so do the priests, who “complain of the irreligion which they themselves created” by their failure “to impress on the hearts of their congregation which would directly lead to an improvement,” instead “see[ing] observances and historical beliefs as the essential duties,” enforcing a “mechanical conformity” to those supposed duties “within a civil constitution”. One needs no “special gift of prophecy” to anticipate the failure to “produce conformity in moral attitudes” with such self-defeating methods. One needs no gift of prophecy, evidently, because in Kant’s estimation the putative kingdoms of God on earth act exactly as other regimes do, even if their claims to rule, to legitimacy, may differ from those regimes.

    Prophesy concerning the modern world might consist of “moral terrorism,” the claim that humanity regresses or deteriorates over time, “eudaimonism” or it might consist of “chiliasm,” the claim that humanity continually progresses and improves, or “abderitism,” the claim that humanity has reached “a permanent standstill.” Since “a genuine standstill is impossible in human affairs is impossible” in “moral affairs,” we are left with the alternative of regress or progress. Paradoxically, it is the disastrous French Revolution, an “experiment” that “no right-thinking man would ever decide” to repeat “at such a price,” that has nonetheless had the excellent consequence of having “aroused in the hearts and desires of all spectators who are not themselves caught up in it a sympathy which borders almost on enthusiasm, although the very utterance of this sympathy was fraught with danger.” One would not wish to undergo such a cataclysm, but the empathetic spectator can draw inspiration from it because it “suggest[s] that man has the quality or power of being the cause and (since his actions are supposed to be those of a being endowed with freedom) the author of his own improvement.” Absent the providential God of the Bible, discredited by Enlightenment rationalism, Man can become his own providential deliverer, even if in his initial effort, in France, he botched the job.

    What the Revolution upheld that remains valid is its “moral cause,” consisting of two elements. The first is “the right of every people to give itself a civil constitution of the kind that it sees fit, without interference from other powers” (what might be called the moral and political vindication of the Peace of Westphalia). Second, having “accepted that the only intrinsically rightful and morally good constitution which a people can have is by its very nature disposed to avoid wars of aggression”—the republican regime which, Montesquieu teaches, conduces to peace with others of its kind—Europeans must therefore move toward the aim, the duty, of “submitting to those conditions by which war, the source of all evils and moral corruption, can be prevented.” The rights of man must be “exalted above all utilitarian values” as Europeans cultivate the “true enthusiasm” that “is always directed exclusively toward s the ideal, particularly towards that which is purely moral,” uncoupled from “selfish interests.” This “concept of right,” accompanied by such sentiments, would generate “zeal”—the passion of religious men—and “greatness of soul”—the aristocratic virtue Aristotle commends—along with “the old military aristocracy’s concept of honor.” And all of these affects would be fundamentally democratized or ‘republicanized’ under the conditions of the modern state, now animated not by the pride of the few but “the universal and disinterested sympathy” of the people. None of this need entail violence, the brutal error of the French revolutionaries. Not revolution but “the evolution of a constitution governed by natural right” is needed. That constitution might be formally republican or even a monarchy animated by the “universal principles of right.” 

    Why does Kant find this plausible? Because “a phenomenon of this kind,” the rights-upholding French Revolution—can “never be forgotten, since it has revealed”—prophecy-like—in “human nature,” not divine providence or God’s ‘nature’—an “aptitude and power for improvement of a kind which no politician could have thought up by examining the course of events in the past.” “Only nature and freedom, combined within mankind in accordance with principles of right, have enabled us to forecast,” even if “the precise time at which it will occur must remain indefinite and dependent upon chance.” All that is really needed is “popular enlightenment,” the “public instruction of the people upon their duties and rights towards the state to which they belong,” along with minimally prudent philosophers, ones who avoid being “decried as a menace to the state” by “address[ing] themselves in familiar tones to the people” (who otherwise ignore them) and “in respectful tones to the state,” imploring it “to take the rightful needs of the people to heart.” Such a much more careful advancement of the Enlightenment project should persuade the state not to ban public petitions regarding its grievances on the basis of “the claim for natural rights.” 

    “We accordingly think of the commonwealth in terms of pure reason,” a commonwealth that “may be called a Platonic ideal,” which, Kant insists, “is not an empty figment of the imagination, but the eternal norm for all civil constitutions whatsoever, and a means of ending all wars.” This is the new ‘Republic,’ the new rule of philosopher-kings, no longer directly (as in Plato’s Socrates’ version) but indirectly, via the modern natural rights teaching, now that Machiavellianism has been moralized. Monarchs, the moralized-Machiavellian princes, “should treat the people in accordance with principles akin in spirit to the laws of freedom which a people of mature rational powers would prescribe for itself, even if the people is not literally asked for its consent.” In this, one sees the nucleus of what would become ‘vanguardism’ in Marxist-Leninist thought, after doctrines of historicist materialism had superseded Kantian ‘idealism.’ Just as the Kantian prophet, the universal historian, accelerates natural progress by the very act of writing history, so the Marxist vanguard would accelerate historical progress with violent deeds and propagandistic words. It is no wonder that Wilson and Lenin detested one another, even if both were cut from the same progressive-historicist cloth.

    Kant himself has a ‘realist’ side. He does not anticipate any moral progress in humanity, which will remain unsocially social, its “basic moral capacity” unincreased, but rather a progress in law, improvements that will channel men into “an increasing number of actions governed by duty.” This progress may come from civil society or from ‘enlightened despotism. But, given the necessary evolution of human nature and especially its improved capacity to reason, pushed ahead by stern necessity, it will come.

    In his 1786 article, Conjectures on the Beginning of Human History, Kant explicitly differentiates his nature-based evolutionary progressivism from the teachings of the Bible. “If the beginning is a product of nature, it may be discoverable by conjectural means,” not invented or imagined by “deduced from experience” on “the analogy of nature.” Beginning, necessarily “with something human reason cannot deduce from prior natural causes,” namely, the existence of fully developed human beings, male and female, in a single family (otherwise war would “break out at once, as would happen if the people in question were close to one another yet strangers”), Kant posits human beings capable of standing, walking, speaking, and thinking. “These are all skills which [Man] had to acquire for himself (for if they were innate, they would also be inherited, which does not tally with experience).” At this stage, Man “must have been guided solely by instinct, that voice of God which all animals obey,” along with the evidence of the senses—an “ability, which is still in evidence today, to sense in advance whether a given food is suitable for consumption or not.” Obviously, Kant follows the account of Genesis but ‘naturalizes’ it.

    And he continues. The Biblical Serpent arrives in the form of reason. Reason “soon made its presence felt and sought to extend [Man’s] knowledge of foodstuffs beyond the bounds of instinct” by “comparing his usual diet with anything which a sense other than that to which his instinct was tied”—sight, for example—represented “as similar in character.” Reason uniquely can cooperate with imagination “to invent desires which not only lack any corresponding natural impulse, but which are even at variance with the latter,” desires such as lasciviousness (i.e., consciousness of nakedness) and luxuriousness (i.e., the desire for clothing). Kant straight-facedly intones, “the outcome of that experiment whereby man became conscious of his reason as a faculty which can extend beyond the limits to which all animals are confined was of great importance, and it influenced his way of life decisively”; indeed, he may have followed “the example of an animal to which such food was naturally congenial, although it had an opposite and harmful effect on human beings.” This “first experiment in free choice…probably did not turn out as expected.” While thereby “discover[ing] in himself an ability to choose his own way of life without being tied to any single one like the other animals,” the “momentary gratification which this realization of his superiority may have afforded him was inevitably followed at once by anxiety and fear.” “He stood, as it were, on the edge of an abyss,” but “now that he had tasted this state of freedom, it was impossible for him to return to a state of servitude under the rule of instinct.” 

    Reason thus augmented Man’s desire for food. It had the same effect on “the sexual instinct,” since a “sexual stimulus” could now “be prolonged and even increased by means of the imagination.” The fig-leaf betokened a strong “assertion of reason,” inasmuch as “to render an inclination more intense and lasting by withdrawing its object from the senses already displays a consciousness of some rational control over the impulses.” More “the first incentive for man’s development as a moral being came from his sense of decency, his inclination to inspire respect in others by good manners (i.e., by concealing all that might invite contempt) as the proper foundation of all true sociability.”

    In Genesis, God expels Adam and Eve from their so-to-speak timeless existence in the Garden of Eden. In Kant’s version, reason enables human beings to anticipate the future, “not just to enjoy the present moment of life but also to visualize what is yet to come,” a motive to plan but also an “inexhaustible source of cares and worries…from which all animals are exempt.” This is the rationalist’s equivalent of God’s curse; to prepare for the future, Man must work, Woman must foresee “the hardships to which nature had subjected her sex, as well as those which the more powerful man would inflict upon her.” Both could now foresee “the fate which must befall all animals but which causes them no concern, namely death.” 

    Finally, reason caused man to begin to realize “that he is the true end of nature,” the animal entitled to use the other animals to provide him with food and clothing, “no longer regard[ing] them as fellow creatures, but as means and instruments to be used at will for the attainment of whatever ends he pleased.” Reason also began to show Man that he ought to regard other members of his own species as “having an equal share in the gifts of nature”—a “distant preparation for those restrictions which reason would in future impose on man’s will in relation to his fellows, a preparation which is much more essential for the establishment of society than is inclination or love.” In Kant’s estimation, after all, the categorical imperative is a distinct improvement over the command to love God and neighbor. Kant thus endorses the Serpent’s claim that knowledge of good and evil puts Man in “a position of equality with all rational creatures” as “an end in himself.” You shall be as gods. By dint of reason, man wins “release from the womb of nature,” having been expelled “from the harmless and secure condition of a protected childhood—from a garden, as it were, which provided for him without any effort on his part,” now governed by “restless reason,” which “does not allow him to return to the state of rude simplicity.” The ‘expulsion from Eden’ symbolizes the dawning of human Enlightenment, the transition from a life ruled by instinct to one ruled by reason, progress of the species even if bad for individuals. In his essay on Enlightenment, Kant selects for its motto, “Dare to know!”

    Kant has in mind not only Genesis but Rousseau’s counter-Genesis, his ‘State of Nature.’ Nature fixes the time of human maturity at sixteen or seventeen years. But the “civilized state” which reason devises introduces such complexity as only can be mastered by the age of twenty-six, on average. But the natural growth and development of human beings remains the same. “As a result, the effect of social customs on the end of nature—and vice-versa—is inevitably prejudicial.” This is Kant’s version of Rousseau’s complaint that the invention of property and other civilizational customs have corrupted man; for Kant, it isn’t so much a matter of corruption as mismatch. Similarly, art is long, life short: could a genius live two or three centuries, he surely would accomplish much more, but now that it is “evident that nature has fixed the end of human life with a view to ends other than that of the advancement of the sciences,” we must live with this realization. And finally, although “in terms of universal human rights” nature has endowed us equally, the inequality of “natural gifts or good bestowed on them by nature,” an inequality “inseparable from culture,” man must struggle both to rise “above the barbarism of his natural abilities, but to care not to contravene them even as he rises above them.”

    Whereas in the Book of Genesis, Cain the agriculturist, the property owner, is the murderous villain, pastoral Abel, the innocent peaceful one, Kant finds in the need to defend property the origin of political society, including mutual exchange, the “rise to culture and the beginnings of art,” along with the need “to establish a civil constitution and the public administration of justice.” Insofar as this enabled “human aptitudes” to develop, “the most beneficial of these being sociability and civil security,” this also mean “the beginning of human inequality, that abundant source of so much evil but also of everything good.” It also meant the beginning of antagonism between property-holding city dwellers and the outlying nomadic herdsmen, “who recognize only God as their master.” Here we see the beginning of Hobbes’s world, two antagonists “continually at war, or at least at constant risk of war.” It is the risk of war that “keeps despotism in check, because a state must now have wealth before it can be powerful, and there can be no wealth-producing activity without freedom.” This is precisely what makes Hobbesian monarchy a form of liberalism.

    In this conflict, the cities have the edge, but not owing to any superiority in technology or military organization. No, it is “the seductive arts in which the women of the towns surpassed the unkempt wenches of the wilderness,” which “must have been a powerful temptation to the herdsmen to enter into relations with them and to let themselves be drawn into the glittering misery of the towns,” relieving the danger of war at the expense of “put[ting] an end to freedom” at the hands of “powerful tyrants,” “soulless extravagance,” and “abject slavery.” This “irresistibly deflected” the human race from “the course marked out for it by nature, namely, the progressive cultivation of its capacities for goodness.” 

    Civilization thus fosters its discontents. War and the fear of war has the double-edged effect of making us miserable while forcing “even heads of state” to show some modicum of that “respect for humanity” required for the degree of social cohesion needed to fight their enemies. Powerful, peaceful China, with no real enemies, accordingly “has been stripped of every vestige of freedom,” descending into “irremediable corruption” and denied “all further cultural progress.” The shortness of human life, resulting from the glittering misery of urban life, is now good for the species, lest humanity’s vices accumulate, needing a cleansing Flood to eradicate them. And we are now tantalized by the vision of a golden age, a return to Eden, utopianism, which would however be bad if achievable, bringing all humanity to Chinafication. 

    Kant enumerates lessons learned from his “conjectural history.” We should not blame providence for the evils which oppress us, nor are we entitled to blame our ancestors for an “original crime” which got us into this predicament. Rather, each of us “should hold himself wholly responsible for all the evils which spring from the misuse of his reason,” inasmuch as we would have done no better, had we been the first humans. Reason quarrels with nature, by nature. In so doing, it improves the human condition, if by means of bouleversements. Human history “does not begin with good and then proceed to evil,” as the Bible teaches, “but develops rather from the worse to the better; and each individual is for his own part called upon by nature itself to contribute towards this progress to the best of his ability.”

     

    Note

    1. Kant: “Review of Herder’s Ideas on the Philosophy of the History of Mankind, Part II.” In H. S. Reis, editor: Kant: Political Writings. 

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    Aron on De Gaulle: The Fifth Republic

    April 4, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    Raymond Aron: Aron et De Gaulle. Partie II: Le Retour de De Gaulle (1958-1959); Partie III: La Cinquième République (1960-1968). Jean-Claude Casanova, ed. Paris: Calmann-Lévy, 2022.

    Raymond Aron: “Liberté et Égalité.” In Pierre Manent, ed.: Liberté et Égalité. Paris: EHESS, 2013.

     

    France recovered economically in the 1950s, but not sufficiently to retain its empire. The French withdrew from Indochina in 1954 and from Tunisia and Morocco in 1956. Algeria remained under their control, having been settled extensively by French nationals, beginning in the 1830s. But the Arab population there had become restive, especially since the Second World War, finding organizational form in a succession of groups, culminating in the founding of the National Liberation Front in 1954. Civil war followed, and as the war went on, the Fourth Republic fought poorly. So much so, that there was danger of a military putsch led by Army colonels who had been posted in Algeria for many years, a gaggle of miniature Caesars but formidable to a weak regime. In the final volume of his War Memoirs, de Gaulle perceived “a glimmer of hope” for his return.

    So did Aron, and by November 1958 it was more than a glimmer. “General de Gaulle left power voluntarily at the beginning of the year 1946, not to say farewell to politics but in the conviction that parliamentarians must eventually make appeal to him” to save the country. This had now happened, albeit twelve years later and after the failure of the RPF. For the RPF to have succeeded, de Gaulle would have needed “to consent to play the parliamentary game,” to become the leader of a party and to renounce the persona of a national hero. “He decided otherwise, and in 1958, events gave him reason.” Parliament had recalled him, giving him plenary powers to resolve the crisis.

    Given the national crisis, Parliament granted him the power of a Roman dictator in his “role as of legal savior” to frame a new constitution. The legality of the role is crucial, although it can be misused in what Aron calls this “Bonapartist conjuncture” of circumstances. But Louis-Napoléon was an “adventurer,” Pétain “an old man.” De Gaulle is “an authentically great man,” one who “by his background, by his intellectual formation, had the right” to “claim the Republic.” Therefore, “the recourse to a ‘dictator’ in the Roman sense of the term, the desire, in a period of crisis, to render obedience to a power incarnated in one man, are not, in themselves, pathological phenomena.”

    Today, Aron writes a non-Gaullist government not allied with the Communists is inconceivable. While the Fourth Republic has presided over a strong economic rebound, it lost the empire without being able to resolve the Algerian crisis and the regime itself continues to exhibit the characteristic defects of parliamentarism, which Aron and de Gaulle alike had never ceased to deplore. Accordingly, in writing his new constitution, de Gaulle has “obeyed precedents less than his own genius.” Given the structure of political parties in France, particularly their advocacy of different and opposing regimes, “one can find stability and efficiency in the executive neither in the British method nor in the American procedure.” In France, “the sole recourse is to reinforce the authority of the executive and to limit the action of the legislature.”

    Under de Gaulle’s constitution, the president of the Republic is “not a symbol” but wields “a part of the power.” He chooses the prime minister, who is responsible before parliament, thereby linking the executive and the legislative branches while maintaining their independence from one another. The president has the power to dissolve the Assembly, to name certain civil and military officials, to submit laws to the country for a referendum vote, to negotiate treaties, and to serve as both Chief of the French State and Chief of the Community—i.e., the remaining French colonial possessions and those former possessions that choose to maintain a close relationship with France. He is elected not by Parliament but by an electoral college of 80,000 persons. 

    Aron considers “none of the articles of the Constitution” to be “scandalous in itself.” “Taken together, they recall to us the constitutional monarchy or the parliamentary Empire of the milieu of the last century.” Aron worries no more about Bonapartism, as he had done in 1943, but about what will happen to the regime once de Gaulle leaves office. As the author of a book on “the industrial society” of the middle of the twentieth century, Aron also regards the Gaullist constitution as weighted to heavily in favor of rural France, “static and traditional.” And while the constitution “maintains a liberal facade,” the “regime will be, in fact, authoritarian” if not despotic-Napoleonic. Finally, he worries that a far-Right majority might take over in the Assembly, its “superpatriots” leading the regime into ill-judged “adventures.” Might de Gaulle himself fall in with their demands?

    By “integrating the plebiscitary element into the democratic regime,” in the form of the referendum, “France oscillates between the anonymity of parliaments of the second order and the éclat of the charismatic leader.” “General de Gaulle is the charismatic leader par excellence, but with historic ambitions comparable to Washington”; as a genuine republican, he wants neither to prolong his ‘Roman dictatorship’ nor to use the legislature “to make his rule permanent.” Two questions nonetheless persist: What will happen with the ambitious colonels and other French “semi-fascists”? And can “the imperial will of the French” reconcile itself to “the necessities of our century,” particularly in Algeria, where the two sides are irreconcilably contradictory? Given these difficulties, a third and more fundamental question arises: “Resignation of the French, or renovation of France?”

    As head of state, the president “represents the whole of France because he is foreign to the parties and superior to the faction. Since General de Gaulle is not the descendent of kings, he is in the line of leaders by acclamation.” As a “Washington, not Louis-Napoléon,” he is “the Legislator” who “has founded a Republic, not an Empire”. And in any event, “neither the First nor the Second Empire were totalitarian or fascist regimes.” But while in his status as founder, de Gaulle remains in the spirit he took on as the “leader of Fighting France” during the world war, the Gaullist members of Parliament are RPF types. De Gaulle is not identical to the Gaullists. Will the real power in this new regime belong to the President of the Republic or to the prime minister, who answers to a legislature now dominated by a coalition itself dominated by the newly-named Gaullist party, the Union for the New Republic? Only experience will tell. And after de Gaulle, who but a UNR man—not likely a great man but a party man—will take up the presidency? Can such a man defend the Fifth Republic from the remaining ‘regime’ parties? And as for the UNR deputies themselves, “antiparliamentarians in opposition, they will not necessarily be so tomorrow.” If so, parliamentarism might return after de Gaulle. True, an outrightly fascist turn seems “improbable,” as the UNR is not “a party of the masses in the style of fascism or national-socialism.” The most worrisome of the lot is the ardent advocate of Algérie française, Jacques Soustelle, but even he “appears too intelligent to misconceive the difference of the epochs and the spirit of the times.” [1] More realistically, “in future years, will the UNR become a normal party in a normalized regime?” Might it appeal to the moderate Left and the moderate Right? “It would be premature to say yes, unjust to say no.” 

    The underlying problem remains in the character of the French people themselves. They want governmental stability, efficiency, and modernization, but they also want la gloire. “But glory in the twentieth century costs early and for a semi-industrial country of 45 million souls will always be semi-illusory.” Many UNR members want both a realistic policy that ushers France into “industrial civilization” and a “French Algeria.” That won’t happen. Indeed, “the political language of the French is more abstract than that of the English or the Americans,” but now that “there are no longer monarchists or Bonapartists of conviction and since everyone demands the Republic, it is by willed illusion that France takes hold of ideologies,” those abstractions, only “in order to tear them off.” While the Left remains, “perhaps, ideological, today it is defeated, it and its ideologies, perhaps more decisively than it was in 1940.”

    This “erasure of the Left” has profound causes: part of the Left “obstinately remains with the Communist Party”; yet even Nikita Khruschev, the current ruler of the Soviet Union, still the ostensible leader of Communists worldwide, has criticized the “sanguinary tyrant,” Josef Stalin. As for the non-Communist Left, it is as much anti-Soviet as anti-American, and a substantial part of its program has been adopted by ‘capitalism’ itself. Finally, the French Left hasn’t succeeded in getting rid of the French empire, however much it declaims against it. The Communist Party still gets twenty percent of French votes, but “has lost its dynamism, its power to attract the youth, the intellectuals,” remaining more Stalinist than the Soviets. To revive itself, can the democratic Left effect a rapprochement with the Communists, set a firm policy on Algeria, reanimate “the old words of the socialist order (especially the notion of collective ownership of the means of production) and induce the people of today to want that? Aron thinks not.

    “Compared to the Fourth Republic,” then, and compared to any of its main parties, “the Fifth appears to be a regime of our time.” With its seven-year presidential term, it features “a monarch invested by the people,” a Parliament that cannot remove him, a prime minister who “explicates the policy of the power the nation has elected.” However, French civil society may still lack the conditions that will support a “technocratic government in industrial society,” a society that accepts the rules of the game and political parties which also respect those rules. And again, if the regime does establish itself, how long will it last when de Gaulle absents himself?

    It took some time before the French would find out, as de Gaulle would serve for a decade, giving Aron no shortage of topics to consider. Being an economist, Professor Casanova quite understandably includes several of Aron’s statements on the Gaullist management of France’s political economy, beginning with the 1959 budget, “a symbol and expression of another spirit” than that of the Fourth Republic. The first Gaullist budget, “inspired,” Aron writes, “by a coherent conception,” indeed by “resolution, coherence, and continuity,” subordinated expansion to equilibrium in the balance of trade. Budget imbalance was inevitable, due to the cost of the Algerian war, de Gaulle’s plans to strengthen the French military (including a nuclear weapons arsenal), and continued expenses associated with the maintenance of ties with former French colonies. “The combination of a strong State, an ambitious diplomacy, and a liberal economic practice is not in itself contradictory.” 

    As years passed, however, Aron—a genuine, free-market liberal in the Adam Smith-John Stuart Mill line, although never so extreme as Bastiat—became disenchanted. On the matter of workers’ profit-sharing, which de Gaulle endorsed, Aron could only shake his head: “One man, sure of having reason against all regarding a problem whose complexity he ignores and whose gravity he misconceives, cannot put to rest the demon of pride.” Companies need profits for investment in equipment and to meet unforeseen expenses in order to achieve the expansion and modernization de Gaulle wants. They are not democracies. In fact, “the firm of our epoch is a techno-bureaucratic hierarchy.” Alert to the criticism that will come at him from both Left and Right, Aron denies that he argues this way to defend some ‘class interest;’ he insists that the self-interest of workers and of capitalists, separately or together, should not animate economic policy. “I defend, on this occasion, no other interest but that of the French economy taken as a whole.” Similarly, worker-capital association poses practical difficulties, however it may cultivate the civic spirit of the French. 

    In the aftermath of the “évenèments” of May-June 1968, when the de Gaulle administration faced down a concatenation of student protests and workers’ strikes, Aron offered a critical overview of Gaullist economic policy. Given strong inflationary pressures, the franc must be devalued, since “neither the French nor the foreigners any longer know how to maintain the parity of money.” What we do know is that “a system of fixed parities, without an automatic mechanism of readjustment brings with it an intrinsic vulnerability” as economic conditions change.” For reasons of prestige (that demon of pride, again), France has attempted to redefine a crisis of the franc as a crisis of the international financial system, dominated by the Americans, and to rely upon French gold reserves as ballast against the vagaries of the fiat money—specifically, the American dollar—upon which that system relies. But, in reality, the franc eventually will need to be devalued, since “the international monetary system has no need of a fundamental revision.” De Gaulle’s policy has been to appeal to the political confidence of the moderates in the Fifth Republic generally and in his administration in particular, to adopt austerity measures, reducing the budget in order to bring prices down, and to increase exports. “Events confirm in this regard a severe lesson: the real power of a country is measured not by its gold resources but by the prosperity of the economy and by political and moral unity.” 

    Since “the dollar no longer constitutes a secure refuge against the eventual devaluation of a currency,” “only one question” remains: “how long until the next crisis?” The de Gaulle administration’s tax on consumption won’t work because “the high prices do not derive from an excess of demand but from an augmentation of costs.” Although “the government…in my mind, had perfect reason to attribute to the ‘évènements of May-June’ the main responsibility for the present difficulties,” devaluation is the only way out of them. Politically, the blame for this refusal to face reality falls upon the President of the Republic, not his prime minister, since his own “constitutional doctrine” makes him responsible for “the big decisions” in all areas of policy, including finance. More broadly, France itself “has never understood the rules of authentic liberalism.” “The refusal of a necessary devaluation, between 1931 and 1936, between 1952 and 1958, caused damages to the French economy that the men now in power must never forget.” But by “never” Aron means not only in his own lifetime but from the time of the foundation of the modern state in France, to the policy of Louis XIV’s Controller-General, Jean-Baptist Colbert. Colbert advocated substantial state intervention in the economy, with heavy tariffs on foreign imports and subsidies of French industry—all with the intent of increasing treasury revenues. “The French have Colbertism in their blood.” But such dirigisme defies the laws of economics, however seductive it may be to state officials, to monarchist subjects and to republican citizens.

    This notwithstanding, Gaullist economic policy by no means preoccupied Aron. He remained primarily concerned with the regime itself, persistently wondering (as he did as early as July 1959), “Does democracy have a future in France?” After all, the First, Second, Third, and Fourth Republics all failed. “What is the meaning of these failings?” In some respects, the French have been inordinately obsessed with one dimension of their regimes, the institutional structures or arrangements of ruling offices. France’s population, especially vis-à-vis a Germany united under the Hohenzollerns, and the French economy—the material foundations of all its regimes—put every regime at a disadvantage when it came to guarding the peace and prosperity of France. More, “the democratic regime” in particular “is condemned, by its essence, to not employ all the arms of power against its enemies,” instead “tolerat[ing] revolutionary opponents.” Now that the monarchist and fascist iterations of the Right and (temporarily) the extreme Left have weakened, de Gaulle has had a chance to found and more stable republican regime. Contrary to Marxist pieties, the future of democracy in France does not depend on the “class interests” of either capitalists or worker. “It is the political psyche of the nation that manifests itself in the constant instability of its institutions.”  Regrettably, “the spirit of faction seems endemic in our country” (as indeed Julius Caesar had said of the Gauls). 

    “A modernized France requires a rational administration and a somewhat reasonable politics.” While the Constitution of the Fifth Republic promised more of those things than any previous republican constitution, Aron judged it to be “not viable in its present form,” given the “duality of the executive”—a powerful president along with a prime minister charged with managing relations between the executive and legislative branches—which he judges unsustainable in the long run. If party struggles and legislative deliberation can function in industrial societies, on condition that citizens understand that they need to be limited in order to allow firm policy decisions by the executive, are French elites and the masses “attached” to the procedures that will ensure such a balance? Aron doubts it. And “the combination of an executive in the style of Louis XIV and a Parliament submitted to English discipline by the will of [Prime Minister] Michel Debré is, in the long term, impossible.” Can de Gaulle govern “in cooperation with a Parliament” at all?

    From time to time, but increasingly, Aron raised a modified version of the concerns he had voiced during the war. Can this regime, can any regime, “combine nearly unconditional authority of one man with respect for democratic forms and essential liberties?” According to the letter of the Constitution, de Gaulle is little more than a counselor to the government which in ordinary times is directed by the Prime Minister, who must submit to interrogation by the legislators. But in fact, “Charles de Gaulle reigns,” presiding over the Council of Ministers, communicating directly with Parliament, and submitting laws for popular referendum. This reduces the Prime Minister to the status of an American vice president, while making the government—i.e., the ministers and their staffs—subordinate to the Head of State and the Parliament, at the same time. And in France, most political and administrative personnel are “hostile to the separation of powers of the American type.” As of 1960, “the French people have given an absolute power to General de Gaulle because they await from him the end of the Algerian War,” but what happens, once he delivers on that expectation? Will he ‘dial back’ his powers, or will he foment new crises, perpetuating his extraordinary powers? 

    Such crises were likely to erupt, given “the diplomacy of the Gaullist Republic.” European internationalists like Jean Monnet “suspect the ruin of their hopes”; supporters of the Atlantic Alliance anticipate “the putting into peril of the alliance that guarantees our security”; in both of these policies, “all the nations” worry that Gaullist policy will provide “an aid to the party of Moscow at the very moment when authoritarianism” in France “risks opening the voice of a popular front” because it falsely, but in the minds of the French Left seriously, raises the ghost of fascism. [2]

    In the end, crisis-mongering will not suffice to maintain the Fifth Republic. “The government of modern societies is, for the most part, a prosaic task. Great politics only occupies the masters of the world a few days per year, a few hours per day.” No amount of dramatic state visits, not even the development of nuclear weapons, will “transfigure the role of France and what she represents,” whatever de Gaulle may hope. “Faithful to his traditional conceptions, he thinks in terms of diplomacy and prestige, rank and power” of nation-states, a stance which tends to weaken the international organizations and alliances that protect France in fact. He does, however, “know that nothing matters as much to his glory, to his biography, to the future of France than the safeguarding of democratic forms, the only ones adapted to the spirit of the epoch, to the nature of French society.” “Liberals who are Gaullists” continue to believe that de Gaulle “has represented a unique and exemplary exception” to the rule “posed by Montesquieu or Tocqueville,” that “no man great enough to exercise absolute power.”

    Having upheld France during the war, having founded the Fifth Republic, how long will his greatness continue to serve France in the decidedly more prosaic tasks to come? And will his “traditional conceptions” of international politics suffice? In the final volume of his Mémoires de guerre, de Gaulle insists that France remains among the great powers of the world, that it must guard its borders, maintain the balance of powers in Europe and in the world at large, that states are, as Nietzsche saw, cold monsters, and so France must above all maintain its independence of action, even as it seeks a certain kind of alliance among Western European countries. He would build a greater Europe, one that can stand up once the Soviet hegemony fails in central and eastern Europe—as it must, because such a hegemony goes against the “national wills” of the countries it now dominates. Because ideology holds the Soviet hegemony together, and because in the end “alliances and enmities are determined more by national interests than by the internal regimes of the States,” a European alliance founded upon the interests of its members will eventually prevail.

    Aron remained unconvinced. Because it is “to a certain degree overheated, nationalism does not favor comprehension of the other.” This is why de Gaulle mistakenly desired to dismember Germany in the 1940, only to reconcile with West Germany in 1963. Today, “has the time of la grande Europe arrived?” Probably not: Europe “from the Atlantic to the Urals” (in de Gaulle’s then-famous phrase) is an “enigmatic and grandiose” concept—dubious because Russians may not want to abandon the mineral-rich lands of Siberia, beyond the Urals. “General de Gaulle is never precise about the date in which la grande Europe will be accomplished,” but in the meantime he has excluded Great Britain from the Common Market, arguing that its economy is still too intimately tied with that of the United States. Aron doubts that an expanded Common Market and the eventual political integration of “small Europe” (i.e., Western Europe) is worth doing, given the existence of thermonuclear arms. This, he maintains, is needed in order to attain greater equality with the United States within the Atlantic Alliance, which is still indispensable for guarding European liberty. De Gaulle’s “anti-anglo-saxons” policy will result in “nothing more than a national policy, more narrow than romantic,” although it is also romantic. It may have the reverse effect of its intention by convincing other Europeans that American guidance is “less insupportable than French guidance.” In sum, as of the mid-1960s there are two questions remaining, questions which “will be given by the future in determining the final meaning of Gaullism.” They are: “is absolute national sovereignty compatible with nuclear arms? And “is the Constitution of the Fifth Republic…the model of democracy in the Industrial Age?” Aron does not necessarily answer ‘no’ to these questions, but, characteristically, neither does he answer with an unqualified ‘yes.’ 

    Casanova is especially interested in Aron’s discussions of the Constitution. Aron continued unhesitatingly to concur with French opinion of 1958-59, which supported de Gaulle as the rightful ‘Dictator-Legislator’ of a France wracked by factions and misgoverned by an imbecilic parliamentary-republican regime. Subsequently, however, de Gaulle has made his founding into a project periodically renewed over the years, claiming in one press conference “that all powers, including the judiciary power, derive from the Chief of State”—an “extreme theory,” indeed, one “contrary to the principles of all liberal regimes.” “Such as it is today, the Constitution is unbalanced to the profit of the President of the Republic,” as it is “monocratic,” more or less an elective monarchy, de Gaulle having persuaded his countrymen to scrap the original electoral college in the Constitution in favor of direct election of the president by popular suffrage. Political life in “the Gaullist republic” is becoming “a succession of plebiscites.” In France today, “political stability is linked to a man, not to a Constitution,” and so the Constitution cannot become any more “deeply rooted” tomorrow than it is today. And when de Gaulle leaves the scene, he will leave the Fifth Republic without “a Constitution accepted by the whole of the nation.”

    Yet, by the end of 1965, Aron admits that “the first experience of the election of the president of the republic by universal suffrage since 1848 has been, in many respects, an incontestable success.” The French people were engaged in politics, not indifferent or apathetic. “Great public problems were posed to the nation” and the candidates had equal opportunities to campaign. To the surprise of many, including Aron, de Gaulle did not win a majority on the first ballot. As head of state, de Gaulle had attempted “to appeal to every party and to incarnate the people as a whole.” But “this conception, in a democratic regime and in a normal period, is pure mythology,” as “the actual president of the Republic is elected by one party of the nation.” France simply no longer has great problems. De Gaulle “has given France years of stability and a Constitution which endeavors to prevent the return to the parliamentary games of yesterday.” Despite his withdrawal from NATO and other anti-Atlanticist moves, which might have emboldened the Soviets, “the fear of Soviet aggression has disappeared, American protection continues to be assured.” Why, then, does de Gaulle in his rhetoric transform all elections into quasi-plebiscites, thereby undermining the stability of his own Constitution with his “art of creating regime crises”? Popular election of the president transfers the authority of the executive to the principle of “majority rule, that of democracy,” not to the principle of “legitimacy, which in his own eyes general de Gaulle has incarnated since 1940.” At the same time, had the latest referendum not gone his way, de Gaulle might have invoked the Constitution’s Article 16, which allows the president to declare a state of national emergency and assume dictatorial powers. That is no way to treat a political event in ordinary times. France has no great problems left to solve, but it does have “arduous” ones: social legislation, education reform, and needed adjustments to the political economy in order to make it more competitive internationally. These are matters for normal politics, not for regime politics.

    It was the educational institutions of France that proved de Gaulle’s stumbling block. Although he survived the crisis of ‘May `68,’ by calling another referendum in 1969—a worthy attempt to decentralize some of the power of the centralized French state— de Gaulle went to the proverbial well once too often. His proposal for education reform failed; wisely, he resigned rather than invoking Article 16. Aron reminds his readers, as he has had occasion to observe before, that “in politics, the French have a solidly established and well merited reputation for inconstancy.” What next? 

    Will the regime devolve into something similar to the Fourth Republic, in which a “man without qualities” assumes reduced executive power? It is true that France has become centrist, but the centrists themselves are divided, even as they were in the late 1940s and early 1950s, now into the Gaullist-nationalists of the center-right and the Atlanticists of the center-left. Further, with no one of de Gaulle’s stature in the presidency, how will relations between the executive and the legislative majority work themselves out? De Gaulle “had pushed he ‘sole exercise of power’ to a point which, in reaction, a certain restoration of Parliament and a reinforcement of the authority of the Prime Minister will impose itself.” How will that go?

    By June 1969, the election of the loyal and decidedly undramatic Georges Pompidou to the presidency portended the change from “plebiscitary Gaullism to institutional and electoral Gaullism.” This should work because the Left remains divided among Communists, socialists and radicals. The center held, along with the Constitution, throughout the next decade. But by 1980, Aron titled one of his essays, “The Constitution in Question.” By then, the Left had regrouped under the leadership of François Mitterrand. The Socialists had put forward a twenty-seven-point platform prior to the presidential election of spring 1981, but Aron was more concerned about a potential constitutional crisis. The election of the president by universal suffrage has worked, so long as the president enjoys a majority in Parliament, but what if the majority party differs from that of the President? If Mitterrand wins the presidency without a Socialist majority in the Assembly, that carefully articulated program will stall. Under the Constitution, the president could dissolve the Assembly, but if the Socialists fail to win the subsequent parliamentary elections he would probably need to resign. That is, “the Constitution of the Fifth Republic, as it was interpreted by the parties in power, suffered the opposite defects of those of the Third and Fourth Republics.” None of them assured “the stability of executive power,” as the parliamentary republics featured little such power to begin with and the Gaullist republic put too much responsibility in the hands of the executive, leading to the rejection of the president when things go badly. At the same time, Aron wants no part of a return to the parliamentary republics. 

    Mitterrand did indeed win the presidency, then dissolved the Assembly, which came back with a large Leftist majority; the Socialists had made a rapprochement with the Communists seven years earlier, and Mitterrand put four of them into his Cabinet. In line with ‘Left’ policy in Europe at the time, Mitterrand advocated European neutrality between the two great powers while continuing France’s alliance with West Germany; given Central and East European subservience to Moscow, this was unlikely, even in Western Europe, whose citizens could not help noticing the lack of an alliance partner among the Communist countries. “Everyone imagines in his own manner what it would be like in a world transformed by the relative decline of the United States, the over-armament of the Soviets and the neutralizing temptation of the Europeans.

    Domestically, Aron observed that the new president “has a mandate from the voters to fight against unemployment and inflation, not to install a French socialism,” inasmuch as “the traditional barriers” against socialism—religion, the family, the ideologies of the past—remained in place. “This year, socialism represented change, novelty,” but “the charm of novelty” will enjoy a “state of grace” with the voters which “will not endure.” Two of the old socialist self-contradictions will endure, however: the intention at once to nationalize industries, somehow in the service of multinationalism; and simultaneously claiming that capitalism amounts to the exploitation of man by man while attacking “the big firms which invest the bulk of their profits and only distribute a derisory percentage of their turnover to their shareholders.” It is rather the small and medium-sized businesses whose owners keep the major share of their profits for themselves, and West European socialists take care not to threaten them.

    In view of the vagaries of French socialism and the disarray on the French Right, Aron calls upon his fellow moderates “to defend and illustrate liberal values” in our contemporary societies “which by their very weight, lean towards collectivist organizations.” This is of course Tocqueville’s critique of democracy—that is, social equality—which exercises a what we now call ‘peer pressure’ against the individual and political liberty prized by modern liberalism. Against this tendency, Tocqueville recommends civic associations; more than a century later, Aron adds that such organizations can, if their members are not careful, serve to reinforce statist collectivism, either finding themselves taken over by the ‘totalitarian’ state or lending themselves to collaboration with the administrative state that has organized itself within the republican regimes.

    Too often, moderates have tended to go along with the collectivist reforms of socialists. “It is still necessary, when the favors of the voters return to the losers of today, that they bring to the French, beyond social advantages, a representation of the good society different from that of the socialist Party.” For, while it is true that “parties can retain power without a project,” “can they conquer it when they have none?” 

    The interplay between democracy or equality and liberty is precisely the theme of the Aron lecture Pierre Manent has edited and introduced, a lecture delivered at the Collège de France in April 1978. Wary of abstractions, Aron begins by remarking, “I seldom like to use the word liberty in the singular.” He wants his listeners rather to think about liberties, the specific instances of liberty. “Even in the most despotic societies, individuals enjoy certain liberties,” and in the free societies one must choose among the many liberties one may exercise, recognizing that to exercise one liberty often entails preventing other liberties from being exercised, as (for example) my political demonstration may be your inconvenience. Or, to cite another common habit, to condemn “in an extreme manner” a governmental policy, whether a law or a war, you may interfere with the government’s ability to function at all, to “apply or sustain the law or the policy.” What is the criterion for such choices? Liberals may reply that the criterion is liberal in the abstract, the right to liberty.  But the problem with liberty as an abstraction, deduced from the modern ‘state of nature’ theory, which requires of the state that it protect our persons and property, is that the mere deduction doesn’t indicate how the state should or can go about doing that. France’s 1789 Rights of Man and the Citizen says that “Liberty consists of the power to do anything which does not harm others; thus, the exercise of the natural rights of each man is limited only to those which assure other members of society the enjoyment of the same rights. These limits cannot be determined by the law.” Aron cannot share the enthusiasm of the old revolutionaries for such practically unhelpful generalizing. “This formula is at the same time in a sense evident and in another sense nearly devoid of meaning.” 

    “Therefore, without pretending to make a general theory of liberties for all societies, I attempt here now to specify the content of our liberties, in our democratic countries, prosperous and liberal.” “The public power recognizes in individuals and guarantees” four liberties: individual security; liberty of movement; liberty of choice of employment or work, and liberty of choice of what we purchase; liberty of opinion, expression, and communication, including religious liberties. The paradox of individual security is that the liberties associated with it (the right of habeas corpus, the right to a jury trial, etc.) are both guaranteed by the state and against the police powers and the powers of courts. “Among us, the ambivalence is strong.” Liberty of movement means both movement within the borders of our own country and over its borders, if one becomes dissatisfied with the conditions there—a “relatively rare” liberty in human history.  In addition to these “personal liberties,” the state also guarantees three political liberties, namely, voting, protesting, assembly. And there are social liberties, particularly the liberty of association. Associations do indeed resist democratization or egalitarianism, inasmuch as “professional life is not organized along democratic principles”; it is hierarchical. 

    All these liberties may be formal and/or real. In contemporary liberal societies, or personal and social liberties are real, but the reality or mere formality of our political liberties is a more complex matter. Political liberties have “symbolic value” and “indirectly a considerable efficacy in most circumstances.” For example, the right to vote bespeaks “the equality of all individuals,” although in reality a vote in a national election is only one among millions, and the choice often lies between two candidates one dislikes, or two parties one finds troubling. The right is nonetheless real in the sense that it is efficacious. Regimes that govern by majority consent do in fact preserve our liberties—better, if imperfectly, than other regimes do— as the history of the twentieth century has shown. “The heart” of citizen liberties is “liberty of participation in the state by the half-way of procedures, elections and others, which we know,” but all of these liberties, personal, social, and political “are defined at the same time from the State and against it.” 

    This causes a problem. In contemporary liberal societies “many individuals have the feeling that they are not free,” experiencing the regime as oppressive, sometimes because our society has inequalities, partly because there are so many kinds of liberty that one is bound to feel deprived of some of them. Too, the real society doesn’t measure up to their own personal conception of the good society. In other words, “the consciousness of liberty is not separated from the consciousness of the legitimacy of the society,” constrained as liberty is by hierarchies in the workplace and by the social liberties of “collective” organizations themselves, whether a firm of a labor union. Such consciousness cannot be satisfied by rearranging political and social institutions alone, or simply by changing the laws. And it cannot be satisfied by the search for and even the discovery of “rights of man that are universally valid.” Satisfaction of one’s consciousness of liberty supposes rather a civilization, “in large measure a civilization like ours, which protects and even encourages the free activity of everyone.” That is, the consciousness of liberty will satisfy itself only in civil—ization, in partaking of the civic culture. “After all, in Greek antiquity, the liberty of cities was primordial. The liberty par excellence was the liberty of the group, the city.” We no longer find such rigorously political liberty sufficient to satisfy us, but it remains indispensable to the human consciousness of liberty in practice, in the lives we actually live.

    By such civic participation, we will need to pose and answer certain questions of political philosophy, while perhaps taking care not to call them that in our deliberations with fellow-citizens who are not particularly philosophic. What is the ‘rank order’ of liberties? “What is the relation between political and social liberties such as I have analyzed and the philosophy of liberty?” And “what is the liberty par excellence?” To answer that last question, one would need to describe “the good society,” then rank liberty and liberties in terms of it. The past two centuries have seen such questions raised in the debates between democratic republicans, partisans of political liberty, and socialists, partisans of social liberty. This debate resulted in “a severe lesson,” seen in the socialist regimes.

    Marxian socialists have long charged that liberties in the liberal republics amounted only to the dictatorship of the bourgeoisie over the proletariat. The remedy, Marx and Lenin both claimed, would be the dictatorship of the proletariat, the ever-growing majority within the industrialized societies. The Soviet Union put this into practice, yielding not real proletarian rule but another ruling class that quickly suppressed personal liberties along with social and political ones. This experience strongly suggests that there is always a ruling class of some sort, that “the difference between societies is the mode of exercising power by the ruling minorities, and the guarantees that the State or these powers are in a position to give to the governed.” While in the past, liberalism justifies itself with “some philosophic doctrines”—those abstract ideas Aron views with caution— today liberalism justifies itself “in a negative, or defense manner” against totalitarianism, even as some earlier liberals of the Enlightenment had defined it “against the absolutism of a religion.”

    Well articulated by Aron’s eminent contemporary, the British political thinker Isaiah Berlin, this definition will not do. Resistance to tyranny in all its forms remains indispensable, but liberal-democratic regimes need more than that to justify themselves. As seen most impressively in the writings of Montesquieu, “one of the great ideas of the liberal democratic movement was to progressively introduce the constitutional principle into the government of men.” The then-recent ‘Watergate’ scandal, which brought down the Nixon presidency in America, illustrated the worth of proper governmental procedures, political participation, and the rule of law. 

    The danger to liberal democracy from within the liberal democracies themselves comes not from any overt appeal to modern ‘totalitarian’ tyrannies, now mostly discredited, but from a radical egalitarianism that democracy fosters in the minds and hearts of citizens. Today, “in the measure that one tends to confound, more and more, liberty and equality, any form of inequality becomes a violation of liberty.” Beneath this confusion lurks another, worse one. It might be called Nietzschean egalitarianism. “If you define liberty as power,” the claim that any form of inequality amounts to a violation of liberty is “evident.” “But if one retains the strict and rigorous sense of liberty—liberty as equal right—then equality of rights cannot be transmitted, in an inegalitarian society, by the equality of powers.” It is one thing to allow anyone to apply for admission to a university, quite another to admit all the applicants. To allow anyone to apply for admission obviates the privileges of social and economic class as they impinge upon the advancement of merit. To admit everyone to a university will interfere with the advancement of merit just as surely as the established class privileges, given the limited resources of any university. This necessarily non-universal universalism of the universities exemplifies the collision between social equality and necessarily hierarchic civil associations.

    The French ‘New Philosophers’—Aron is thinking of such men as Bernard-Henri Lévy, Jean-Marie Benoist, Alain Finkelraut, and André Glucksmann, former Marxists who sobered up after reading Solzhenitsyn’s Gulag Archipelago —have clearly seen this confusion of equality and power but overreact to it by rejecting “power itself.” For all the merit of their newfound anti-communism (to which they added a firm critique of Heidegger and other recent idolators of Rightist power), they fall into the sort of self-contradiction seen, nearly two decades earlier, in the Port Huron Statement, the founding screed of the American New Left. They would like to combine communalism with anarchy, but “I fear that these two ideas are antipodes to one another,” as indeed Walter Berns had noted in his critique of New-Left ideology. [3]

    Aron politely dismisses such niaiseries. He reminds his listeners that “there is a great philosophic tradition according to which authentic liberty is the mastery of reason or the will over the passions.” “Liberty par excellence” guides the will, giving direction to choice, as distinguished from liberating the passions, which do not, strictly speaking, choose but merely impel. Genuine liberty doesn’t make reason the scout of the passions, as Hobbes contended in his advocacy of absolutist monarchic regimes in a powerful modern state. It is true, Aron remarks, that philosophic liberty and political liberty are not the same; philosophic liberty means the liberty of the human soul to think rationally, to live a life of the mind as the proper activity of a rightly ordered soul; political liberty, the liberty of a free citizen who is usually not a philosopher, consists of ruling oneself according to laws he and his fellow citizens have made, guided not by the theorizing reason of the philosopher but the practical reasoning that asks not so much ‘What is X?’—justice, nature, custom—but ‘What shall we do?’ Shall: “civism is a part of morality.” 

    However, “in the majority of Western societies” today, “liberty situates itself in the liberation of the desires.” Under this hedonistic framework, “it is the State or power” is made “the enemy of individual desires.” Even the liberal-democratic state’s enforcement of toleration—its protection of religious practice and of freedom of speech and of the press—has been damned as “repressive” by the likes of Herbert Marcuse, in the name of “the liberation of eros.” Aron unhesitatingly calls this “the moral crisis of liberal democracies.” [4]

    Contrary to these claims, “the theories of democracy and the theories of liberalism have always in some way included the definition of the virtuous citizen or the way of life that will conform to the ideal of a free society.” It is scarcely possible “to give stability to democratic regimes” without ideas of what is just, without a “conception of good and bad.” But “the fact is that today, it appears to me extremely difficult, whether in the lycées or the universities, to speak seriously about the duties of citizens.” Against the phantom of ‘repressive toleration,’ educationists begin to impose a frankly repressive intolerance. Aron generously nods at André Malraux, who had identified and deplored this trend in his memoir, Le temps des limbes. “Like him, I am not sure that in our societies,” in some measure animated by a sort of egalitarian nihilism, “there is still a representation of the good society, or a representation of the ideal or accomplished man”—the ‘man in full,’ the completed human being. “Perhaps this kind of skepticism which underlies liberalism is the necessary culmination of our civilizations,” yet there can be no doubt that Western civilization faces rival regimes which do not hesitate to uphold their own “principle of legitimacy and their representation of the good society and the virtuous man.” While “I am not sure that such indoctrination as we encounter elsewhere really succeeds,” and “I do not conclude that all societies of the rest of humanity have for their vocation to organize their common life on our model, I say that we should never forget, in the measure to which we love liberties or liberty, that we enjoy a rare privilege in history and in space.” 

     

    Notes

    1. In this, Aron proved mistaken. Soustelle, who had served as Secretary-General of the RPF throughout its existence and who had been appointed governor of French Algeria by a subsequent French government, surviving an assassination attempt by the FLN, aided de Gaulle in his return to power in 1958 but broke with him when de Gaulle chose to grant independence to Algeria in 1960. 
    2. Casanova smartly presents us with Aron’s excellent refutation of the charge that de Gaulle had real affinities with the pre-war French Right, which in any event had always detested him and would attempt to murder him on more than one occasion. See “Maurrasism and Gaullism,” an article published in Le Figaro in December 1964. While it is true, Aron writes, that de Gaulle shares Maurras’s distaste for the regime of the parties and also Maurras’s insistence on the primacy of politics over economics, the reality of the struggle among nation-states, the permanence of national interests over ideologies, a sympathy for economic corporatism, and “the passion for France alone, at the risk of accepting that France be alone,” de Gaulle sharply departs from Maurras in his republicanism and his toleration of religious and ethnic minorities. “Gaullist France is not fixed once and for all in the Roman, monarchic, or classical order; it remains itself, but on condition that it espouses its century,” that is, adapts to existing circumstances. Unlike Maurras, de Gaulle “is conscious of the chances and necessities of our epoch,” understanding that “one commands nature only by obeying it.” Finally, again unlike Maurras, de Gaulle is no historicist. “History is not, in his eyes, a fatality to which one must submit, it si no more a benevolent divinity, it is a milieu, more or less favorable and hostile, which a statesman has the duty to understand in order to master.” Hence de Gaulle’s readiness to relinquish the French empire and to adapt France to both the existing means of production in the French, and modern economy, and to the instruments of war modern technology has invented. 
    3. See Walter Berns: “The New Left and Liberal Democracy.” In How Democratic Is America? Responses to the New Left Challenge. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1971.
    4. See Paul Eidelberg: “The Temptation of Herbert Marcuse.” The Review of Politics, Volume 31, Issue 4, October 1969, pp. 442-458.

     

    Filed Under: Nations

    Aron on De Gaulle: Wartime and Postwar

    March 29, 2023 by Will Morrisey

    Raymond Aron: Aron et De Gaulle. Partie I: De Gaulle et les Parties (1943-1948). Jean-Claude Casanova, ed. Paris: Calman Levy, 2022.

    Raymond Aron: Liberté et Égalité: Cours au Collège de France. Pierre Manent, ed. Paris: Éditions EHESS, 2013.

     

    Fifteen years younger than Charles de Gaulle, Raymond Aron came of age intellectually at about the same time that de Gaulle came of age politically, in the late 1920s and early 1930s, with a communist tyranny secured in Russia and Nazi tyranny rising across France’s border with Germany. All was not quiet on the eastern front. As republican regimes across Europe grew increasingly endangered, both men, each a staunch republican, prepared for conflict. As a Jew, Aron had what later became the obvious additional concern that neither Hitler nor Stalin much liked his people. (For his part, de Gaulle had taken the side of Captain Dreyfus as a youth, and so could claim few friends among the substantial portion of the French ‘Right’ which adhered to anti-Semitic prejudice.)

    In his characteristically deep-probing introduction to “Liberty and Equality,” the concluding lecture in the last course Aron taught at the Collège de France, Pierre Manent provides an overview of Aron’s political thought, aptly remarking that “the work of Raymond Aron is like politics itself: apparently simple of access and nevertheless difficult to grasp in the last resorts and in its final ends.” One might add that Aron’s thought is political in Aristotle’s sense of politics, animated by reciprocity and deliberation, by ruling and being ruled in turn, not a matter of merely seeking influence (as do those, like Hitler and Stalin, who are all-too-sure of themselves) but seeking to be influenced—influenced not by influential persons but by the facts that turn up, by experience and by reflection upon that experience. Aron, Manent writes, spent fifty years reflecting upon politics, “an education” never completed. In politics, there is always something more to learn.

    By 1978, the year of his lecture, Aron understood his lifetime, most of it lived in the political, intellectual, and spiritual aftermath of the Great War—that vast deflation of once-fashionable confidence in inevitable historical progress—as “an epoch wherein European politics had begun to put European civilization in danger.” “Germany made the destiny of Aron.” He knew Germany rather well, having spent the ominous years of 1930-1933 in Cologne and Berlin, where he studied the writings of Max Weber. Aron admired the philosophic sociologist’s “sense of the conflict, of the drama and even the tragedy that is the human adventure.” German sociology provided him with “intellectual equipment” indispensable for the coming “black years.”

    Unlike most German intellectuals, but exactly like that maïtre of democratic civil society, Alexis de Tocqueville, Aron detested “deterministic evolution” and “historical relativism,” which he regarded as “two strategies opposed to one another but equally ruinous, neutralizing or abolishing the proper character of the historical condition of man and his specific tragedy, which is precisely that man is neither the lord nor the plaything of the times.” Against Hegel and his countless epigoni, “In [Aron’s] eyes, history could never become a substitute for philosophy.” He clearly saw the link between historicism as a philosophic doctrine and modern tyranny or ‘totalitarianism’ as a political ideology and practice. The existence of such a regime, instantiated by the Right and the Left, proved Weber mistaken in one sense: “the administration of things” had not replaced “the government of persons”; on the contrary, persons of tyrannical passion ruthlessly and repeatedly purged the bureaucracies they ruled, turning the remnants to acts of tyranny up to and including mass extermination of enemies real and imagined. Meanwhile, democratic-republican regimes like France’s Third Republic urgently needed to “reconstitute a directing elite, neither cynical nor cowardly, which has political courage without falling into Machiavellianism pure and simple”; additionally, and crucially, that elite needed “a minimum of faith in the common will, lest they fall into tyranny themselves, whether ‘soft’-bureaucratic, as Tocqueville had warned, or ‘hard’-dictatorial, as fascist and communist rulers exemplified.

    During his long career, Aron “was, with Bertrand de Jouvenel, the principal representative of French liberalism.” And if his (how you say?) research agenda derived from Weber, his reflections upon European political experience took him in an Aristotelian direction, made him into a political sociologist ‘of an Aristotelian mark.’ For him, liberalism was not a doctrine but a form of politics that “presented the best chances for rationality” and for “a life of human dignity”—rather as the American Founders saw things. The hyper-politicism of Carl Schmitt and the nearly apolitical economism of Friedrich von Hayek amounted to dazzling and deluding extremes that obscured the political character of liberalism—Schmitt, by denying liberalism has political content at all, Hayek by wishing that were true. In Aron’s more sober view, political liberalism consisted of the rule of law (so far, Hayek concurred) but also the understanding that foreign policy cannot be governed by law, even the ‘law of nations,’ but by men, and preferably just and prudent ones; no amount of Hayek’s beloved “spontaneous organization” animated by free trade will suffice. Further, political good “are difficult to produce,” even more difficult than commercial goods because they are often intangible, matters of honor and of justice. As Manent so judiciously puts it, “Aron was a liberal classic more than a classical liberal,” that is, “not so much a modern,” entertaining no “intemperate hopes in progress or in ‘modernity,'” but instead esteeming the classical virtues of moderation, sobriety, and “qualitative merit,” succumbing neither to the madness-inclining spiritedness of modern tyranny nor to the weak and poor-spirited shrinking from political and military reality that progressivist ‘idealists’ nurture but instead exhibiting a “virile acceptance of the limits in which human life is placed.” Virility or manliness need not careen into Achillean bloody-mindedness, if one is un homme sérieux. And so Aron’s classicism remained untainted by “nostalgia for the Greek polis or the ‘ages of faith,'” both no longer humanly recoverable, but is “particularly illustrated in the manner in which Aron conducted his political and sociological inquiries,” in which he located rights not so much in abstract doctrine but “a sort of ‘rule of ends,'” which never, computer-like, ‘prints out’ the prudential choices citizens must make. That is, ‘History’ determines only some things; it gives us our set of circumstances, which we as citizens must then understand, assess, and act within, but are seldom simply compelled by. 

    This made Aron the adversary not only of the regime of modern tyranny but of all those persons, however well-intentioned, who want to wipe the slate of our circumstances clean. One should not condemn “the society of which we are members in the name of a past glory or of a regime of the future.” A ‘classical’ soul living in modern circumstances, “Aron accepted the overall characteristics of the modern society and regime.” With Aristotle, he began his inquiries with consideration of the opinions of his fellow citizens—especially, their opinions on liberty and equality, not as ideas simply but as combinations of ideas and sentiments which “orient the evaluations and actions of men.” In testing those opinions against reality, in refining and enlarging the public views, Aron showed us that “the gaze of the wise man encourages the virtue of the citizen.” 

    While Manent surveys Aron’s intellectual trajectory, the economist Jean-Claude Casanova’s introductory essay to Aron et De Gaulle hews to the facts of his old friend’s biography. He knew Aron very well, having co-founded the journal Commentaire with him in 1978. He recounts that Aron escaped from Nazi-occupied France in late June of 1940. Like most Frenchmen, he had not heard de Gaulle’s now-famous eighteenth-of June radio ‘Call to Honor,’ broadcast by the BBC from his London exile. But he rightly anticipated that Churchill would never treat with Hitler, made his way to England, and soon found himself the editor of La France libre, a journal dedicated to exactly that purpose. Aron was thirty years old, already the author of the 1939 article, “Democratic States and Totalitarian States,” in which he had accurately described the geopolitical lay of the European land. He shared with Churchill and de Gaulle the confidence that American entry into the war would tip the balance against the Nazis.

    After the liberation, he served briefly as André Malraux’s chief of staff during Malraux’s tenure as de Gaulle’s Minister of Information. He quit the editorship of La France Libre in June 1945, now publishing frequently in the journal Combat and in Le Figaro, then as now a leading newspaper in France. It was in this postwar period that he wrote his still-remembered, entirely accurate assessment of the Cold War: “Peace impossible, war improbable,” a formula which invites us to understand that peace isn’t the mere absence of war. Observing the parliamentary maelstrom that re-emerged in France in those years, he also remarked, again rightly, that the division between the Communist Party and the center-Left parties was sharper than the division between the centrists and the Gaullists, that the latter parties were real democrats, the Communists shammers. The controversy between the Gaullists and their fellow republicans was whether the French republican regime should be centered in a unicameral legislature or balanced between the executive and legislative branches, with the executive having charge of foreign policy. In this, Aron sided with the Gaullists, but only after writing an earlier piece, published in 1943, warning against the French (and not only French) tendency toward Bonapartism. 

    In the 1950s, unlike most of the French, Aron advocated Algerian independence, considering Algeria too Muslim to remain French. At this time, Gaullists were against decolonization, although de Gaulle himself, having seen the futility of French rule in Syria while posted there in the early 1930s, had likely begun to have other ideas. He also departed from the Gaullists in his friendly sentiments toward the Americans as prior liberators and current protectors of Europe against the tyrannical regimes still menacing France and the rest of Western Europe, nearby to the east. In 1958, while teaching at the Sorbonne, Aron applauded de Gaulle’s return to power as a “legislator” in the Rousseauan but also classical sense of a “founder of institutions”—namely, the constitution of the Fifth Republic. “Raymond Aron admired de Gaulle without always approving of him,” disagreeing with the General’s withdrawal from NATO, his anti-Israeli remarks in the aftermath of the 1967 war, and his call for U. S. withdrawal from Vietnam in 1967. Through it all, Aron remained an “engaged spectator” of the Fifth Republic and of European politics generally. If de Gaulle had what Malraux once called “geological courage,” Aron had geological, rock-solid, good sense.

    Nor did he lack civic courage. In the one wartime essay published here, “The Spirit of Bonaparte,” Aron raised a cautionary flag at de Gaulle himself in the form of a monitory history of French absolutism, an ambition for which many suspected the General of entertaining. He begins with a certain jaunty irony: “Since the traditional monarchy collapsed in the revolutionary tempest [of 1789], France has multiplied its political experiences with prodigality,” to wit, three constitutional monarchies (divided between two dynasties), two plebiscitary empires (Napoléon I and Napoléon III), and two parliamentary republics. “But the social structure of France,” French civil society, “was less shaken during this period than those of other great countries of Europe.” The political crises were caused by “conflicts and traditions and ideologies over, as one says today, the principle of legitimacy,” specifically, the aristocratic-monarchic model against the elective-democratic model. That is, what embittered French political life were controversies over the foundation of political life itself, the regime. A form of democratic republicanism finally established itself (firmly, this time) in 1871, though shaken by the Great War and finally overwhelmed by the Nazi Blitzkrieg in 1940. Now, in 1943, humiliated and “vibrat[ing] with a touchy patriotism, the French want to restore “a regime of liberty,” once the Allies throw out the Nazis. France seeks an effective government to repair the ruins and to strengthen the new armature of the country.” She wants no extremism but she does want unity, and, unfortunately, the regimes most successful in promoting unity in recent French history have been Bonapartist—plebiscitary despotisms, phenomena seen in many countries but with distinctive French characteristics.

    Napoléon I having been sui generis, Aron concentrates his readers’ attention on his much more ordinary nephew, Louis-Napoléon. Louis-Napoléon regarded himself as one of those providential personages “in whose hands the destinies of their countries are placed,” and it did indeed require qualities owing less to his nature than to his fortune in order for such a mediocrity to ascend to prominence: “his name” and “the circumstances” which “transformed a mediocrity into an emperor.” He owed his popularity to “a cult founded on memory”—the “Napoleonic myth”—bestowed upon this hitherto “unknown person.” He and his political allies reinforced the myth by “purely personal propaganda, approaching commercial advertising,” which included pictures and songs. As to the circumstances, the people were terrified by the workers’ revolt of 1848 and wanted a “party of order” to quell the disturbances. The shrewd parliamentary Adolphe Thiers, who had already acted as a kingmaker in the 1830 “July Restoration” of the Bourbon line, judged Louis-Napoléon “a cretin,” and therefore “an ideal candidate” for the inaugural presidency of the Second Republic, as against the alternative, Louis-Eugène Cavaignac, a capable French general, previously Minister of War, whom Thiers regarded as too sympathetic to the Left. “For the first time, but not for the last time in the history of Europe, the most reactionary elements of the ruling classes gave their approval to an adventurer against a conservative republican,” hoping that the adventurer’s “popularity among the popular classes would be the best barrier against social troubles.” The pattern would be repeated, much more ominously, in Italy with Mussolini and in Germany with the choice of Hitler over Brüning. “Across the country, the masses, overheated by a mythology and maneuvered by the party of order, assured a brilliant victory to a phantom of a hero.” More, this election “confirmed the unpredictable results of a plebiscite organized outside the parties,” an election animated by a passing if powerful sentiment instead of “durable political convictions.” “Inevitably,” the plebiscitary system “favors the candidate who appears the most charismatic, the demagogue more than the bourgeois, the inheritor of the revolutionary general [the first Napoleon] against the conservative general.” This election by the whole people elevated Louis-Napoléon above the assembly deputies, who in any event were factionalized between advocates of a social regime and the petit-bourgeois supporters of commercial republicanism. 

    So disunited were the republicans, they proved “incapable of common action, even for defending the Republic” against a president who had begun to believe his own propaganda. Imitating Napoléon I, Louis-Napoléon paraded around the country in military array; he named his own ministers, ignoring the parliamentarians—all of this “a sort of pale prefiguration of the train of gangsterism which surrounds the tyrants of today.” Captains of industry and finance, having rallied to his candidacy in 1848, successfully prepared for “the coup d’état of Napoléon III” in 1852, an event staged in the name of nothing less than republicanism. “Louis-Napoléon, like all plebiscitary chiefs, is in a sense the substitute for a monarch.” But not the traditional, dynastic monarch he invoked “revolutionary dogmas (national sovereignty, civil equality, property) combined with the defense of order and social stability.” Thus was effected “the transformation of an unknown émigré” into the “emperor of France.” 

    De Gaulle’s friends in exile may be excused for suspecting that Aron implied in all of this any number of resemblances, real and potential, to de Gaulle himself, especially as Aron went on to consider the career of Georges Ernest Boulanger, another Bonapartist (though not himself a Bonaparte), whose fervent nationalism, expressed in his calls for the recovery of the provinces of Alsace and Lorraine, which France had lost in its war with Prussia, earned him the title “General Révanche.” Thiers was gone, but Boulanger had another parliamentary maneuverer, Georges Clemenceau, as his sponsor, early on. The American president, Franklin Roosevelt, indeed compared de Gaulle to Boulanger at this time, so the thought was in the air.

    Aron identifies five conditions in which such plebiscitary dictators arise. First, in France, when “the popularity of a man is simply the popularity of a name; ‘Bonaparte’ was associated with national self-respect. To this, add “nostalgia for a certain reconciliation between the heritage of revolutionary romanticism and the stabilization of the established order.” Almost no one in France outside the Army and French ruling circles knew de Gaulle, either, but his speeches in London had brought popularity to his name. Second, the bourgeois classes may rally to the new ‘Caesar’ because they fear social troubles (the Communist Party was the most powerful party in wartime France, organizing much of the underground resistance to Nazi rule) and in light of the impossibility of a monarchic restoration (given the “dynastic disunion” between Bourbons and Orléanists). The third condition of Bonapartism or Caesarism is disdain, sometimes earned, of the parliament. Crucially, in France “the Republic and democracy” are terms that “express rather a certain sentimentality or a certain revolutionary ideology than a choice decided in favor of determined methods of deliberation and government.” The French of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries bore little resemblance to the Americans of 1776-1800. Fourth, Bonapartism thrives when republicans and the French people themselves are divided but long for unity. And finally there are the chances offered by the plebiscitary system of election itself, which (as Louis-Napoléon had shown) lends itself to an eventual coup d’état. 

    Boulanger enjoyed a similar set of circumstances. As a general, then Minister of War in 1885, he’d established himself as a friend of social order. He had some parliamentary support, especially among the Radical Party of Clemenceau. He shrewdly proposed to exclude the military and military families from rule, thus appealing to the Left and turning on his old military chief, Henri d’Orléans, the Duke of Aumale—a likely parallel to de Gaulle’s break with his patron, the great (if now much-diminished) Philippe Pétain, who had lost credit with many of his countrymen by agreeing to head the puppet government headquartered in Vichy, in southern France. The reforms Boulanger had introduced into the army had enhanced his popularity (even as de Gaulle’s advocacy of tank warfare, against the French military establishment in the 1930s, had given him credit after the Maginot Line was breached in 1940). Boulanger effectively played on révanchist sentiments, as of course de Gaulle was quite rightly doing; his propaganda was similar to that of Louis-Napoléon, with its “advertisements like those of American commerce”; he had ‘evolved’ from Left to Right; and he wanted “a strong government” (by which Aron means an executive branch) to balance the parliament, as indeed de Gaulle now wanted. And, in a sentence that must have deeply offended the Gaullists, “Like Hitler never ceasing to denounce the ‘system’ of Weimar, the Boulangerists reprimanded the republican personnel and regime,” rulers who had acceded, Hitler charged, to “the scandal of Wilson”—that is, the Versailles Treaty, its terms understandably hated by Germans—and who had indulged in “factional quarrels” without vindicating the national honor. 

    Unlike 1849 and 1851, however, in 1889 the parliamentarians were alert to the danger. And Boulanger was by then only a Parisian parliamentarian, not a president of the Republic, as Louis-Napoléon had been when he staged his coup. Boulanger amounted to little more than a “Caesar of the music-hall,” a point that illustrates “the fragility of these brilliant popularities.” Gaullists, take note? They would surely take offense, and did.

    Aron then asks, are Bonapartism and fascism “specimens of the same genre”? Not really. The Second Empire established itself in a period of economic prosperity, not depression. The Bonapartists were supported by small peasant proprietors, defending their landed property; what Tocqueville calls democracy, social egalitarianism, was the heritage of the Revolution, which by now had replaced aristocratic and Church hierarchies, as indeed Marx observed at the time. This, indeed, is what made the political device of plebiscitary election feasible and appealing. By now, too, there were many more city-dwellers, including some petit-bourgeois many artisans, and “even workers” who thrilled to the myth of the charismatic leader, the national hero leading to mass mobilization. Several of these features did indeed resemble the circumstances in which fascism arose, and in nineteenth-century France, as in twentieth-century Italy and Germany, “Popular Caesarism” became possible due to an alliance of a part of the bourgeoisie and a part of the proletariat against dynastic monarchy and against the “menace to the social order” posed by the Left. Still, the comparative extremism of the later fascists was fostered by an economic desperation not seen in France. The French were responding to “social troubles and the weaknesses of all the constitutions” they had seen in previous decades. The fascists exploited economic as well as political crisis, and that made them more radical, more dangerous. In France, it was regime instability that caused “the desire for a strong power, incarnated in one man,” a longing for “unity of sentiment,” in the phrase of the celebrated writer, Maurice Barrès. What occurred in mid-nineteenth century France, was “the anticipation of and the French version of fascism” but never the thing itself. 

    “Uncertain of his rights and his fortune, the Caesar is unceasingly pushed toward new enterprises by the insatiable need of renewing the source of his authority, of refreshing the favor if his own people.” Hence Napoléon III’s vain march against Germany, resulting in the catastrophic defeat at Sedan in 1871. “As in so many times in history, the adventure of a man ended in tragedy for a nation.” 

    Three years later, Aron looked upon de Gaulle with much more confidence, having observed his decidedly republican, not Bonapartist, policies during the war and its immediate aftermath. In June 1946, the fifth anniversary of de Gaulle’s now-famous radio “appeal” to the French from London, de Gaulle had given a speech in Bayeux, advocating a new constitution in which the executive branch would have independence from the legislative branch—this, to remedy the foreign-policy imbecility repeatedly demonstrated by the parliament-centered and factionalized Third Republic. This speech, Aron wrote, “manifestly pursues a higher ambition” than the resolution of some immediate crisis; de Gaulle aims “to influence the evolution of the political crisis in which the French nation is floundering,” the “central theme” being “that of a State worthy of the name.” “The thought of General de Gaulle is manifestly dominated by one major care: How to prevent the State, torn between rival ambitions, not to disaggregate to the point that the country has only the choice between anarchy and a tyranny.” Such an ambition and such a thought obviously elevated de Gaulle well above a Louis-Philippe, to say nothing of a Boulanger.

    Such a reform was urgently needed. “The politicization of l’existence Française—economics, administration, literature—has progressed in a manner recalling the last years of the Weimar Republic.” The supposedly apolitical administrative state itself has been politicized, as well, as the cabinet offices have been divided among the three major parties (republican, democratic-socialist, and communist). “Such a regime, by definition, can offer no promise of stability.” In his proposal for a president installed by a large electoral college, not just the National Assembly, de Gaulle would establish an element within the State that is above the parties, an element which “takes account of the national interests in their continuity.” This “decisive idea, which provokes the most criticisms,” would take executive power out of the hands of party leaders. The president, “foreign to partisan conflicts, would be the equitable arbiter” among them, attending to “the general interest” of the French nation—impartial “with regard to all groups and organizations, passionate only for France and her grandeur.” 

    De Gaulle’s proposed constitution is undeniably republican, but is it presidential or parliamentary? The president names the ministers but do the ministers report to the Assembly (as in Britain) or to the president (as in the United States)? Aron says it does neither, that it isn’t inspired by “the Anglo-Saxon democracies” at all. In them, “the stability of the executive” is “rooted in a traditional principle, between the system of two parties and the constitutional mechanism.” In Britain, socialists and conservatives tend to agree on British national interests, especially in foreign policy; in America, the same attitude prevails among Democrats and Republicans (as it did at the end of the Second World War, very much in contrast to the end of the First World War). But in France, as noted, the parties are ‘regime’ parties; France needs the model of the arbiter-executive to a degree that the “Anglo-Saxon democracies” do not. De Gaulle intends thereby to counterbalance “the regime of the parties,” which consists of a regime that cannot actually rule because they each attract substantial voting blocs but share scarcely any conception of what France should be and do. Although de Gaulle’s critics decry his Constitution as undemocratic, true defenders of democracy, Aron insists, want a regime that functions. 

    Against this proposal, the National Assembly had proposed a constitution similar to that of the Third Republic. This merely “codifies and prolongs the current practice without seriously modifying it, the practice of parliamentarism under its present form, that is, the regime of the parties.” De Gaulle’s proposed constitution instead “requires the parties to renounce one part of the power they retain” from the pre-war regime. In so doing, he has consulted “History and the experience it gives to reason,” rather than assuming that the course of history itself must be rational, as Marxists of both the democratic and the Leninist stripe do. In doing so, Aron now sees, de Gaulle’s Bayeux speech “conforms to the ‘style’ of June 18th [1940].” “I am not sure, on my account, that this ’18th of June strategy’ will suffice in the present situation,” in which all the major French parties had been oppressed by the Nazis, united against a common enemy, but it is true that a constitution with an “omnipotent Assembly” and a precedent and cabinet “without real authority” will fail. Against all suspicions of Gaullist Bonapartism, Aron now remarked that the General had in fact exhibited “a sense of the authority of the State, and of respect for legality”; he “has the demeanor of a legitimate sovereign, not of a usurper or a tyrant.” True, he advocates a Constitution with a strong executive, but both the American president and the former German Reich Chancellor did that, and “can one really think that Roosevelt and Hitler were leaders of the same species?” He has “rejected the formulas of presidential power and personal power,” affirming instead “the separation and balance of powers.” “General de Gaulle is not Marshall Pétain.”

    The problem with de Gaulle’s proposal is not some alleged despotic intent but its current feasibility. Admittedly, the Bayeux Constitution is “perfectly legitimate on the plane of History,” but on the level of “political struggle” in today’s France it provokes “stirrings that are difficult to foresee that are not all favorable.” During the war, de Gaulle was in accord “with the sentiment of the people,” but now, in 1946, such unity of sentiment is no longer possible. “When General de Gaulle demands a homogeneous government, one well knows he has good reason in theory, but one can ask how a nation so profoundly divided as ours can have a unified government.” In the event, the Constitution for the Fourth Republic, ratified in October, reprised the parliamentary republicanism of the Third Republic, with the three major parties firmly in control of the executive.

    Why so? In the United States, a Democratic Party president, Harry Truman can collaborate with a Republican-controlled Congress on many policy decisions. That is because the United States Constitution is “rooted in the habits and national convictions” of Americans. And so, given a perceived common threat, Soviet Communism, American foreign policy will not return to the “isolationism” of the 1930s. Similarly, under Great Britain’s unwritten constitution, a “homogeneous” parliamentary majority supports the Prime Minister. But in France, with its more tortured recent political history, which has spawned ‘regime’ parties, the parties “paralyze the public powers”; even when an executive administration or “government” has been formed, it is a coalition government in which “communists, socialists, and republicans continue their quarrel while feigning to collaborate.” The unspoken underlying dilemma is that one of the major parties, the Communists, do regard the Soviet Union not as a common enemy but as an ally. While the Gaullist presidency would “surmount this impotent union,” the parties are not unhappy with it. “If the Fourth Republic is endangered by dictatorship, it is not because General de Gaulle enjoys great popularity with his ideas on the organization of the State, it is because the coalitions, which pass for inevitable, are revealed to be impotent.” Under such conditions, a real ‘dictator’ might arise to deal with the next major crisis—whatever and whenever that might be. 

    Given this danger, simultaneous with the regime of parliamentary republicanism which has left France in it, and given the rejection of de Gaulle’s constitution, what is to be done? “The current crisis amounts to givens that are simple to define but difficult to modify,” namely, the choice between government by a minority party or government by a coalition of two or more minority parties. “In the abstract, the first, thanks to its homogeneity, works better. Meanwhile, the economic and financial crisis continues to worsen. It can be met, but the political system prevents it, thanks to “the game of the regime.” 

    By the end of November 1946, de Gaulle had refused to serve under the new constitution, breaking with the centrist parliamentary republicans with whom he had allied. Aron sympathized. Admittedly, “the life of parties cannot be separated from democratic realities,” and anti-democratic regime cause “the reduction of the parties to a unity, the identification of one party and one credo with the state which simultaneously, extends its faction to infinity and augments its authority with the prestige of a pretended absolute truth”—a form of tyranny Mussolini himself named ‘totalitarianism,’ a “confusion of the temporal and the spiritual.” [1] But in France, on the level of civil society, the regime consists of “the masses and their organizations” or civil associations. Under these conditions, it is “difficult to safeguard independence, the capacity of decision” that the “public powers” must maintain, pressured as they are by these organized “social groups.” That is, the political paralysis of the regime of the parties has a civil-social foundation that makes that regime possible and hard to dislodge or to reform. further, in that civil society, and therefore in that regime, there is a “totalitarian party,” the Communist Party, which uses “democratic methods” in an attempt “to found a regime in which it will rule alone it, it and its secular religion and its partisan State.” This is “the fundamental crisis” in France, owing in part to the fact that de Gaulle’s constitution was rejected and “the Fourth Republic exists.” It means that the parties’ “most redoubtable enemy is not outside but within themselves.” 

    In April 1947, de Gaulle announced the formation of the Rassemblement du Peuple Français, a movement that amounted to a party against the regime of the parties, a party that aimed at the more nearly presidential, balanced-power republic enunciated in the Bayeux Manifesto. The leaders of the existing parties were quick to express their contempt, a contempt that may have been more affected than real. “Solidly entrenched in their fiefs, the parties must become well assured of their lot and disdain the words of a man who has no other arms than his past and his prestige.” But in reality, “the new regime” of the Fourth Republic “lacks confidence in itself and in the future.” The parties fear the Gaullist movement because they understand, ‘from the inside,’ their own vulnerability. “The Fourth Republic is founded on compromise between incompatible ideas, on the collaboration between parties which always try to continue their fight and govern in common.” Obviously, there can be no “moral unity” or “unity of action” between communists and non-communists without “a common enemy,” as there was during the Nazi Occupation. “The “true dilemma of France is this “coalition of contraries, vegetating in mediocrity and at every instant menaced by paralysis” or by ‘civil war and recourse to authoritarian methods” that would be necessary to end that war, at the expense of the regime of the parties. 

    There might be a remedy for this dilemma within the legal framework of the Fourth Republic, Aron hopefully suggests. Potentially, there is a majority of democratic-republicans who, “on condition that they surmount the secondary and anachronistic quarrels, can give life back to parliament and restore the distinction, indispensable in democracy, of the majority and the opposition without such a regrouping” of the parties, “no such regime will be viable.” The only thing they currently agree on is the supposed danger to the Republic de Gaulle poses, but de Gaulle, Aron calmly observes, has respected the rule of law. One may not be entitled to condemn parties in a democracy, inasmuch as they are inevitable in any regime of liberty, but one can surely condemn a regime of “rival parties incapable of a sustained and coherent policy.” “In truth, there can scarcely be doubt about the justice of [de Gaulle’s] critique. The real question is another. What means can emerge?” That is, how can a democratic republican regime overcome the results of serious party factionalism? 

    Aron recommends that the centrist party, the Mouvement Républicain Populaire, and the Socialist Party disavow collection with the Communist Party and rule as a majority—in effect forming a true ‘popular front,’ inasmuch as genuine democrats really do have enemies on the Left. This would solve, or at least ameliorate, the problem in terms consistent with the parliamentary republicanism of the Fourth Republic.  De Gaulle’s “attacks on the [Fourth Republic’s] Constitution risk the formation, against the danger of ‘personal power,’ of an artificial and sterile solidarity between the rival parties and to add one more quarrel to those we already have.” “For better or for worse, the Parliament reflects the country: there is hardly more unity in the one than in the other,” since “our official divisions are linked to the past” regime struggles.  France as it is today simply will not adopt de Gaulle’s constitution, although it is within the democratic “cadre” of regimes. It is “vain to invoke a fictional unity.” 

    Aron also does not share de Gaulle’s conviction that “it is necessary to reconstruct Europe as a neutral zone established between the giant empires.” Nor does he think that it is possible to establish a socio-economic system between communism and capitalism—de Gaulle’s conception, drawn from Catholic social thought prior to the First World War, of labor-capital ‘association.’ In both his foreign and domestic policy proposals, “I fear that the president of the RPF fishes with optimism.” As of now, April 1947, “the evolution of our politics depends less on the French and their words than on the world and its tragic conflicts,” no matter how much de Gaulle, and not only de Gaulle, may detest that reality.

    By July, Aron had become editor of Le Figaro. In its pages, he published a careful analysis of the French political situation. The Socialist prime minister had excluded Communist Party member from the government—a hopeful sign. The partisan constellation was now configured with the Communists on the left, the MRP and the Socialists in the center, and the Gaullists on the right. Under the Constitution (recently adopted in a third referendum), “the Assembly is sovereign, but it does not encroach upon the prerogatives of the government.” Nonetheless, the executive powers themselves are weak. As a result, “the Constitution functions badly, but the faults experience has revealed are not exactly those which the critic,” de Gaulle, “passionately denounced in advance.” The second chamber, the Council of the Republic, has withered because both the Communists and the Socialists prefer unicameralism; it had little legal authority, anyway, and now has little moral authority, either. Having taken all responsibility for itself, the Assembly has acted irresponsibly, failing to address the major issues confronting France—import policy and the Monnet Plan (the first fruit of postwar French economic central planning which sought to modernize the French economy by increasing productivity), foreign trade, and foreign investment under the dirigisme of Jean Monnet’s General Planning Commission. More, the Assembly members have failed even to “accomplish their traditional tasks” of ordinary legislation. Aron wants to see an orderly governing process, whereby the governmental ministers conceive and apply a program, the Assembly members “attend thoughtfully to the quality of the laws,” and the administrators perform the “essentially technical” task of carrying out those laws at the direction of the ministers, the “government.” Unfortunately, the instability of the governments, dominated by the Assembly, prevents them from performing their duties, while the Assembly members lack the “competence and interest” to perform the executive and technical tasks. This leaves technical matters to administrators, unsupervised and the political matters to the groups that pressure the Assembly. No real deliberation occurs in the legislative branch. “How can one be surprised that Parliament falls, little by little,” in prestige?

    In reality, then, “France is governed by the administration.” The “great functionaries” in the bureaucracies hold “a considerable part of the real power.” The parties distribute ministerial posts, but the civil-social pressure groups (Aron calls them “syndicates”) can obstruct them when the parties appear to act “contrary to their interests.” This “transfer of power from assemblies to the administration is neither a new phenomenon nor an exclusively French phenomenon. It is the fated result of the increasingly ample capture [of power] of the State” by administrators. “Only the administration has the competence and the continuity”—given the short life of governments and of parliamentary coalitions—that is “necessary for directing and orienting the economy of the nation.” Characteristically, the moderate Aron regards this as “not a question of rebelling against an irreversible evolution” but “a matter of adapting old institutions to the new tasks, of asking oneself in what condition such a regime will be effective.” Because administrative rule alone won’t work, either. “Left to itself, administration becomes at once arbitrary and impotent,” as seen in “the sclerosis of our army” between the world wars. And when government ministers attempt to ‘politicize’ the administration, “one does not have the impression that the government knows better than [popular] opinion,” that it refines and enlarges the public views, or that it even has the force or the courage to execute its decisions in the face not so much of administrative recalcitrance as pressure-group opposition. “Government, parties, administration, syndicates tolerate one another reciprocally. Unfortunately, their complex relations achieve not action but disorder and paralysis.”

    In twentieth-century “mass societies,” the “same problems appear—namely workers and leaders of enterprise organize themselves into syndicates” in an attempt to influence the vast and complicated apparatus of the modern state. How can such societies “establish the necessary collaboration between the syndicates, on the one hand, and the State on the other,” especially given the emergence of state bureaucracy or administration as effectively a fourth branch of power? And how can modern states under democratic-republican regimes, with governments representing the popular will, “maintain the sense of the national interest, if they represent particular interests of social groups and political parties”?

    The “totalitarian regimes give a brutal, primitive response” to such questions. “Reserving to one party the exclusive right to political action, integrating into the State all the particular groups, in creating a monopoly of ideology and propaganda, they suppress the problems rather than solving them. It is good to denounce this barbaric simplification. Now one must find a solution The Fourth Republic has not resolved these problems. To speak truly it has not even posed them or thought about them.”

    De Gaulle and his “Rassemblement” have thought about them. But if “all the French were Gaullists in 1944,” only “forty percent of the electors voted for the RPF in October 1947.” In 1944, Gaullism had become “the symbol and the guide of the nation in combat,” de Gaulle an arbiter, neither partisan nor doctrinaire. Now, the RPF is “the first party of France,” but still a party. The “three great parties” reorganized themselves “under the shadow of Gaullism” in the aftermath of the war. When de Gaulle recognized this and resigned as the head of the provisional government, this decision, “surprising as it seemed at the time, takes in retrospect a logical meaning.” The parties had regained “the reality of power.” Having no party, de Gaulle “little by little lost his authority.” “He ran afoul of growing economic difficulties, without either the taste to study them or an overall conception for mastering them. He attempted, in the name of a fictional national unity that had not survived the war, to assume an arbitrating function more or less illusory.” Yet in attempting to regain political authority at the head of his own party, he now participates in the impotence of the Parliament. 

    Can he overcome that impotence? “If in the long term, this structure,” the Fourth Republic, “less constitutional than social and political, will not be modified, the regime will be paralyzed, and the country condemned to stagnation in the chaos.” What is needed is a “homogeneous majority” that can “break away from the syndicates under the control of the Communists,” who had succeeded to that extent in staging their long march through the institutions, and “bring them back to the legitimate function of defending professional interests, along with parliamentarism, the decline of which the crystallization of social groups has precipitated.” In the election, “the Rassemblement has pulverized the MRP and is ready to push socialism to the wall,” too. It has no doctrine, having downplayed the notion of worker-capital association, but it has a will to restore individual liberty and the liberty of the State from the syndicates and the parties. “Strong power of free citizens: the formula maintains a radical accent, provided that the first term does not erase the second.” 

    For their part, the Communists, the only ideologically coherent party, need another Popular Front à la 1935, but they have alienated the Socialists by claiming that democratic socialists are no more than agents of American imperialism. Yes, they have an ideology, but what an ideology it is—one that depending upon denying reality. Quite apart from the falsity of the charge, “we have an obvious need of American aid.” The RPF, however, could bring the “government sustained by a homogeneous majority” that Aron has been hoping for.” 

    This possibility proved just as illusory as Aron’s previous hopes for an RPF-Socialist coalition. Recognizing reality, de Gaulle reluctantly approved the formation of NATO in 1949, then rejected the proposed common market in coal a year later. By 1951, economic recovery and the nascent Pax Americana in Western Europe had reduced de Gaulle’s appeal, and the so-called Third Force, a renewed alliance of democratic socialists and the MRP, led by the skilled parliamentarian Guy Mollet, took control of the government. By the mid-1950s, De Gaulle retired to his home in the village of Colombey les Deux Églises to write his Mémoires de Guerre, seemingly removed from politics for the remainder of his life.

    But then things took a turn.

     

     

    Note

    1. Aron’s phrase may remind Anglophone readers of Temporal and Eternal, the title of a collection of several writings by the Catholic writer, Charles Péguy. However, Temporal and Eternal was published in 1955. It is possible that Aron borrows and adapts the phrase from the original works, published before the First World War; de Gaulle was a careful and sympathetic reader of them. 

     

    Filed Under: Nations

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 32
    • 33
    • 34
    • 35
    • 36
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »