Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Hegel: Philosophy Historicized

    February 17, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    In the introduction to The Philosophy of History Hegel takes up the Aristotelian distinction between philosophy and history. Aristotle ranks history below philosophy (and below poetry) because history lacks generality. Hegel replies that the events of history reveal a rational process, that reason is not only prescriptive but productive. To speak theologically, Hegel resolves Aristotle’s history-philosophy distinction, and vindicates history, by claiming that god is not an unmoved mover but a self-moving mover. Hegel’s God is neither Anaxagorean nous nor the Biblical disposer of Providence. ‘God’ or the Absolute Spirit is immanent, moving not only over the waters but within the waters; the waters themselves are congealed or self-alienated, concretized, Absolute Spirit. In Platonic terms, Hegel’s Absolute Spirit amounts to a synthesis of logos and thumos, reason and spiritedness, emerging from the apparently material desires. It is this melding of reason and spiritedness that gives Hegel’s thought its characteristically ‘modern’ (Machiavellian-Cartesian-Baconian) air, that telltale whiff of grapeshot. The mastery of fortune and the conquest of nature remain, redefined as aspects of the dialectical unfolding of the Absolute Spirit as it moves toward the end, the purpose of ‘History.’

    The Absolute Spirit is free (the Rousseauian theme) because self-determined; unlike matter, it is not determined by gravity or anything else. History consists of the working-out of Absolute Spirit. With no false modesty, Hegel claims that the Germans discovered that man as such is free—in contrast with the Greeks, who supposed that only some men are, and in even sharper contrast with the Asians, Africans, and native Americans, who have yet to ascend to even that small degree of self-conscious spiritedness. (For example, the native Americans are said not merely to lack reason but to lack spiritedness, to be merely passive, a mere quantitative mass, like nature itself—and unhistorical therefore.)

    Seeing is not the same as achieving, Hegel sees. Real history, even in Germany, has been a slaughter-bench. Passionate self-seeking coexists in a matrix with eruptions of Absolute Spirit; sometimes, as seen in great men or world-historical individuals, the passion and the eruption coincide. Lesser men follow great men, feeling “the irresistible power of their own Spirit thus embodied”; the life-force philosophy of Nietzsche is here, but still in rationalist form. (Nietzsche is the Rousseau of the Hegelian Enlightenment.) Apparently chaotic historical concatenations are all part of “the cunning [which literally means ‘knowing’] of history,” as the passions of men are gratified but simultaneously and often unwittingly build up the edifice of rationality: the State. Right comes out of this concordia discors of selfish wills, superintended by the Absolute Spirit, which struggles out of matter in the manner of never-finished Michelangelos.

    True freedom is therefore collective, within the State, not ‘bourgeois-individual.’ All individual worth is possessed through the State, as shaped by great men, in the conflictual-thumotic and rational self-development of the national spirits or Volkgeists, themselves particular expressions of the Absolute Spirit. Rousseauian perfectibility comes not according to nature but in contradiction to it, even as nature itself exists only via the Absolute Spirit’s self-alienation. The ascent from the Cave of mere opinion—the most noteworthy achievement of Plato’s philosopher—has been illusory, inasmuch as religion, art, and even philosophy and science are subsumed under the larger category of ‘culture.’ The ‘Idea’ or final manifestation of Absolute Spirit is no mere ‘ideal,’ never to be actualized, but something to be struggled for, achieved conceptually in the thought of G. W. F. Hegel (again, no false modesty), and achieved in politics by the realization of a stable constitutional monarchy buttressed by a bureaucracy whose members will have been culled from the very bourgeoisie that is now merely commercial-selfish. Thus shall logos and thumos triumph together (as they could only do in speech, hitherto) in what might be called an attempted synthesis of Athens and Jerusalem, theory and practice, rationality and providence. That is to say, if Absolute Spirit/ideas are productive, and find their consummation in discourse, then the dreams of sophists and rhetoricians shall be realized, and speech will complete reality; in theological language, words shall become flesh or, more precisely, flesh words.

    The metaphysical connection between man’s freedom/conscious human will and Freedom/Absolute Spirit/historically inevitable dialectical progress may be seen in Hegel’s Logic, to which he refers more than once in his Introduction. To make a long story short, Hegelian logic attempts to account for change; it proceeds dialectically not analytically. Deeper than contradiction is thinking the thing contradicted. To think ‘X,’ and then to think ‘not-X,’ is not to annihilate ‘X’ but to retain both ‘X’ and ‘not-X’ in one’s mind; contradiction simultaneously is and is not ‘X’; we posit as we negate. Hegel avoids subjectivism by saying that this sagacious knowing, and not merely wisdom-loving or philosophic, thinking is the mind of a particular sage. One function of contradiction is to show the impossibility of apartness; everything is part of a Whole. This logic of Becoming contains both Being and Nothing; nothing, or negating, is what keeps Being from inertia. The Absolute Spirit is neither a thing (as is nature for some Greeks) nor a subject (as is the God of the Bible); it is the formation-process of subjects and objects; wisdom is the knowledge of the formation process. This obviates the problems associated with epistemological foundationalism. Hegel is a sage or so-phist, not a philo-sopher, because the whole is itself Proteus-like (and therefore Protagoras-like!), a changeling. Sagacity or wisdom sees the slaughter-bench of history with equanimity, knowing itself to be the final result of the slaughter, physical and intellectual/dialectical. Sagacity satisfies, because the sage embodies the unity of what humans want and need, the grand assimilation of every ‘X’ and ‘not-X.’

    Politically, this means that ‘otherness’ is relational, not destructive, but one must be very cautious here. Hegel is no college administrator, playing a more sophisticated version of ‘Can’t we all just get along?’ by commending the love of ‘diversity.’ Hegel’s idea of a great man in political history is Napoleon, whose assimilations involved real spilt blood.

    Having jettisoned the Biblical God and undermined its own conception of natural right by making nature unteleological (which founders on the ‘is-ought’ problem, as Hume sees), modern thinkers first tried to found morality on natural freedom (Rousseau), then on rationality divorced from nature (Kant). The latter scheme of reason-as-lawmaker runs afoul of the nihilist implications of the universalization principle of the categorical imperative, which, as Hegel remarks, could as well result in the command, ‘Thou shalt steal’ as ‘Thou shalt not….’ ‘History’ is the next way-station, wherein Absolute Spirit replaces the General Will and the Categorical Imperative. The historical ‘struggle for recognition’ replaces the Hobbesian state of nature, but now struggle itself is rationalized, albeit ‘cunningly’ or concealedly.

    The plausibility of Hegel’s magnificent scheme depends on accepting the link between logic and phenomenology: Does Hegel’s point about the logic of contradiction ‘transplant’ to any correct observation about phenomena? It is clear that his process of Spirit alienating itself into matter (its apparent opposite) bears some resemblance to Einstein’s famous equation of matter and energy. But Einstein also accepted the inevitability of entropy, not ‘progress.’ Nor is it entirely clear that the Absolute Spirit is finally any less mysterious, less cloud-shrouded, than the Creator-God of the Bible. How does any thing come to be? If Einstein is right, this process does not need mind. On the level of logic: If the actual is brought into being by the discursive revelation that occurs only after the actual presents itself, how do you avoid linguistic constructivism, and the deconstructivisms that follow in its wake? On the level of theology: If the sage is a sort of mortal God, a mighty Leviathan of the intellect who settles the intellectual war of all against all, is not divinity something you need before you experience totality, not after? If the answer is, ‘We have met God, and he is us,’ this may be an intoxicating or a disappointing revelation, depending upon one’s estimate of men who claim to be gods. Politically, the parallel question is: How much like a (Hegelian) syllogism is political society ever likely to be?

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    Self-Government, the American Theme

    February 16, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Publius calls the American “empire” “the most interesting in the world”: Americans will decide “the important question” of whether “societies of men” can establish “good government by reflection and choice,” not “accident and force.” Can human beings actually govern themselves well? If American prove they can, it will be “a revolution without parallel in human society,” a new order of, and for, the ages. Americans are moderns discontented with previous and existing political orders, ancient and modern, none of which has fulfilled the promise of establishing a political regime that rules according to reason, the distinctively human characteristic.

    Perhaps the primary question concerning the practicability of good self-government is union, not only of the American states but of civil society itself. Divisions among the states, particularly the northern versus the southern, would render Americans “formidable only to each other,” pawns of the great powers. Divisions within civil society can lead to faction, convulsion, insurrection—the violation of the very natural rights that governments are designed to secure. If “liberty is to faction as air is to fire,” then republican civil liberty easily veers toward incivility and to the self-immolation of self-government.

    The “new science of politics” offers inventions of prudence that can control if not eliminate faction. A faction is the opposite of reasonable government. It is a group united by an impulse of passion or of interest averse to the citizens’ rights or to the “permanent and aggregate interests of the community.” “Interest” may be good or bad, but faction can only be bad.

    Hobbes knows how to annihilate faction. End liberty and impose uniform opinions upon everyone. Hobbes’s cure is not only worse than the disease, it is a likely cause of the disease, as Federalist 63 argues. Publius prefers to control faction’s effects by involving “the spirit of party and faction in the necessary and ordinary operations of government,” but in a manner that will enable reason, which is not in itself powerful, to rule faction.

    The problem with self-government, then, is that it contradicts the principle, the interested party must not judge his own case. But without self-government, natural right will be violated, the purpose of government itself nullified. Government must really govern. It must also govern itself. How can public reason control public passion, in government and in society generally?

    Although the causes of faction cannot justly be removed, faction’s effects can be controlled. Republican government itself controls minority factions, inasmuch as republicanism finally rests on popular sovereignty and the opinions of popular majorities., who sooner or later perceive designs against their own interests. But what of majority faction? Central to the tenth Federalist is the observation that “neither moral nor religious motives can be relied on as an adequate control” of majorities that would behave factiously. Democracy—popular government whereby the citizens meet as a body to legislate and judge—will destroy minority rights—most notably the rights of the philosophical, the most reasonable, who may be ‘hemlocked’ one day, memorialized the next.

    The American republic, by contrast, will be unmixed, commercial, extensive, compound, and federal, founded upon consent and the rule of law (i.e., upon reasonableness). Reasonableness is the key: although Madison is not so optimistic as to suppose that a radical Enlightenment, every-man-a-philosopher-king regime could work (“the most rational government will not find it a superfluous advantage to have the prejudices of the community on its side”), reasonableness, government by consent and by law, in part means assent to the self-evident truth of natural right. This is the significance of the Madisonian argument on property as a natural as well as a civil and economic feature of human life. Protection of what is truly ‘one’s own,’ for a human being, is first and foremost the protection of the distinctively human faculties (evident to themselves) and, secondarily, the protection of the fruits of the exercise of those faculties. Reasonable (therefore good because enactive of human nature) self-government starts there.

    An unmixed republic: this is not the Aristotelian/Polybian/British ‘mixed regime,’ with different hereditary classes enshrined in different governmental branches, an arrangement that gives faction (in moral terms, passion) too much official sanction. In the British system, government is sovereign, not the people; the factions in the government divide up the spoils taken from the people. (Hence Paine: the English Constitution’s Bill of Rights is a Bill of Wrongs.) In America, all three branches will be republican, elected by the people or appointed by their elected representatives.

    A commercial republic: this is not a military republic, a Sparta, a Rome (a France, some might mutter, a few years later). As Montesquieu had argued in his Considerations, such regimes destroy themselves by succeeding, as vast conquests lead to the corruption of a free people and finally to the rule of an emperor. Commercial society will yield so many and varying interests that no Caesar can unite them behind him into an overbearing faction.

    An extensive republic: representative government enables the sphere of popular government to be widened, resulting in a bigger ‘talent pool’ of potential representatives, a greater variety of interests. Better representatives will “refine and enlarge the public views,” extracting the reasonable part of public opinion from the passion, ‘amour-propre,’ factional part of it. A greater variety of interests will not coalesce into a single faction, which would lead to neo-Hobbesian calls for non-popular government, fatally compromising popular sovereignty itself and driving a wedge between popular sovereignty and natural right.

    A compound republic: the government will avail itself of the new political science’s argument for separated and balanced powers within the government—roughly equivalent to the multifarious social order. The Constitution will be preserved not only by such moral virtues as the non-angelic representatives may possess, but by such “auxiliary precautions” as connect the interest of the officeholder with the constitutional purpose of the office he holds. Reasonable deal-doing will replace dictatorial passion.

    A federal republic: the government of an extended republic will not ignore or, worse, interfere with the needs of local communities if the state governments share a portion of the people’s sovereignty with the federal government, exercising republican authority over objects known personally (not abstractly but reasonably) to the state legislators. Jefferson’s proposed ‘ward republics’ would enhance this system, although the constitutional function he envisions for them looks cumbersome.

    Jefferson and Paine, though not necessarily Madison, expect the new political science to progress, along with all the other sciences. New and improved constitutions will come. This ‘progressivism’ or learning-by-experience is the ‘liberal’ version of the ‘conservative’ or Burkean appeal to tradition as experience. (Recall Bacon on the superior ‘antiquity’ of modern times.) Paine ripostes that tradition is the wrong kind of experience—experience in corruption, conquest, and tyranny. Going well beyond Madison, Paine believes politics to be unnatural. Like the American Founders, and unlike Rousseau, Paine regards sociality as natural. Left alone, men govern themselves tolerably well in civil society. Despotic governments arose when robber bands conquered the isolated societies of prehistory, inflicting the welfare-taxation state and hereditary usurpation on “the wholesome order of nature.” Fortunately, men can overthrow their oppressors, thereby awakening through conflict, their dormant capacities for self-government. A minimal representative government will imitate “the order and immutable laws of nature, and meets the reason of man in every respect” by selecting men in their prime—not kings, who are so often either too young or too old. Above all, human societies do not need leaders, those apes of military command loosed upon civilians.

    The American Founders do not go so far in Enlightenment optimism as Paine does. One measure of this may be seen in Paine’s sometime preference for a unitary legislature, which Publius rejects because the legislature in a republic will tend to dominate the other branches, and therefore needs to check and balance itself with a bicameral structure. They do not go so far as Kant in their confidence in institutional arrangements; the people and their representative need not be angels, but they had better not be a nation of devils. And they surely do not go so far as Hegel in his confidence in reason, and consequent endorsement of a monarchy-cum-bureaucracy—a regime they would have recognized instantly as a brilliant disguise for some new tyranny, animated by a sort of megalomania. They do not lose reasonableness in a delusive rationalism, and so stay sane.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Discontented Moderns

    February 16, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Rousseau is the first great modern political philosopher discontented with modernity who nonetheless remains a ‘modern.’ He is not Pascal, criticizing modernity in the name of Christianity, or Swift, enlisting in the battle of the books under the banner of the ‘ancients.’

    Rousseau rejects the ‘bourgeois’ or post-Machiavellian turn of modern thought. Machiavelli (with Descartes to follow) despised what he called the effeminacy of ‘modern’—he meant Christian—life. The synthesis of ancient ‘idealism’ and Christianity had led (he charged) to an unworldly, castles-in-the-air irresoluteness among the very classes of men who should stand firm and act severely: the princes in principalities, the citizens in republics. The Prince of Peace had unmanned them, and the philosophers hadn’t been much better. As a result, petty ‘city-states’ squabbled at the very center of what had been a world empire. The Augustinian empire of the papacy, neither fully in nor fully out of the world, had corrupted and replaced the real empire of the original Romans. The Prince of Peace must be replaced by the Prince of War and battle-ready citizens.

    For Montaigne, Hobbes, and Locke, the practical problem looked quite different. Their Europe was wracked by civil wars. The spirit of Machiavelli had joined with the spirit of Christianity to produce militant fanaticism that was frustrating the very spirit of acquisitiveness Machiavelli had intended to foster. These modern philosophers wanted peace; if not effeminacy, then surely a touch of moderation would be a relief. They emphasized the principle of self-preservation in a world all too inclined to Christian jihadism. For this purpose, the practical, vigorous but unwarlike spirit of the commercial classes seemed a welcome touch of sanity in a world of ambitions inflated by the conflation of manliness and religiosity.

    Rousseau understands this. But his heart rebels against it. He is too spirited, too ‘thumotic’ to stomach the halfway-house rule of the commercial classes. Unlike several of the ‘bourgeois’ moderns, he resolutely defends human free will, even if he eventually replaces it with ‘perfectibility.’ Rousseau returns to the manly/spirited origins of modernity, to the Machiavellian polemic against effeminacy and the Cartesian stance of resoluteness. He does so in his own way, however, with an attack on the ‘Enlightenment’ claim that progress in human knowledge will yield, or at least comport with, progress in morality and politics. Although very far from being anti-science, Rousseau does oppose public science, science as a part of public life.

    Rousseau begins the second Discourse with a paean to the republicans of Geneva; he appears to harken back to the virtues of antiquity: severe morals, proud courage, martial spirit, all in a country scaled to human governance. (In this he imitates Machiavelli, who appears to appeal to the example of ancient Rome). But Rousseau soon shows a different hand. The human consists, fundamentally, of two principles: the desire for self-preservation and the sentiment of pity. Enlightenment rationalism is too complex to serve as a constituent of any real society; in this it resembles Machiavelli’s ridiculed builders of castles in the air. Mere sentience is the indispensable foundation for peaceful human life. Rationality, which usually serves vanity or amour-propre instead of natural amour de soi, has thus far only impeded decent human life. A thinking man is a depraved animal. What all men—ancient and modern—have called progress is only an elaborate and dangerous reification of vanity. Rousseau rejects ‘histories’ or books (most notably the Book, the Bible) as unreliable guides—vain in both senses of the word—and instead has recourse to nature, which turns out to mean unassisted human reason.

    Rousseau (in my opinion unwarrantedly) argues that the original human beings were by nature asocial. He needs this claim in order to integrate spiritedness/thumos in a harmless form as free will, and independence (therefore not the libido dominandi) into his concept of human nature. A social being would not be independent. This rhetorical need results in the contorted discussion of how language arose. Paradoxically, this rhetorical need also results in a possibly self-defeating need to say that much of human nature is mere latency—a set of potential characteristics that emerge by the force of chance events channeling human beings into civilized life. Rousseau’s ‘back to nature’ leads to what we later denizens of modernity might call a historicized nature, a nature that is changeable, manipulable. Of course, what is manipulable is also tyrannizable, unfree. Rousseau himself regards natural freedom as irreversibly destroyed. His life’s work is dedicated not to ‘reaction’ or returning to an recoverable past, but to pushing phony progress into real progress, into the reconstitution of freedom in modern society. He too is thus a ‘progressive,’ a man in need of a future. Like all progressives, he finally must sing, thumotically, ‘Tomorrow belongs to me.’ The very tyranny that results from civilization begins to force men to be equal, again, because (as in Hobbes) under tyranny all men but one are equal, even if (unlike Hobbes) Rousseau wants popular not state sovereignty. Moreover, the reason that led us astray also enables at least one philosopher to think his way back into the natural, and thereby prepare to set a path to ‘progress.’

    Such a conception of human nature yields its own monstrosities. In subsequent centuries, we have seen some of them. The Machiavellian, Cartesian, and Rousseauian inspiriting of men to use political means to manipulate course of events in order to reconstitute manliness in some new form, hitherto only latent, has proven overly ambitious, even from a strictly political standpoint. Scientifically, it is by now too late to pretend that human nature is a vague and politically manipulable thing; we know too much about genetics, for example, to suppose that language results exclusively from some train of historical accidents. (Genetics also solves the knotty problem of how to classify orangutans and mandrills, discussed in Rousseau’s Note J.) When it comes to manipulation, it is the scientistic modernity envisioned by Bacon and not that envisioned by the more purely political writers that may prove most formidable.

    Kant’s ‘progressivism’ is more straightforward than Rousseau’s because Kant believes he sees a way towards peace that does not jettison Enlightenment rationalism. The crucial difference is that Kant maintains freedom of will and happiness to be dependent upon the capacity to reason; whereas in Rousseau reason attaches to nature, and thus to the realm of determinism, for Kant reason undergirds the realm of freedom. Reason can and must be a crucial public element in a peaceful social order, although not primarily and immediately. Kant can then claim that human “unsocial sociality” is finally good, part of nature’s ‘plan’ to compel human beings to rise above their own laziness and sleepy or unenlightened peaceableness, through centuries of strife, culminating in an awakened or enlightened ‘perpetual peace.’ This historicized nature teaches the recalcitrant schoolboy, man, “that which reason could have told [him] at the beginning and with far less sad experience.” Kant admits that if he is mistaken, and there is no such historical teleology in nature, then nature is “not far wrong in  preferring the state of savages.”

    To help prevent that dystopian conclusion, Kant advocated what today’s ‘international relations’ specialists call idealism: the formulation of a republican “international government” of “world citizenship.” This a priori creation of the human mind will function as the goal of enlightened statesmen, the Woodrow Wilsons of the future. (It is therefore quite unlike a Platonic eidos, which is hardly a blueprint for future action.) Again unlike Rousseau, Kant optimistically claims or hopes that rational enlightenment will go with “a certain commitment of heart which the enlightened man cannot fail to make to the good he clearly understands.” In this Kant conflates, as Rousseau does not, goodness and morality. Toward this end, a new kind of philosophical historiography is needed, a historiography that will replace previous histories (including the Bible, as seen in his The Conjectural Beginning of Human History) with a narrative of judiciously selected events highlighting the latently ‘enlightened’ features of all previous epochs.

    In my view, Kantian idealism is less practicable, and quite possibly less desirable, than he supposes. The contention that commercial republics—as distinguished from such military republics as ancient Sparta and Rome—do not fight with other commercial republics is sound enough. But the prospect of world government or even “international government” (by which he seems to mean a worldwide federalism) does not portend a civitas of self-governing citizens. Commercial, federal republics have proven their capacity to extend over large territories without losing their republicanism, but a worldwide republic of five or six billion souls strikes me as a chimera. The 300-million-soul version has discontents enough.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 164
    • 165
    • 166
    • 167
    • 168
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »