Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World
  • What’s So Funny About the Law?

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    American Prisons

    December 31, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Thomas L. Dumm: Democracy and Punishment: Disciplinary Origins of the United States. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, May 18, 1988.

     

    A reverse sandwich, bread encased by baloney: in the center of this book, Professor Dumm offers an informative, brief history of the rationale for prisons in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century America. At the beginning and end, he lays on thick slices of ‘Left’-Nietzscheism, perhaps the most dubious meat now available in academe’s busy cafeteria.

    Friedrich Nietzsche utterly despised both ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ partisans in the Europe of his time. This has not prevented certain German and French thinkers, and their American imitator, from attempting to use him for political purposes. The ‘Right’s’ efforts ended in the debacle of fascism. Leftists deserve credit for greater caution; they confine their vulgar Nietzscheism to cultural and political criticism, leaving action to the few rash souls who take professorial cant seriously.

    Channeling wind from the late Michel Foucault, Professor Dumm commends the study of prisons as instruments and symbols of the subtle, frightening oppression we all suffer in American liberal democracy. If by chance you are not frightened, then I fear you lack subtlety. Professor Dumm will do his best to sensitize your benighted soul.

    The United States, you see, “is a disciplinary society.” Few Americans know this, having “fail[ed] to face the strategies of power that constitute them as subjects.” The System needs no obvious methods, such as a centralized and despotic state, which would serve as a focus for popular resentment. Instead, it exercises a device of truly Machiavellian cruelty, “repressive individualism,” whereby each person abides by moral rules voluntarily, in order to work its tyrannical will. “Moral assertions” and “appeals to truth” ought to be ‘deconstructed.’ What, you ask, will replace these mind-forged manacles of the bourgeoisie? Imagination. I hope you’re satisfied.

    So go the first sixty pages of a slim book. When the imaginative professor finally gets down to the subject, he turns out to have some intelligent things to say. He considers three prison systems: that of the Pennsylvania Quakers; the “republican” model of the founding period, and the “democratic” model of the nineteenth century.

    The Quakers wanted to maintain freedom of conscience while enforcing Christian virtues. Their prisons “maximized the free play of the techniques of moral suasion” by eschewing corporal punishment and treating imprisonment as a time of solitary contemplation and repentance. “Imprisonment was to be a pedagogy.” Dumm shows limited knowledge of Quaker theology. He never mentions the importance of free will and “Inner Light” in Quaker moral psychology. He evidently believes Quakerism innovative in conceiving of the soul as “the battleground of power.” In fact, the Quakers only followed the teachings of Jesus opposing spiritual “principalities and powers.”

    On the “republican” penitentiary, Dumm rightly challenges historians who contend that American Founders merely continued English tradition in this and other areas. He shows how the Founders revolutionized “the use of repressive power.”

    Dumm concentrates on the reforms of Dr. Benjamin Rush, the physician/statesman who tried to reconcile the republicanism of modern political philosophy and the most recent discoveries of modern science with Christian morality. In a civil society dedicated to liberty, incarceration by itself punishes severely. This, coupled with solitary confinement—a re-enactment of Locke’s state of nature to which the criminal had returned himself, in violation of the social contract—and followed by hard labor—the basis of economic value—aims to re-channel anti-social passions and refit the individual for republican life. Dumm adds that Rush’s penitentiary also stressed Bible-reading—intellectual work to supplement the physical labor—but falsely concludes, “the proposition that all are fundamentally alone is the most extremely liberal aspect of what was designed as a liberal institution.” The Bible hardly teaches that anyone is fundamentally alone; presumably, Dr. Rush wanted prisoners to learn exactly the opposite lesson from their studies.

    The “democratic” penitentiary had the more modest aim: to habituate the inmate to socially useful action. Dumm finds this despotic, an instrument of the Demon Industrialism, and puts Tocqueville’s warning against majority tyranny and the replacement of political and republican institutions with bureaucracy, to good if slightly tendentious use. Oddly, leftist critics of ‘the State,’ forgetting that it consists of people, indulge in at least as much mystification as those they claim to enlighten.

    Dumm concludes with another Foucaultian chapter, now claiming that the cultivation of fear “might contribute to a rearrangement of the current regime of truth.” Robespierre and Stalin believed that, too (as a reviewer, I exercise my right to counter-tendentiousness) without much wholesome effect. But a ‘disciplinary regime’ that needs a professor to persuade us to believe it exists, may lack needed plausibility.

    In the old days, not so good but better than these, Professor Dumm would have written a study longer on research, shorter on polemic. May Nietzsche’s derided but less pretentious “scholarly oxen” return to the fields of published research.

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    America’s Logocracy

    December 30, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Daniel T. Rodgers: Contested Truths: Keywords in American Politics Since Independence. New York: Basic Books, 1988.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, June 14,1988.

     

    “Logocracy,” not republic or democracy, was Washington Irving’s word for the American regime. Daniel T. Rodgers agrees; our “political culture” coheres by virtue of words that bind, words that “legitimize the outward frame of politics, creating those pictures in our heads which make the structures of authority tolerable and understandable.”

    This view of politics, called realistic by its adherents, reduces the meaning of words to their use. Because it denies the existence of any stable ideas to which used and abused words might refer, this school refuses to think that politics can be about anything other than power, fundamentally.

    Principles? Mere “abstractions.” Even historians who try to posit “paradigms,” those weak imitation-ideas invented by science historian Thomas Kuhn, commit the “fallacy of misplaced coherence.” “We have been too conflict-ridden a church to have a creed.” Contested, not self-evident truths are what Rodgers wants us to see as we look at the American past. He takes his keyword “keywords” from a British neo-Marxist, ideologically congenial.

    Having said that, one also should say that Rodgers doesn’t let his dogmatic skepticism carry him too far into misology and propaganda. Although biased against such “abstractions” as natural rights and Christianity, he does see some of the picture; almost poignantly, he wishes for something his epistemology will not let him have—a public realm where citizens can deliberate meaningfully.

    He selects his “keywords” with studious avoidance of the word ‘equality,’ the most ‘key’ of words in any regime where citizenship extends to everyone. In so doing he fails to consider not only the core of the American regime but the theoretical core of its most virulent competitors, his fellow Marxists.

    Rodgers begins instead with utility, “one of the glittering words of the Enlightenment.” One might expect Americans to find a doctrine centering on practicality appealing, but utilitarianism, the reduction of human life to the quest for pleasure and the avoidance of pain, failed to win many admirers here. Americans were too afflicted by the “hunger for abstractions”—specifically, Christianity, the Word that does not take kindly to the utilitarian notion of words as mere tools.

    The God who created all men equal endowed them with certain unalienable rights; “natural rights” is Rodgers’ second target for deconstruction. Natural-rights talk amounts to thinking “utopianly,” he claims, circularly confirming his argument by dismissing the Declaration of Independence as “a legally impotent document” unconnected to the Constitution. He describes the conflicts leading to the Civil War as “the elevation of practical claims into the higher stuff of rights”—a thesis that explains everything except Abolitionism, Abraham Lincoln, and the war itself.

    Turning from the Declaration to the Constitution, Rodgers discusses “the People” who speak in the Preamble through their representatives. Who are the People? A “democracy of white adult males,” Rodgers answers, overlooking the way those whites killed each other over black slavery, and eventually shared their power with women because they venerated those ‘abstractions,’ God and natural rights.

    Rodgers prefers to identify Christianity with conservative reaction to the natural rights doctrine and to the Revolution, appeals to which reached something of an extreme with Jacksonian democracy. He does not see that ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ argued over different aspects of the same ideas, both sides appealing to Christian faith and natural rights philosophy, at times exaggerating their claims beyond what the Constitution legitimates. This is the normal working of republican politics. Surface conflict masks a deeper coherence, and when that conflict gets past the surface, the republic risks civil war, a real conflict over real ideas.

    Rodgers’ own ideology prevents him from taking the American revolutionary and civil wars seriously. But the post-Civil War period, with its Gilded-Age conservatism and its equally gilt-edged antagonist, Progressivism, deserves less serious treatment, which Rodgers eagerly provides. On the ‘Right,’ judicial review as exercised by the Supreme Court of the day often did not so much defend the Constitution as a body of civil law in defense of natural rights as it undermined natural rights with legal positivism, the doctrine which claims that rights and laws are what lawmakers, most emphatically and indeed preeminently including judges, say they are.

    Meanwhile, on the ‘Left,’ the newly-founded political science profession did what it could to strip away such ‘unscientific’ fripperies as the social contract, unalienable rights, and government by consent. Rodgers catches Professor Woodrow Wilson calling Thomas Jefferson’s writings “false and artificial,” indeed “un-American.” Thanks to the professors, God and natural right gave way to ‘History’ in the minds of American elites. This situation persists to this day among social-science academics and their students in the courts and the media.

    ‘History’ itself has changed noticeably in the century since its popularization by American scholars. At first ‘idealist’/Hegelian, it turned empirical after the First World War knocked the stuffing out of things lofty and Germanic. It ran into the arms of two other Germans, Max Weber and (almost unmentioned here) Karl Marx. Despite this, Rodgers admits “the ineradicability of rights talk, despite repeated efforts to root it out.” It’s almost enough to make you think such rights self-evident.

    What we have here is a book of six chapters, two of them worth reading. And that, in the eccentric arithmetic of book reviewing, is not half-bad.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Jewish Law versus Modern Philosophy

    December 30, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Joseph B. Soloveitchik: The Halakhic Mind: An Essay on Jewish Tradition and Modern Thought. New York: Seth Press/The Free Press, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, May 10, 1988.

     

    The non-Jewish majority of mankind, including the majority of those called ‘intellectuals,’ know almost nothing of Jewish thought, ancient or modern. Anti-Judaism, and later anti-Semitism, discouraged such knowledge in the past; it is no excuse today. Yet formidable obstacles remain.

    Because Jewish thought emphasizes the Law, the Halakhah, it cuts against the libertarian and indeed libertine instincts of our time and place. Christian thought, which criticizes Jewish ‘legalism’ and attempt to summarize the Law by the commands to love God and to love your neighbor as yourself, also discourages careful inquiry. For their part, Jews themselves have never much proselytized; orthodox Judaism intentionally discourages too-curious ‘outsiders.’ Lawgivers command; study of the law serves obedience, and is not to be undertaken from an attitude of ‘mere curiosity.’

    This latter difficulty need not prove insuperable. Great rabbis have written books accessible to conscientious non-Jews. Moses Maimonides’ Guide of the Perplexed remains the paradigm of these. But Maimonides was and remains a controversial and complex figure, his understanding of Judaism tinctured by Greek and Arabic philosophy. Modern readers will need a mastery of those philosophers before they can approach Maimonides.

    Rabbi Joseph B. Soloveitchik speaks in terms more familiar to us. Educated at the University of Berlin, he knows the writings of Kant, Hegel, and the major German theologians. As a member of a distinguished rabbinical family, he began serious, disciplined academic training in childhood. This background makes him a lucid and profound commentator on a conflict that very nearly defines Western culture: the conflict between Jerusalem and Athens—more specifically, Jewish tradition and modern philosophy (call it ‘Berlin’).

    The Halakhic Mind complements Rabbi Soloveitchik’s Halakhic Man, published five years ago. In Halakhic Man, he distinguishes the man governed by Jewish law from the more familiar Homo religiosus, whose emotionalism and quest for transcendence inclines toward mysticism. In The Halakhic Mind Soloveitchik distinguishes the thought of Halakhic man fro modern philosophic thought.

    Under pressure from the discoveries of twentieth-century physics, Soloveitchik observes, modern philosophy has split into two major factions. Logical positivists attempt to evaluate all realms of human life by the criteria of modern scientific method; apart from the fact that this simply rules morality, politics, and religion out of philosophic inquiry, it does not have much explanatory power. This leaves the field open to various philosophers who, deriving their thought from Hegel, do not reject scientific method but do not suppose it the last rational word on the nature of reality. “Epistemological pluralism” results—the selection of a rational method of inquiry appropriate to the object of the inquiry. Unfortunately, like its practical counterparts, moral relativism and political pluralism, cognitive pluralism tends toward chaos, an egalitarian stew wherein all the ingredients look and taste the same.

    Soloveitchik wants to redeem the common sense behind epistemological pluralism—that the criteria of knowledge in physics differ from the criteria of knowledge in religion, for example—without sacrificing cognitive and ethical hierarchy. He insists that any psychical act has a logical shape to it; even the most passionate lover must apprehend his beloved. Thus Homo religiosus “substitutes neither belief for knowledge nor faith for critical reasoning; no less than the philosopher himself, he is an enthusiastic practitioner of the cognitive art.”

    Soloveitchik sees the problem: “apprehension” here can mean false perception or misunderstanding as easily as true, and lovers of God do not always much care for rationality. Soloveitchik rejects religious sentimentalism as a “pretentious and arrogant” attitude that “frees every dark passion and every animal impulse in man.” “It is of greater urgency for religion to cultivate objectivity than perhaps for any other branch of human culture.”

    This returns him to the importance of law. Law makes religious love and religious thought manifest. It makes subjectivity objective, susceptible to rational inquiry. “Subjectivity cannot be approached directly; it must first be objectified by the ‘logos,'” the word of God.

    It should be needless to say that for Rabbi Soloveitchik “objectification reaches its highest expression in the Halakhah”—which Law, he cautions, one must not confuse with the causal natural law of scientists. To confuse halakhic law with natural law would be to deny free will to human beings, and therefore to deny any merit to our obedience to God’s laws.

    As for religious liberalism, it “has traveled in the wrong direction—from objectivity to subjectivity,” sacrificing religiosity to liberalism along the way. Aiming at objectivity will yield a different result: “Out of the sources of the Halakhah, a new world view awaits formulation.”

    Rabbi Soloveitchik’s pair of books will remain an indispensable introduction to Jewish thought and its response to modern philosophy.

     

    Filed Under: Bible Notes

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 177
    • 178
    • 179
    • 180
    • 181
    • …
    • 225
    • Next Page »