Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World
  • What’s So Funny About the Law?

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Strauss on Political Philosophy

    January 29, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Hilail Gildin, ed.: An Introduction to Political Philosophy: Ten Essays by Leo Strauss. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1989.
    Thomas L. Pangle, ed.: The Rebirth of Classical Rationalism: An Introduction to the Thought of Leo Strauss. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1989.

    Originally published in Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy. Volume 17, Number 3, Spring 1990. Republished by permission.

     

    “One cannot settle any Platonic question of any consequence by simply quoting Plato,” (Pangle, 193) writes Leo Strauss. Strauss titles a collection of his essay, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy; insofar as Strauss Platonizes, he must be quoted with care. Quoting Plato or Strauss with care means to quote them in the spirit of evidence, in the spirit of ‘pointing to,’ not in the spirit of demonstration, of ‘Q.E.D.’ He who knows he does not know will unfailingly frustrate those who want to know what to believe as well as those who know what they want to believe. The frustration and even suspicion Strauss stirs in dogmatic souls has found ample ventilation in a variety of journals and books. Those readers for whom controversy arouses curiosity instead of indignation may seek firsthand knowledge of Strauss from Strauss’s writings.

    Hilail Gildin’s collection will serve as an excellent place to begin. This new edition contains four additional essays: Strauss’s own brief introduction to political philosophy, one on the theologico-political question, and two on liberal education. Gildin’s introduction succinctly outlines Strauss’s principal concerns as a politicl philosopher, particularly the way in which modern political philosophers brought out the nihilistic implications of Machiavell’s thought in ever more elaborate forms, and the consequent need for a renewed radicalism, so to speak—recourse to the Socratic roots of political philosophy.

    Strauss adopted the Socratic view of philosophy as first of all a way of life, even the way of life—the highest form of politics or self-rule. This view regards human life as needful of wisdom, as rightly animated by love of wisdom, the quest for knowledge of the whole. Even the vast majority of human beings, who are unphilosophic and content to stay that way, in some sense need philosophy; the political good requires education of qualified young persons for philosophic life, not only for political life as conventionally understood in a given regime. At the same time, philosophers need to start with political life as conventionally understood, to treat citizens’ opinions as portals to understanding, not as barriers to be knocked down. Socratic philosophy contrasts sharply with historicism, which begins with Rousseau’s rejection of the naturalness of reasons and issues in the divorce of ‘ought’ from ‘is’ in the name of realism. For radical historicism, even reality becomes an ‘ism.’ After Nietzsche refuted optimistic historicist progressivism, only self-conscious nihilism remained. The modern attempt to dismiss ideal republics and cities of God in order to free man for reshaping nature to his own liking, ended in a rebirth of tragedy, first with, then without, nobility. “The attempt to make man absolutely at home in this world ended in man’s becoming absolutely homeless” (108).

    Modernity often fuses reason to spiritedness, forming ideology and propaganda. Socrates associate reason with eros, not spiritedness, seeking a self-sufficiency that need not harm (or directly help) the philosopher’s fellow-citizens. Only force or, perhaps, a form of love, patriotism, could induce the philosopher to participate in politics. In his essays on liberal education we see Strauss as a kind of statesman, indeed as a reformer describing “the necessary endeavor to found an aristocracy within democratic mass society” (314). This language will exercises egalitarians among Strauss’s critics, who may overlook his call for “unhesitating loyalty” to decent constitutionalism (345). Or, what is more likely, perhaps some critics balk at constitutionalism itself, and at Strauss’s observation, made in the same breath, that the “grandiose failures” of Marx and Nietzsche should teach us never to separate wisdom from moderation. Be this as it may, even at his most ‘political’ Strauss never fails to point to philosophy, to the awareness of our understanding the philosopher may enjoy, beyond the ambitions of the modern project.

    Strauss crafted each of his published essays to stand alone and also, in most instances, to stand within a book. A cautious reader will therefore approach Professor Gildin’s collection with some reservations, concerned that the act of extracting essays form their original contexts will somehow lose many intended resonances. Such fears prove needless here. Gildin has given us a real book, one whose chapters lead logically from one to another, making a coherent argument. Even readers familiar with these essays may find these new juxtapositions instructive. The book’s only shortcoming is its bibliography, which has not been updated since the 1975 edition. If there is another printing, the publisher might consider making this useful revision.

    Thomas Pangle’s collection first calls attention not to Strauss as political philosopher but to Strauss as philosopher, to Strauss’s “classical rationalism” or “erotic skepticism” (xi-xii). In this, however, Pangle is as politic as Gildin, given current academic interest (bordering on obsession) with things epistemological. The volume may give Strauss a hearing before those who expect the philosopher to ‘do philosophy’ rather than to ‘know himself’ or to ‘live philosophically.’

    In his introduction Pangle quickly brings his readers to politics, to the way epistemology and politics intertwine. “Norms of civic justice, of civic virtue and vice,” emerge from dialogue (xii). Not absolute in the sense that natural laws or categorical imperatives are said to be, they are nonetheless trans-historically valid because they are grounded in unchanging human nature. Modern philosophers attempt to lay down laws evident to non-philosophers, reducing observation, prudence, and classification to methods and rules. ‘Method-ists’ want to overcome the need for both kinds of wisdom, practical and theoretical, and thereby rigidify both politics and philosophy, including the liberal education of potential statesmen and philosophers.

    In the United States during Strauss’s lifetime there was much talk of ‘humanism’ as an alternative to totalitarian ideology. Strauss saw that humanism cannot replace the traditional religion as the foundation of morality in commercial republican society, even among the academic elites. Humanism cannot account for the whole of being, as may be seen in Isaiah Berlin’s concept of “negative freedom” or “freedom from,” which needs an absolute foundation but denies itself one on principle (7, 16-17). And even the self-created limits favored by existentialists cannot be seen as limits without “the light of infinity” (38). After the Nazi disaster convinced Heidegger that “contempt for reasonableness and praise of resoluteness” (30) quickly run themselves aground., Heidegger retained his contempt for reason but added patience. His patient ‘waiting-for’ a religion that cannot be consciously created, produced the atmosphere of our own time, called by André Malraux, “the days of limbo.”

    Classical political rationalism begins with political opinions but seeks a conversion to truth, away from lies (however noble). “The political man is constantly forced to have very long conversations with very dull people on very dull subjects” (74). he philosophic life avoids much of that, without losing all moderation, and without losing its sense of humor. (“Modern research on Plato originated in Germany, the country without comedy” [206]; too many commentators on Strauss are German, all too German.) Philosophic life begins in wonder; Biblical wisdom begins with fear of the Lord; modernity, which has tried “to preserve Biblical morality while abandoning Biblical faith,” loses philosophic and Biblical virtues (240). Because Western civilization lives in the relation between ‘Athens’ and ‘Jerusalem,’ radical modernity tends toward the disintegration of the West. Contemporary ideologues who chant for the purging of writings by ‘dead, white, European males’ from university syllabi know what they don’t want, sort of. The spirit of Strauss in the pages of these books counsels us to react to such incantations with neither indignation nor dismissive laughter: “The recognition by philosophy of the fact that the human race is worthy of some seriousness is the origin of political philosophy or political science” (126). (Emphasis added and, it is to be hoped, balance observed.)

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    The First Amendment, Misunderstood

    January 27, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    In July 1990, Red Bank, New Jersey political activist William Davis wrote a letter to the editor of The Register, a daily newspaper published in nearby Shrewsbury, New Jersey. Davis commented on a decision by Howard E. Cook, a Gwinnett County, Georgia judge who ruled that state law banning the wearing of masks intended for purposes of intimidation or criminality (in this instance, the mask worn by Ku Klux Klan members) was an unconstitutional violation of the First Amendment right to freedom of speech. Davis called the decision “resoundingly correct,” an act adhering to “the dictates of the law”—a Constitution that originally held “certain folks to be only a little more than half human.”

    My reply, dated August 8, 1990, rebutted Mr. Davis’s argument.

     

    In his justifiable indignation at the Ku Klux Klan, Mr. William Davis of Red Bank has misstated the principle and intentions of the Framers of the United States Constitution.

    The Georgia judge who ruled that Klan members have a First Amendment right to wear their ludicrous costumes (including masks to conceal their identities) was not necessarily “following the dictates of the law,” as Mr. Davis supposes. The prohibition, “Congress shall make no law… abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people to peaceably assemble”—even if this may be applied to legislation drafted by municipal and state lawmakers—does not shield dress-up racists preaching sedition. There are three reasons to question the judge’s reading of the First Amendment, and the regrettable body of legal opinion upon which his decision is based.

    First, costuming isn’t speech. Alothough judges who prefer writing laws to interpreting them now chatter about ‘freedom of expression’ and ‘symbolic speech,’ you won’t find those formulas in the writings of the Framers. They said “speech”—not “fashion statements.” To the Framers, clothes most emphatically did not make the man. God and nature do, and reasoned speech is the unmistakable sign of that handiwork.

    Second, freedom of speech is a civil liberty; that is, it partakes no only of liberty, but of civility. Freedom isn’t license, as a rather libertarian British educator [A. S. Neill] used to say. All forms of Constitutionally protected speech are civil. Constitutionally unprotected speech, speech fundamentally subversive of civil society, includes terroristic threats, obscenity, disruptions of public meetings, and so on. (It’s too bad that the American Civil Liberties Union exalts liberty while forgetting the civility that makes it possible, and thus mistakes what ‘American’ means.) The Klan’s history of terrorism clearly falls outside the limits of civil society.

    Third, as Mr. Davis correctly observes, “the Klan has always regarded” certain ethnic and religious groups, including African-Americans, Jews, and Roman Catholics, “as subhuman beings.” But Davis misses the legal implication of this. Klan bigotry subverts each of the stated purposes of the Constitution: “to form a more perfect union, establish justice, insure domestic tranquility, provide for the common defense, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings of liberty to ourselves and our posterity.” Klan bigotry also contradicts the underlying principle of the Constitution set down in the Declaration of Independence: “that all Men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness.” The Ku Klux Klan is a subversive organization practicing sedition speech, verbal and ‘symbolic.’ A proper understanding of the Constitution would permit legislators to outlaw such organizations as the Ku Klux Klan. Whether or not to act on such Constitutional permission should be a matter governed by prudential calculation of the likely results, not judicial interference.

    Mr. Davis thus fails to see the resources our Constitution provides to Americans who oppose racist politics. Part of the problem is his uncritical acceptance of a polemical thrust made by James Baldwin and others who claim that the Framers regarded the slave (in Davis’ words) as “only a little more than half human” or (as Baldwin put it) as “three-fifths of a man.” Were this true, the Framers would rank only a cut or two above the Klan in overall intelligence and humanity. Fortunately, the interpretation is a falsehood amply refuted by an examination of the Constitution itself. Unfortunately, this falsehood still enjoys currency among people who should know better.

    Article I, Section 2 of the Constitution as originally written apportions representatives and direct taxes among the states according to a population formula “determined by adding the whole number of free persons,” including bonded apprentices, excluding “Indians not taxed,” and including “three-fifths of the [population of] all other persons”—i.e., slaves. The formula was written this way because representatives of [predominantly] free states objected to the additional representatives slave state would have acquired, had the full slave population of those states been included. The slaveholders, obviously, wanted their slaves counted as if they were full citizens, as this would have maximized the power of the slaveholding states in Congress.

    It is, of course, the lasting shame of the slaveholders that they perpetuated slavery, and the lasting misfortune of the United States that the slaveholders had the power to make their ‘peculiar institution’ last as long as it did. But the sentiments of the majority of the Framers should not be obscured. In his Address at Cooper Union, New York City, on February 27, 1860, Abraham Lincoln showed that only two of the 39 signers of the United States Constitution ever acted to forbid Congressional prohibition of slavery in the federal territories—a prohibition understood by pro-slavery and anti-slavery partisans alike as fatal in the long run to slavery everywhere in the Union. The Framers deliberately left intact the very engine that could dismantle slavery. During the founding period, many of the most prominent slaveholders in the South (e.g., George Washington and Thomas Jefferson) sought feasible ways to put slavery on the road to extinction. Although the slaveholders denied it, the Constitution itself as written (and, most emphatically, not as distorted by the majority of the Supreme Court in its infamous Dred Scott decision) proved the supreme instrument of slavery’s extinction, in the hands of a great statesman guided by the principles of the Declaration, even as the Framers were.

    Pro-slavery passions hardened in the 19th century, partly as a reaction to the denunciations of radical abolitionists, partly as a response to slavery’s increased economic benefits to slaveholders after the invention of the cotton gin, and partly in the wake of nationalist and racist ideologies spawned not in American, but in continental Europe. None of these phenomena may fairly be traced to the principles of the American Founders. The commercial-republican regime embodied in the Constitution works toward the abolition of tyranny in all its forms, and under all its masks.

    Mr. Davis concludes, “The Klan should wear their masks not as a First Amendment right, but as a sentence.” Agreed. But he should add that this sentence would be Constitutionally sound if preceded by the Klansmen’s arrest, unmasking, and trial by juries supervised by judges who understand Constitutional principles.

     

    2018 Note: Judge Cook’s ruling was reversed later that year by the Georgia Supreme Court in State v. Miller (1990).

    Filed Under: American Politics

    What Is Executive Power?

    January 27, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr.: Taming the Prince: The Ambivalence of Modern Executive Power. (New York: The Free Press, 1989).

    Originally published in Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy. Volume 18, Number 1, Fall 1990. Republished with permission.

     

    In his Message to Congress in Special Session on Independence Day, 1861, Abraham Lincoln asked, “Is there, in all republics, this inherent, fatal weakness? Must a government, of necessity, be too strong for the liberties of its own people, or too weak to maintain its own existence?” [1] These questions have remained urgent, to put it mildly. ‘History’ most likely will not silence them and thereby conveniently put an end to itself.

    Harvey C. Mansfield, Jr., reminds his readers that “until America, the history of modern republics was modest, inglorious, and spotted” (xvi). Much of republican history since the American founding has remained so. While the Founders provided their country with an executive strong enough to enforce the law but not strong enough to contravene it flagrantly without ill consequences, other republican founders (including our own, at first, with their Articles of Confederation) mired their countries in parliamentarism. Parliamentarism reacts too strongly to the monarchic or even despotic strain in modernity, the line that runs, in political thought, from Machiavelli’s Prince to Hobbes to Hegel and then, democratizing itself with a vengeance, to Marx. “[T]he constitutional executive is an invention of liberalism, of Locke, Montesquieu, and the American founders, rather than of Machiavelli and Hobbes” (xviii). The “ambivalence” of the executive of modern liberalism, and also its “beauty,” inheres in its combination of weakness and strength, its subordination to law and with its ability to “reach where law cannot” (xvi), doing so prudently and with consent if the executive knows his business.

    The ambivalence of the modern executive plays itself out in political theory as a bifurcation of liberalism into two branches: ‘deontological’ liberalism, emphasizing rights and rules, and ‘teleological’ liberalism, which emphasizes utility. Deontological liberalism tends toward parliamentarism and, recently in America, toward collaboration of the legislature with the bureaucracy. To counterbalance this tendency, and to give voice to prudence if not to outright utilitarianism (which also has its legislative spokesmen), one must reconsider the Machiavellian origins of the modern executive.

    In his book Le fil de l’épée Charles de Gaulle quotes Goethe’s Faust: “In the beginning was the Word? No! In the beginning was the act!” Both Goethe and de Gaulle know their Machiavelli, and de Gaulle contrasts the excessive talkativeness of French parliamentarians with the forceful actions needed to defend republicanism. Mansfield, who may be said with confidence also to know his Machiavelli, observes that “the doctrine of executive power originates in Machiavelli’s proclamation of the sovereignty of deeds over words” (xxii). At the same time, unjustified deeds cause resentment among those they are done to . Therefore, “executive power is power exercised in the name of someone or something else—God or the people or the law” (xxiii). Mansfield expresses this in the oxymoron “legalized lawlessness,” meaning acts of retaliation and anticipation that “would be illegal”—perhaps even immoral—”if they were not performed by the police” under the direction of a legitimate executive (3). Because “laws that are mere demonstrations to the intellect are like prayers to the deaf” (40, and because “the rational appeal to interest is much diluted without a capacity to engender fear” (6), and because “the necessary exactions of any government bring more danger and dishonor to free governments than to tyrannies” (14), a way must be found to enable the executive to act firmly, in good conscience, while saving (so to speak) the pardonable pride of the ruled. If “tyranny” is the “human name” for unreason, and a degree of unreason will always be required to rule unreasoning men (most notably by exploiting the ambition or pride of the few who want most of all to rule and the fear of the many who want only not to be ruled) [2], then “law can only be executed tyrannically” (18-19). Whereas Machiavelli openly recognizes the necessity of tyranny, even invites the prince to it, Aristotle “transforms the tyrant from the destroyer of law into a king, the guardian of law” (19). Both philosophers find ways to tame tyranny, to use it. Mansfield proceeds to explore the differences of their ways and their purposes.

    Aristotle has “little or nothing to say” about executive power (23). In Book VI of the Politics he briefly mentions executive or punitive powers, suggesting that they be divided “so that,” in Mansfield’s word, “no one person takes all the discredit” for the perceived injustice of punitive actions (24, 29). “The whole history of executive power depends on understanding why it is absent in Aristotle” (25). Aristotelian rule contrasts sharply with Machiavellian execution, a contrast reflecting “a different attitude toward nature in Aristotle and Machiavelli” (28). For Aristotle, politics is neither simply natural nor simply unnatural. Politics involves human beings’ natural capacity to deliberate, to speak, and to choose, intending or at least claiming to intend the common benefit. Rule (archē) also means beginning; it is a principle (again the Latin root is the same as for ‘prince’) directed toward an end “made visible to the public in a certain order that Aristotle calls its form (eidos 1276b2)” (32). In politics this form is the politeia or regime, and forms have a truth-content; there is no “mere relativism of regimes” (33). If regimes had no truth-content, if tyranny were only monarchy misliked, then “all politics is tyranny, and justifiably so, because necessarily so” (33). The end toward which choiceworthy political forms direct us is fully developed human nature. “To begin directly with nature leaves human freedom and choice out of account; but to fail to return to nature would leave freedom and arbitrary quirk and without a guide” (33). When Aristotle calls man a political animal, he means both words. The best man “wills nature’s kingship as his own. Thus his will is neither arbitrary nor unfree” (42).

    Because the best man is rare, and because even ordinarily spirited men resent the rule of the best, or of anyone, laws are needed in order to win their consent. These laws are relative to the regime and need a statesman’s prudence to remedy their generality, their inability to address themselves to each circumstance in all its particulars. The prudent man will give every appearance of strictly reverencing the laws—even (especially) as he quietly supplements them with his own judgment—in order to protect himself and others from tyranny. “The best man… chooses according to nature as if nature were his own will. He also chooses as if human choice, especially past human choices bound up in custom, were nature’s (1287b 5-8). This assumption of nature, law, and custom, which is part deference, part presumption, is what it means for men to rule; they make themselves the beginning principle (archē) of themselves and of things. This is the very opposite of executive power, in which the ruler presents himself as an agent of some other power (human or not), or as one who is forced into action by brute necessity. We see the distinction in the very words used; in Greek to rule means to begin; but to execute, from the Latin exsequor, means to ‘follow out’ what has been begun by someone else.” (43) There is, then, a certain relationship between Christianity and modernity.

    A philosopher is sometimes a prudent man. Perhaps “out of philanthropy, but also for the sake of his own understanding… about human resistance to reform and how to overcome it,” the philosopher will consider and recommend political institutions and share in political deliberation (46). He discovers that it is in the spirited nature of men to resist rule, even beneficial rule; more, he discovers that nature itself is “more ornery than the most ornery of men” (49). Human excellence, which alone “can rescue human freedom from the willfulness which disguises the submission of freedom to lower nature,” seems tyrannical because it “looks like willfulness to willful men, as they attribute the principle of their own conduct to the government of nature,” running “from the appearance of tyranny to the reality” (49). Aristotle recommends the mixed regime or “polity” combining democracy and oligarchy, natural necessity and human choice, lot and choice. The three parts of this regime correspond to the three parts of the human soul: deliberating, ruling (based on the spirited defense of the body), and judging. Only through the soul “can we understand how reform in politics is possible.” “[H]uman stubbornness,” which resists reform, must be made the foundation of reform, through arbitration and “sophisms” (50-51). The modern divisions of government (legislative, executive, and judicial) “do not describe rational functions of the soul” but instead refer to law (divine, natural, or conventional) regardless of how it is made (53). In modernity “wary calculation” tends to replace deliberations. While for Aristotle deliberation is sovereign, for moderns legislation is sovereign, with the significant proviso that the executive may need to do more than imply “execute” laws, and may thereby become sovereign in fact if not formally.

    Aristotelian deliberation “join[s] the human good that [men] choose with the nonhuman necessities or good they must accept”; to learn to deliberate, “we must be abstracted from our own concerns,” relax our spiritedness (56). (In modernity, prudent men often find they must encourage or “inspire” citizens to defend the laws vigorously.) Aristotle commends a plural magistrate in order to maintain dialogue or the sovereignty of deliberation. “Men are not under the rule of nature or god such that their own rule merely reflects a grander principle ruling them” (59). To establish a regime on the foundation of “a single natural law” would lead to passionate, partisan misinterpretation of that law. Aristotle’s way, requiring a “momentary separation of judging from the standard of judgment,” teaches moderation (62-63). John Locke’s assertion of the individual’s natural power to execute the law of nature whenever it seems threatened risks ill-judging of one’s own case. Nor would Aristotle countenance the religious persecution Locke intended to make impossible: “There is no court for cases of impiety because Aristotle does not want divine anger executed on humans” by humans (64). Both the religious regimes and some of the modern liberal regimes that overthrew them take an over-simple approach to law, directly applying it to political life and thereby making it prey to passion, instead of filtering it through prudential judgment. This is as important for the rulers as it is for the ruled: “The offices do not govern men as if they were external powers or laws from nature guaranteeing the regularity if not the perfection of human behavior. Rather, men must assume the offices and make the potentialities actual in their own virtuous activity” (68). Because “justice can be ignoble, especially in the execution of penalties” (66), and because he wants to preserve the political man’s sense of his own nobility and the nobility of political life in order to moderate them, keep them “occupied in wholesome or at least constructive activity,” Aristotle lists only one executive office among the seventeen magistral offices mentioned in the Politics. “He does not expand the office into the awesome modern executive by taking advantage of its odium to make it more powerful and efficient” (69). On the contrary, he divides it, assigning its function to several courts—his own version of separation of powers. He seeks “to awaken virtue rather than stimulate fear and the desire for gain, as Machiavelli was to do” (69), attracting base souls to office and comprehending all offices “in the office of jailer” (70). “Nature understood as unfriendly to man gives human justice no support and compels human government to imitate angry gods, to rely on fear as the motive for obedience, and to loose hatred against its enemies. This was Machiavelli’s way but not Aristotle’s.” (70) Thus does Paul’s Letter to the Romans anticipate Machiavelli’s ‘letter’ to the remnants of the Romans.

    Rome and the Holy Roman Empire are said to feature purely executive offices, but that illusion comes from viewing them after Machiavelli’s selective unveilings. Rome substituted the tension between republic and monarchy for the Greek tension between democracy and oligarchy. This substitution was practical, not theoretical. Aristotle regards monarchs as ideal rulers, not realistically to be hoped for, and there is much in Roman history to confirm his caution. Polybius’ mixed regime relies less on reason, more on fear, than Aristotle does. But Polybius would also correct Rome by referring Romans to nature, and less to “fear, superstition, and imperialism” (82). The office of dictator in the Roman constitution was magnified by Machiavelli and Bodin; the Romans themselves, notably Livy and Cicero, minimized its role.

    The Holy Roman Empire presents a somewhat different, but still pre-modern, aspect of the executive. The pope rules by the grace of God, not natural right, and the Holy Roman Emperor “was not a modern executive, whose effectual actions are designed to end all dispute, but a theologico-political executive, whose claim to grace is essentially contestable” (89). Thomas Aquinas, Dante, and Marsilius of Padua are the great commentators on that executive, “attempting to restore and adjust the Aristotelian argument for ruling, in which men take responsibility for governing themselves” (91). Aquinas conceived politics “as guided by God’s commands but not merely executing them” (92). Aquinas combines Scripture and philosophy by emphasizing natural law. Prudence derives human law from natural law, which does not imitate divine law. With respect to human spiritedness, Aquinas arranges “a friendly compromise” between Aristotle’s effort to ennoble it and the Bible’s attempt to humble it (95).

    Dante claims that the secular prince owes his authority directly to God, not the Church. (In this he made himself resemble Paul.) His prince aims at human happiness, leaving spiritual instruction to the clergy. This is no modern sovereign, although Dante does suppose, unlike Aristotle, “that Aristotle’s kingship can be actualized, that one prince might be made ruler of the whole world” (97). However, his proofs “seem more physical or metaphysical than political” (97), raising questions about how Dante means some readers to understand his argument.

    Mansfield takes particular care with Marsilius. “For the first time ‘execution’ and ‘executive’ become a theme in political science” (100). Yet Marsilius does not take Machiavelli’s final steps. “Why does Marsilius almost come to the modern executive?” (100)

    Marsulius does not rely upon nature, as Aristotle and even the Roman historians and philosophers do. He does not seem to say that human nature is political. He emphasizes prudence and human law founded upon popular consent, a curious combination. “Marsilius is the first to conceive the ruler entirely as an executive for the people” (103). “[T]o prevent the pope from ruling,” Marsilius revised Aristotle in order to save him, “redefining ruling as executing by distinguishing ruling from legislating, the function of the people” (103). Marsilius stops short of Machiavellianism because he wants to keep the executive “within the orbit of law, or—when that is not possible, thanks to the defects of law—under the control of virtue” (106). His executive is weak, an executor of the popular will “that creates the ruling part of the city,” the regime (108). Marsilius thus democratizes politics, weakening the claims of monarchs, aristocrats, and oligarchs to rule. He locates the form of the city in the law, not in the regime. “The result, if we compare Marsilius to what we have seen in Aristotle, is to separate the city from the soul—Marsilius’ purpose being to prevent the ordering of the soul [the aim of priests] from determining the ordering of the offices” (109). The order of the offices will aim at protecting the body.

    To retain the rule of prudence, Marsilius assigns it not to some dubious “wisdom of the people” but to the executive. He advocates an elective monarchy, not a representative democracy, in an attempt to make the rule of prudence more likely. As guidance for his executive, Marsilius metamorphoses Christian doctrine into “natural right” (111), teaching men “to respect Christianity without yielding to its claims to rule,” and “sav[ing] the Christian sect” from “simultaneously prizing and despising worldly honor” (113), that is, from claiming title to rule while despising worldly power. In this Marsilius retains something like Aristotelian virtue, as against both Machiavellian necessity and Christian charity. Judges may be ministers of God’s wrath (just ones, if they are prudent), but priests are not. And, in a most noteworthy formulation, Marsilius has his executive act almost like a philosopher: “As knowers, they renounce rule over others: since rule requires executive force, which can only come from the consent of the legislator [i.e., the people], knowledge does not entitle one to rule” (114). A knower has “a claim to rule on natural grounds”; the flaw in Aristotelian kingship is that it has been claimed by the pope (114). For both Aristotle and Marsilius, “the difficulty is that political men are in need of philosophy; but if they use philosophy, they are in danger of surrendering to it” (115). A still greater practical danger is the one opened by the modern call to applaud uncritically man’s natural, spirited resistance to being ruled. This “leaves no accommodation between knowing and freedom, between the realm of necessity and that of choice” (116). Marsilian natural right is an accommodation between philosophic knowledge and political consent. His executive is “Aristotle’s kingship in a different guise” (117). Marsilius shares Aristotle’s regard for prudential adaptation to circumstances by statesmen and political philosophers alike. He commends no “new modes and orders” for systematic introduction and perpetual use.

    Mansfield devotes his central chapter to Machiavelli. Machiavelli appropriates Christian modes and orders, artfully perverting them. Observing “that the central event in Christian revelation is an act of execution” (124), Machiavelli politicizes a father’s sacrifice of his son. The pious cruelty of Christianity is half right; Machiavelli retains the cruelty, the imperialism. Execution will now be guided by “the decrees of natural necessity” instead of divine commands (127). Natural necessity differs from Aristotelian natural right in being below, not beyond or above, conventional law. Therefore good arms, not good souls, yield “good” laws. Nature is “the necessity that forces us to seek nutriment, safety, and glory”; virtue is “the habit or faculty or quality of anticipating that threefold necessity” (129). “Your virtue is both strong and weak: strong because you have chosen to do what you would eventually have been forced to do, weak because you had no other choice” (130).

    To accomplish this ambition the modern executive needs seven characteristics: He must use punishment politically, and therefore needs broad powers; he must put war and foreign policy above peace and domestic affairs; he must govern indirectly; he must employ techniques applicable in all regimes, and does not much worry about differences among regimes; he must act suddenly and decisively; he must act secretly, surprising all the others; there must be only one of him. It should be needless to say that conventional law will be supplemented by selected illegalities, made easier by the lack of any independent judiciary. “[F]ear replaces justice as the ground for politics” (136); princely ambition replaces divine providence in the sky. No more cyclical history, no more consideration of the best regime: Machiavelli considers only survival, expansion, and glory. “[N]ecessity is stronger than principle,” and executions loose the “primal fear” that is “the first mover of politics” (140). “Consent” means involving the people in crimes, making accomplices out of mere citizens. The prince does not merely react to necessity. He creates (a deliberately godlike term) necessity for others, eschewing Aristotelian public deliberation for conspiratorial planning and sudden action. Rulership rightly understood is tyranny.

    Thomas Hobbes attempts to reduce Machiavellianism to a (modern) science, borrowing the concept of “power” from physics. He makes Machiavellian execution “legal” by classifying it as an expression of a natural necessity termed natural law. This enables him to publicize his executions. The science that discerns natural law/necessity is perfect reason. Science conquers fortune or nature, but, in keeping with the more public character of the Hobbesian executive, it assuages popular fear more than it satisfies the spiritedness of princes. Peace, not glory, is the Hobbesian objective. There is a problem with this: “The very union of legislative and executive power weakens the executive by leaving the impression that government consists in passing laws that obey the laws of justice” (177-178). Despotism issues, theoretically at least, in democracy.

    The potential instability of the modern project (seen in the history of seventeenth-century England, of France from 1789 to 1958, and of Russia since 1907) has made philosophers consider how the new executive might be given some constitutional restraints. “Locke’s political science shows that the modern constitution and the modern executive are mutually dependent and yet antithetical” (181). Unlike James Harrington, that “eager but incompetent guide” to Machiavelli who “could not figure out how to combine the state of nature with constitutional government” (183-184), Locke formulated a rule of law that is “the rule of a legislative power that each [individual] has constituted out of the state of nature” (186). The state of nature is a state of scarcity; constitutional law governing civil society will aim at self-preservation, including the preservation of the property needed to preserve oneself. Because each individual is the best judge of his own needs, Locke “constitutionalizes the necessity of tyranny” (187) by putting necessity on an individualistic and egalitarian foundation. Natural liberty and equality issue in constitutional or civil liberty and equality, reconciling self-preservation with government by consent. Locke therefore limits the executive by dividing and separating its powers, in recognition of the potential threat to self-preservation posed by tyrannical executives.

    Consistent with this democratization, Locke is no less atheistic than Machiavelli and Hobbes, but far more discreet about it. Atheism can comport easily with egalitarianism because it denies the existence of the Creator-created hierarchy. “The people” are seldom atheists themselves, however. Locke first claims that all human beings are God’s property; he later asserts that “every man has property in his own person,” thereby attacking patriarchalism natural and divine, replacing it with the “very strange”—but also very useful—”doctrine that we establish governments by the execution of a law of nature” (195). This requires Locke to give the people a somewhat more spirited character than does Hobbes. to encourage them to resist tyranny he moralizes the state of nature a touch, making it a place not of war (which maximizes necessity) but of scarcity (more amenable to planned remedies that may be thoughtfully defended). “Freedom as the foundation makes government by consent; reason as the ground denies the legitimacy to governments wrongly consented to” (198). Lockean reason can make mistakes, for “[i]f Locke were to insist on the correct use of reason, he would have to give government over to the best reasoners, as Aristotle does,” or to “one reasoned, following Hobbes” (198). “Tacit consent” combines reason with freedom.

    In civil society, Locke advises, the legislative and executive powers should be separated but not formally balanced. Executive power will apparently follow the legislative will. “Executive power is subordinate, but the executive person may not by” (201); that person enjoys the “tacit consent” of the people, particularly in matters concerning their preservation, such as war and the punishment of criminals (203). “By gradually introducing his readers to the scope of executive power, Locke uses reason to help them appreciate that element in humanity which is not amenable to reason” (204). The tension between legislative and executive powers will constitute “a structure for self-criticism within the regime” (204-205). This tension will be expressed in the struggle between a rhetoric of rights and a rhetoric of interests, foreshadowing the debate between deontological and utilitarian liberals today. Prudence itself will divide along the lines of “claiming one’s right” and “following one’s interest” (209). Locke “builds a divided mind into constitutional government” (210). A divided mind cannot rule in the Aristotelian sense. It gives scope to individual liberty but is prey to ideologues who would dialectically overcome the division to satisfy the mind’s natural craving for unity. “For Locke, right and necessity were held together by the convention of Property, in which the need to work was answered by the virtue of industry, and in which the right of each depends upon the right of everyone else” (210). Predictably, ‘totalitarians’ attack property as vehemently as they attack the divided mind.

    Mansfield rightly describes Montesquieu’s The Spirit of the Laws as “the most comprehensive modern book on politics, exceeding in range and complexity any that appears before or since, excepting Aristotle’s Politics” (215). Montesquieu does not lay down the law, natural or conventional. He considers regimes in order to bring out the “spirit” of each. This procedure enables Montesquieu to move away from spiritedness toward moderation, albeit a moderation quite different from any found in Aristotle. Montesquieu’s moderation has its natural foundation in a mean between two vices, Hobbesian domination and Hobbesian fear. Montesquieu’s moderation is timidity. Moderation’s foundation in civil society is “reason,” that is, a people’s “disposition” (219). Consent is no longer so necessary, because natural freedom is not an issue. Opinion replaces it, but not opinion as Aristotle conceived it. Opinion for Montesquieu is no longer an indirect reflection of rationally knowable truth. Opinion expresses emotions—fear or confidence. “Virtue” is not a passion; “moderation” is dilute passion, possible only in civil society.

    All this leads Montesquieu to a recommend a new kind of executive. “If liberty need not be asserted, free government need not be based on fear, and the executive need not terrify” (222). An independent judiciary becomes possible and desirable. A version of classical virtue may be retained, but it is strictly politicized or conventionalized. Liberty is not in nature. It is in England, an England thoughtfully reformed by Montesquieu to enjoy separation of powers. Political liberty is the feeling-opinion of security. Commerce brings both political liberty and moderation; it dilutes partisan ambitions by rendering them impotent, making Machiavelli’s spectacular punishments unnecessary. “The partisan representative executive is both perfectly constitutional and more reliably self-executing than the natural prerogative held by Locke’s executive—not to mention Machiavelli’s prince” (246).

    The American Founders established a regime embodying many of the principles elaborated by modern political philosophers. But there was no mere discipleship at work. The Founders recognized natural necessity without “draw[ing] the Machiavellian conclusion” (252). They constitutionalized necessity, designed a republican or representative government and a new republican executive as part of it. This executive represents the public while exercising deliberate choice. No Machiavellian prince, neither is he a philosopher-king. “Madison specifies the reason of the public, not of philosopher-kings, as that which ought to prevail” (256). Whereas Aristotle distinguishes deliberation (choosing, taking political responsibility for actions) from judging (“disengaging from politics in order to call these choices into account” [261]), Publius, with other moderns, doubts that this distinction is real, because men are not reliably capable of “the required detachment from their own interests and necessities” (262). Institutional structures are needed to control popular passions and to engage the virtues and abilities of the best. Energy and stability are terms Hamilton borrows from physics (even as Hobbes borrows “power”); however, they do have a moral effect, namely, the public virtues that can develop when political men take responsibility for their actions and have scope for their better ambitions. “In the Constitution, virtue, appears not in its own name but under the rubric of qualifications for office” (274). The very struggle for office the Constitution encourages and limits is “an incitement to excel” (278). Mansfield edifyingly goes so far as to contend that the Constitution encourages public virtue so effectively that America can become, in practice and over time, “an Aristotelian regime formalized in writing” (276). The American regime has moral foundations well concealed by founders who wanted to escape the opprobrium of the epithet ‘moralist,’ and even more wanted to escape the exactions of those who deserve that epithet.

    Mansfield concludes with some observations on the modern executive. “[W]e know now that Machiavelli was wrong: religion is not liberty’s worst enemy” (280). Avowed atheists who execute in the name of the people and with the ready compliance of bureaucrats who only follow orders are liberty’s worst enemies. Or perhaps the philosopher who replaces prudence with cunning is liberty’s worst enemy. Even regimes that retain a republican shape have tended to become mere democracies, complete with passive demi-citizens and charismatic leaders. “[T]he same tendency to sacrifice form to end” that characterizes totalitarian regimes may be seen in contemporary democracies, fortunately in much less virulent form, for now (291).

    “[W]e need a political science capable of discerning responsibility,” an “essentially Aristotelian” political science that “seeks a reconciliation between nature and choice (or end and form), not Machiavellian mastery of nature that turns out to be submission to necessity” (291-292). Contemporary philosophers fail to provide any such reconciliation, alternating instead “between not enough freedom—realism—and too much—idealism” (293). A reconceived executive will understand its “natural law basis in monarchy which it both reflects and attempts to repress” (295). In thus reconceiving the executive we shall begin to rediscover that philosophic monarchy that strives for “the perfection of the soul” (297).

     

    NOTES

    1. The Collected Works of Abraham Lincoln, Roy P. Basler, ed. (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press, 1953, Volume 4, 426.)
    2. The journalist C. L. Sulzberger asked Charles de Gaulle, “What is the primary force governing men in their actions?” “One must draw a distinction,” de Gaulle replied, “between the individual and the collective masses. For the individual it is ambition and a taste for adventure. I think the real motivating force for the individual is ambition, but for the masses it is fear. And this applies to the masses of all countries.” (C. L. Sulzberger: An Age of Mediocrity: Memoirs and Diaries, 1963-1972 [New York: Macmillan, 1973], 189.)

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 172
    • 173
    • 174
    • 175
    • 176
    • …
    • 225
    • Next Page »