Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Macedo v. The Constitution

    December 26, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Stephen Macedo: The New Right v. The Constitution. Washington: Cato Institute, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, March 23, 1988.

     

    2017 Note:

    Some three decades later, my reference below to “the Battle of the Bork” may be obscure. Judge Robert Bork was nominated to the Supreme Court by President Ronald Reagan in 1987. At the time he sat on the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit, prior to which position he had held a chair at Yale Law School. He had made enemies a decade earlier, when he took over as Acting Attorney General of the United States after President Nixon ordered the Special Prosecutor Archibald Cox, who was investigating the Nixon Administration’s cover-up of crimes committed by persons working for the Republican Party during the 1972 election—the ‘Watergate’ scandal. U. S. Attorney General Eliot Richardson refused to follow the order and resigned, as did the Assistant A.G., leaving Bork, who was third in line, to execute the order. During his confirmation hearings before the Senate Judiciary Committee, he was questioned closely by members and eventually rejected, partly as revenge for his role in ‘Watergate,’ but mostly on the basis of his conservative approach to Constitutional interpretation, and particularly his critique of the supposed ‘right to privacy’ underlying the Roe v. Wade decision legalizing abortion.

     

    Impassioned, plausible, often telling, as often wrong, this forceful essay carries on the colorful tradition of American Constitutional polemic. Possibly intended as a missile in last year’s Battle of the Bork, it raises questions that will endure long after the ill-fated judge has faded from popular memory.

    “The rise to power of the New Right is the preeminent political phenomenon of the last decade,” Professor Macedo writes, ominously. In Constitutional law, the New Right would cause “a basic revision of the nature of citizenship in America” by exalting majority rule over Supreme Court decisions, thus “narrowing… judicial protections for individual rights.”

    Macedo begins by attacking the “jurisprudence of original intent” proposed by Attorney General Edwin Meese and developed by such scholars as Bork and Gary McDowell. He rehearses the familiar objections: Who counts as a Framer of the Constitution? What’s the hard evidence of their intentions? What do we do about ambiguous language, changing circumstances, Constitutional amendments?

    It must be said that Macedo’s complaints here turn out to be hypocritical. He claims that the Founders themselves rejected “reliance on historical intentions” as an interpretive principle. Obviously, he can make this claim seriously only if he knows what those intentions were—in this case, not to have future generations governed by the Founders’ own intentions. While he is right to say the Founders wanted Americans to engage in “reasoned, legal deliberation” when applying their Constitution to changing circumstances, this in no way abrogates a jurisprudence of original intent, unless one believes the Founders’ intent unreasonable. It is reasonable to suppose the Founders did not find their own deliberations unreasonable, so Macedo’s distinction collapses. Macedo evidently has no knowledge of Emmerich de Vattel’s The Law of Nations, published in 1757 and well-established as a part of American legal education by 1780. Vattel’s long chapter, “The Interpretation of Treaties,” outlines fair-minded principles of contractual interpretation that cut through a great deal of the tendentious blather emitted by academics today. The Founders knew that book.

    Macedo justly criticizes some New Rightists, notably the hapless Bork, for their flirtations with moral relativism, for their dubious defense of ‘traditional moral values’ that rests on traditionalism merely, not transcendent moral principles. New-Right majoritarianism follows from this odd mix of skepticism and sentimentalism, both of which incline toward letting majorities do whatever they will. “The Framers were not simple democrats, but republicans who rejected the idea that popular government is necessarily good government.” Macedo sees that “moral abstractions, such as rights and justice, did play a central role in the minds of the Founders”—another unintended nod to intent, it should be noted—and do form an essential part of America’s constitutional tradition.”

    The merits of this argument make it all the more unfortunate that Macedo misstates the principles of American constitutionalism in so many other respects. First, he evidently believes the Supreme Court must stand alone in defending individual rights. He ignores the central institutional principle of American republicanism, representation. As James Madison repeatedly emphasizes, each branch of our federal government consists of officials elected by the people or appointed (or elected) by their representatives. Representative government, by refining and enlarging the public views, along with the power balance among the three branches, prevents most systematic abuses of citizens’ natural rights; Supreme Court decisions form only part of this system. It is precisely because their representatives have preferred to let the courts and the bureaucracy overrule the common decencies of normal citizens that New-Right populism has proven so attractive. Representative government needs revival, not Court-ly burial.

    It is true that two major institutional checks on federal government power, federalism and the indirect election of presidents and senators, have weakened drastically since the amendments added during the Progressive era. Macedo regards the Supreme Court as the best realistic check on abuse of individual rights by the federal executive and legislative branches. He overlooks the Court’s own role in (mis)interpreting those amendments as warrants for vast federal intrusions into states’ rights, and for the unconstitutional principle of ‘one person, one vote.’ If the federal government has gone too far, the Court all too often has led the way. Why would that Court prove a dependable guardian in the future?

    Macedo is a libertarian. He wants the Court to defend liberty on moral issues (pornography, homosexuality) and on economic issues, too. He closely identifies liberty with morality itself, and with community, too. His belief that “liberty and community, finally, are not opposed,” that “a society of free, tolerant individuals is the best form of community,” resembles nothing so much as the 1962 Port Huron Statement, the founding document of the ‘New Left.’ Macedo is Tom Hayden in Izod Lacoste.

    In one sense, this is an improvement. Today’s libertarian works to earn his money instead of marrying it. But in place of the New Left’s sentimental egalitarianism, libertarians offer nothing at all. The American Founders fought for the proposition that all men are created equal, that human rights come from human nature itself. Libertarians don’t want to hear about human nature, or the Creator-God who endows human beings with unalienable rights. Nature and God would restrict liberty, if liberty is defined as doing as one likes.

    By maximizing the principle of liberty, libertarians finally undermine toleration and constitutionalism themselves. God and nature set the limits that make liberty meaningful. Without such limits, libertarians can aver “sympathy for all that is human,” but they cannot say what humanity is.

    Constitutionally, libertarianism logically yields not judicial authority but anarchy, whereby each federal official may interpret the Constitution for himself and act accordingly. Macedo sees this and approves of it, thus deflating his own argument, absent any sense of representative government based upon a firm idea of human nature.

    Filed Under: American Politics