Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    The Real Anti-Racism

    October 30, 2024 by Will Morrisey

    Andre Archie: The Virtue of Color-Blindness. Washington: Regnery Gateway, 2024.

     

    With the United States at “a crossroads when it comes to race relations,” its citizens hesitating about whether to adhere to its longtime defense of the natural rights of individuals or to endorse “anti-racism” in the form of group rights, Professor Archie urges conservatives to “join me in reclaiming a noble racial tradition: color blindness.” As a scholar whose work has centered on classical political philosophy (he has published a monograph of Plato’s Greater Hippias), he knows that virtue “comes through practice and habit;” “we become morally good by performing actions that embody moral qualities.” “Natural, sympathetic relations among Americans” can develop if we guide our practice and habituation by the principle of color-blindness, conserving “the hard-won gains achieved on the racial front by reminding ourselves of the spirit of 1776 and 1863.” The emancipation of slaves followed from the color-blind principle of the American Revolution, that all men are created equal in their natural rights, as individuals of one species, one kind, regardless of skin color. So did the gains made by the civil rights movement, two generations ago.

    Yet “I cannot think of any contemporary author on the Left or Right who doesn’t think the color-blind approach is at least outdated and probably naive.” (I can think of several but let the claim pass as generally true.) Beyond the chattering classes, “the false accusation of systemic racism has now been embraced by titans of the tech and financial industries,” while “color-blindness, a once commonplace approach to race relations, is now considered heresy.” Accordingly, U.S. Supreme Court Chief Justice John Roberts caused a stir in a 2007 opinion in which he ventured to suggest, “The way to stop discrimination on the basis of race is to stop discriminating on the basis of race” by means of ‘affirmative action.’ As Archie elaborates, “To be color-blind is to understand that an individual’s or a group’s racial membership should be irrelevant when choices are made or attitudes formed.” But for a long time, American conservatives have “failed to see just how corrosive and revolutionary the anti-color-blind pedagogy is.”

    On the Supreme Court, Justice John Marshall Harlan called the Constitution “color-blind” in his dissent in the wrongly decided 1896 case, Plessy v. Ferguson, which upheld laws enforcing racial segregation. The Constitution, Harlan wrote, “neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens,” who “are equal before the law” when it comes to civil rights because “the law regards man as man.” But, as Archie writes, “racial segregation has returned in full, ugly force” via “the diversity training industry,” a “Trojan horse for far more insidious racial doctrines like Critical Race Theory and ‘Antiracism.'” The “true intention” of this industry is “to promote intimidation and psychological control over concerned, but racially passive white Americans.” That is, diversity training, affirmative action, and the like are instruments of rule, rule by a new ruling class in alliance with existing business and academic elites playing divide-and-rule against Americans by “encourag[ing] racial balkanization on the part of blacks and whites,” thereby undermining a hitherto republican regime animated by “a sense of American identity.” Archie sets as his goal “to reacquaint Americans” with the tradition of color-blindness “and to fight against modern-day segregationists.”

    The false anti-racists of the ‘Woke’ ideology charge that Western civilization has been racist from the start. A classicist has no difficulty batting that down, citing Frank M. Snowden Jr.’s scholarship concluding “that classical antiquity was familiar with black people through black-skinned Ethiopians and Nubians, and that neither the Greeks nor the Romans expressed racial animosity toward either.” Classical moralists centered on character, the ethos of individuals and peoples, asking what is the best way to live, not what complexion one might have. Their moral theory was “person-centered.” Modern moral theory has emphasized not virtue but “criteria for selecting the best action,” whether those criteria were ‘deontological’ (e.g., Kant’s categorical imperative) utilitarian. Utilitarianism is especially “susceptible to attributing moral status to ascriptive qualities like race” because the principle of utility cannot “prevent race or racial characteristic from being used as a criterion in deciding whether or not an action produces the greatest amount of utility, happiness, or well-being.” When the Reverend Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., wanted to be judged by the content of his character, not the color of his skin, he appealed to the principle of classical morality, not that of the moderns, as that personalism has been affirmed by Christianity, whose Founder commands, “Do unto others as you would have others do unto you.” “Character is everything. It’s all you really have at the end of the day.”

    Frederick Douglass had already articulated decisive arguments against the claim that American racism is “systemic” in principle. As a former slave, he could have no doubt that “in the nineteenth century, discrimination against African Americans was factually systemic. Even after the abolition of slavery, “emancipation and reconstruction promised very little in the face of organized violence, political and economic marginalization, and segregation that blacks experienced.” Nevertheless, Douglass never conceded that the United States Constitution and the philosophic principles behind it were anything less than color-blind. In this, he opposed the claims of the prominent Abolitionist agitator, William Lloyd Garrison, who stigmatized the Constitution as a “covenant with death” and the American founding as designed to perpetuate slavery. “Garrison believ[ed] that the Founding documents were anti-black through and through.” Douglass believed no such thing.

    “Garrison’s constitutional beliefs were, fundamentally, informed by his acceptance of perfectionism,” the belief that human beings can be purged of their sins and that, “through will and faith, man can achieve perfection on earth” through obedience to Christ. Renouncing human government as an unnecessary hierarchy, Garrison also rejected the warfare governments undertake, advocating “nonresistant pacifism.” Garrison’s analysis of law was, accordingly, positivist; laws express only the ruling opinion of the regime that sets it down—in the United States, majority opinion. Human law has no real underpinning in the laws of Nature and of Nature’s God. Unsurprisingly, then, the Constitution should be regarded as a pro-slavery document because it includes the ‘three-fifths’ and fugitive slave clauses. And before it, the Articles of Confederation had relegated slavery to the status of an issue to be decided by the states, a feature the Constitution did not eliminate. In the 1850s, Garrison pushed for secession—secession of the Northern states from union with the slaveholding South. This was in keeping with his moral perfectionism; secession would have done nothing to put slavery on the road to extinction, but it would have made Abolitionists feel purer.

    Douglass initially concurred. But in 1851, having read the arguments of abolitionists Gerrit Smith, Lysander Spooner, and William Goodell, he began to see the Preamble to the Constitution as the link between the supreme law of the land and the laws of Nature and of Nature’s God cited in the Declaration. Congressman Smith had turned his hometown of Peterboro, New York into a center of anti-slavery activity, particularly the Underground Railroad; Douglass dedicated My Bondage and My Freedom to him. Spooner, and ally of Smith, was an Abolitionist anarchist, opposed to the Constitution because opposed to governments generally, but still moved to write The Unconstitutionality of Slavery, a book on the Constitution as an anti-slavery document. Goodell, a New York publisher and 1852 Liberty Party candidate for the presidency, held similar convictions. “Their racial advocacy and intellectual focus on behalf of helping black Americans achieve equality before the law were quite remarkable,” and Archie doubts “that the Frederick Douglass we revere so much today would have achieved the status he presently occupies without having been shaped by the ideas he inherited from these men.” They, in turn, had consulted the writings of the great English jurist, William Blackstone, who considered the law of nature as the foundation of English common law. “Unlike positive law, the law of nature is unhistorical,” valid everywhere human beings exist, and so long as they do. The law of nature “exists objectively both as a norm for individuals, communities, and the state, and as a limiting principle in the political arena where objective right could be repudiated by the legislator.” Blackstone in turn derived his natural law principles from John Locke, who argues that the natural law supports the individual’s natural rights to life, liberty, and property.

    As one of the greatest orators of his time, Douglass understood that those opposed to slavery and to the racism of its advocates (notably, Senator John C. Calhoun and his disciples, including then-Senator and future Confederate States of America president Jefferson Davis) would best win hearts as well as minds by showing Americans that their country was founded upon the anti-slavery principles of natural law. Nor was this a mere rhetorical ploy. In the 1805 case, United States v. Fisher, Chief Justice John Marshall had written, “Where rights are infringed, where fundamental principle are overthrown, where the general system of the law is departed from, the legislative intention must be expressed with irresistible clearness, to induce a court of justice to suppose a design to affect such objects.” As a member of the founding generation, Marshall understood the fundamental principle of the Constitution he was interpreting to be the natural law; in Archie’s words, if a law under review by the Court is “ambiguous or simply unclear, and can be interpreted in line with natural rights or in opposition to natural rights, the interpretation consistent with natural rights is the meaning that should be given to the words under consideration.” Smith, Spooner, and Goodell were in good legal company, and by 1851 Douglass had joined them.

    Their most distinguished ally at the time was the Free-Soil Party United States Senator from Ohio, Salmon P. Chase. “Chase held two political beliefs that especially appealed to Douglass: that slavery “perverted the idea of labor” by “pitting slave labor against free labor” and thereby diverting the government from its rightful task of securing unalienable natural rights; and that slavery’s extension into western territories “posed a mortal threat to republican government” by bringing the anti-republican, oligarchic regime of slaveholders to the western states, which would then ally themselves with the Southern state oligarchs. But, as the Northwest Ordinance had shown, “the Federal government has the power to outlaw slavery in all Federal territories” and thus to defend American republicanism against its enemies. As a founder of the Republican Party, a few years later, Chase helped to insert these Constitutional arguments against slavery into the 1856 and 1860 platforms. 

    Concluding his refutation of claims that the United States has always exhibited “systemic” racism, racism valorized by the principles of the regime, Archie endorses Douglass’s approach. “For right-thinking African Americans what America is and what it stands for has never been the issue: the issue has been to get America to stand by the principles expressed in the Declaration of Independence, the Preamble to the constitution and the Constitution itself.”

    In the second third of his book, Archie turns, with more than a touch of distaste, to what he rightly terms the “sophistry” of the principal publicists for pseudo-anti-racism, whose arguments pervade the African-American Studies programs in American universities and colleges. “A narrative of separateness has been their constant refrain from the beginning: The United States and its history is irredeemably racist and exploitative. Slavery is America’s original sin.” Not only African-American Studies departments, but ethnic studies generally “have played an influential role both in academia and in undermining an American identity that is grounded in color-blind principles and transcends race.” For a professor of classical philosophy, a certain impatience with the flyweight intellectuals of Wokeness is understandable and, sure enough, Archie quotes Socrates in Plato, dissing the poets: “the more poetic they are, the less they should be heard.” And Socrates was talking about the likes of Homer and Aristophanes, not Derrick Bell, Ta-Nehisi Coates, Ibran X. Kendi, or Robin Di Angelo. So, to the critic who might chide, “Archie, you are no Socrates,” the professor might reply, “and the likes of these are no Aeschyluses.”

    The late Professor Bell wrote Race, Racism, and American Law and Faces at the Bottom of the Well: The Permanence of Racism. A law professor, he replaced the Founders’ principle of natural right and the Progressive’s principle of historical growth with Critical Race Theory. As a short story writer (as it were on the side), he sought to dramatize that theory. Bell claims that racism is permanent in American because “it serves the material and psychic interests of both white elites and working-class whites,” an argument that Douglass had already rejected on the materialist side and worked to correct on the personal side by pointing to the repeatedly expressed opinions of the American Founders and their latter-day allies in the Abolitionist and Free-Soil movements. But, as Archie remarks, Bell prefers a “politically motivated, results oriented, and anti-color blind” use of law “to practice positive discrimination,” i.e., discrimination on the basis of skin color, now for the benefit of people of color. He has the practical sense to understand that African Americans will only make real advances “if white America sees its interest as also advancing at the same time”—a “power dynamic” Bell calls “Interest Convergence,” not unlike the ‘Convergence Theory’ left-wing Americans proposed during the Cold War, in their (futile) attempt to reconcile the United States and the Soviet Union. But whereas the color-blind approach brings ‘whites’ to frame their mutual self-interest with ‘black’ and ‘brown’ Americans within the framework of natural rights, and thereby the dignity of persons, the anti-color-blind approach works to reduce ‘whites’ to shameful and silent acquiescence. “The abolitionist movement alone is a counter narrative to Bell’s Interest Convergence thesis and its assumption that African Americans lack agency to improve their own well-being in America, but “Bell has no interest in historical facts, nor is he interested in racial fraternity.” Bell prefers to tell “subjective and preachy” stories of Caucasian oppression. “For no other group in America, except for white Americans, would we tolerate the wholesale racial demonization of a group.”

    Journalist Ta-Nehesi Coates’s Between the World and Me taps “the thrill of militancy.” Coates writes in the line of James Baldwin’s polemic, The Fire Next Time, a work in what Archie calls “the exhortative tradition” of black American literary production. The book consists of a series of letters to Coates’s adolescent son, calling ‘white’ people (as Coates himself puts it) “destroyers” who enforce “the whims of our country.” These whims extend to putatively rational enterprises: “You must always remember that the sociology, the history, the economics, the graphs, the charts, the aggression all land, with great violence, upon the body.” Take that, Margaret Mead. “Here we see Coates’s tendency to exaggerate for literary effect,” Archie observes, understatedly. Although addressing his son, Coates keeps a careful eye on his ‘white’ readers, “speak[ing] to a deep vulnerability in the national psyche of Americans, especially elite white Americans,” hoping that they will behave rather as a previous generation of rich Manhattanites were persuaded to fund The Nation —the sort of behavior Tom Wolfe satirized in Radical Chic. By tapping into such sentiments, Coates hopes to sucker ‘whites’ into paying ‘reparations’ to ‘people of color,’ the least they can do to redress past and present abuses. Reparations are the obvious consequence of group rights (and of group wrongs). Archie brings a bit of sanity to the fore, recognizing that while “the majority of African Americans were introduced to America through slavery…they were not permanently scarred by the experience of slavery” and so “are not in need of constant moral cheerleading from their betters,” to say nothing of constant monetary restitution. 

    History professor Ibrahim X. Kendi explains How to Be an Antiracist, not a mere non-racist, which simply won’t do, in his eyes. “His ideology and the political movement it represents are, on the most basic level, antithetical to individual autonomy and the individual right enshrined in the Bill of Rights”; the practical upshot of his pseudo-anti-racism entails denial of freedom of conscience and civil liberties to “blatant racists.” In Kendi’s words, “if discrimination is creating equity, then it is antiracist.” The problem, Archie remarks, is that racially discriminative laws, however well-intended (and that is questionable), contribute to “the modern segregationist trends we see today in any parts of our society,” the valorization of “affinity groups” that “foster divisiveness, mainly along the lines of race, gender, and sexuality.” As an academic, Archie deplores the policy of requiring college and university employees and students to sign “diversity statements,” even before they are allowed to enter academia. Such statements are the contemporary equivalent to the confessions of faith churches and church-related institutions once required of prospective members. The articles of the new faith are simple: “systematically racist” America, ruled by ‘whites,’ aims at exploiting ‘peoples of color. Such injustice can only be remedied by “various schemes to socially engineer desired outcomes” under the assumption that “if it weren’t for discrimination, the achievements and outcomes of various racial groups would be random or even.” Against this claim, Archie points to the research of the economist Thomas Sowell, who attributes economic and social differences among various ethnic groups to their “cultural traits,” their habits of mind and heart, especially those that either encourage or discourage adaptation to changes in demand for certain types of labor and for the skills required to perform them. 

    Robin Di Angelo, a professor of “multicultural education” at Westfield State University, wrote White Fragility: The Challenges of Talking to White People About Racism. “White fragility,” a term she coined, adroitly bathes ‘whiteness’ in the waters of condescension, putting her fellow Caucasians firmly in their place. It serves as a rhetorical expression of her “abiding disdain for enlightenment concepts such as neutrality, objectivity, impartiality equality, individualism, and formalism”—the whole roster of ‘postmodernist’ bugbears. Bathwater, baby, Archie replies: “Despite the fact that the European Enlightenment as a political movement had some drawbacks”—you know, the Jacobin Terror during the French Revolution—such concepts as “objectivity and impartiality, mostly in the context of law, were crucial to the modern era’s efforts at extending the notion of equality to broader segments of the population in Western societies,” as seen in the Declaration of Independence and indeed in the earliest phase of the French Revolution. In her book, and in her work as a “diversity trainer,” Di Angelo exhibits “the ugliest aspects of tribalism and racial atavism” as “good and necessary in the quest to heighten the racial consciousness”—a.k.a. ‘wokeness’—of “her intended audience: the white middle upper class.” She dislikes individualism, and rights held by individuals, on the basis of the age-old structuralist argument that says the naive among us believe that their actions are due to their own efforts, and that the ascriptive qualities that define them socially—race, class, gender—have very little sway over how they exercise their capacities to express themselves, to express their characters, as they see fit as individuals.” On the contrary, human beings “belong to groups first and foremost,” groups that “define how we see ourselves, as individuals, in relation to other groups.” This supposed fact is supposed to make “the relations between white Americans and people of color, particularly black Americans, as a zero-sum contest for economic and political power,” with ‘whites’ having taken most of the marbles, so far. ‘Whites’ are “biased,” given their superior economic, social, and political position, which imposes the wrong moral and intellectual perspective upon them. This is where the classicist Archie might recall the work of Numa Denis Fustel de Coulanges (no democrat, he), who described in his book, The Ancient City, the way in which the small, closed poleis of antiquity assiduously framed a nearly airtight set of civil-religious beliefs upon their citizens, before those naughty philosophers arose to subvert the laws. ‘Whites’ are analogous to such citizens, Di Angelo in effect argues, and she is the subversive philosopher. But the hemlock will be served to her fellow ‘whites,’ who will be required to call it ambrosia. 

    Whatever the differences between the classical political philosophers and the Enlightenment philosophes —and they are considerable—they share an interest in setting “epistemic standards that govern the relationships between groups” in ‘the city,’ the political community. “Rational discourse” requires that “we put aside, or bracket, our differences in order to be impartial or neutral with regard to our own biases and predilection” in order to “rise above” them—a more modest version of the Socratic-Platonic ascent from the cave. In contemporary America, “relationships are fraught with confusion, tension, and posturing when they are governed by irrational standards that essentialize individuals based upon their racial characteristics,” but those are the standards “the diversity training industry operates under.” With those standards in hand, the legerdemain begins, as the diversity trainer frames “questions or issues in a specific way to enhance the chances of achieving a desired end,” very much in the manner of the slightly older techniques deployed in ‘values clarification’ school exercises. [1] Despite the pretense of dialectical questioning, “the diversity trainer’s main goal is to quiet white people by conducting the session under the assumptions that all black people experience racism, whether they know or not, and that white people just can’t relate to such experiences.” (In this, diversity training mimics feminist ‘sensitivity training,’ with its assumption that men, renamed ‘males’ for the occasion, are insensitive brutes which, like brutes, better not open their snouts.) Meanwhile, “skeptical blacks”—Professor Archie may have been one of them?—are “shamed into not speaking out in disagreement with the trainer or the racial victimhood narrative that’s told, and, most important, white attendees now feel duty bound to remain quiet or they will be ostracized and called out.” It is as if John Locke’s “law of opinion” has been redeployed for decidedly un-Lockean ends. Lockean-liberal toleration has no place in the new illiberalism, which permits “no tolerance for alternative points of view, nor tolerance for any point of view other than the official racial line.” Jim Crow redivivus, with the bottom rail on top, this time. 

    To restore the virtue of color-blindness, Archie appropriates a phrase of Roger Scruton’s, “oikophobia” or fear of one’s own, giving it a new application. Classical political philosophy and Enlightenment rationalism both moderated inordinate love of one’s own. (In the case of some Enlighteners, they moved to suppress it altogether, leading to the reaction of nationalism.) In contemporary politics, we now see the opposite of the love of one’s own. The Oikophobe or, abbreviatedly, the Oik, has unmoored himself, or has been unmoored from, his “native soil, home, community, and country.” “Think of it as an imperious attitude toward his compatriots, coupled with a radicalization of the spirit of democracy,” extreme egalitarianism. He prefers the foreign enemy to his fellow-citizen, as when the Left sympathizes with Islamist terrorists who would line them up for a throat-cutting, given the opportunity. “The Oik has a deep disdain for America, its way of life, and its institutions”—its regime. To put it in Platonic terms, as Archie is happily wont to do, the ‘identity politics’ of the Left subordinates the economics-based analyses of the Old Left, its emphasis on the needs of the body and the cravings of the appetites, for the spirited passions of the thymotic aspect of the human soul. For this reason, “it’s no longer enough” for Americans “to appeal to a creedal identity in the way Martin Luther King Jr. and the civil rights movement did,” although it is necessary to continue to do so. “The other part of the American identity is cultural,” a matter of families, neighborhoods, and local “associations,” as Tocqueville calls them. Abraham Lincoln understood that, citing the principles of the Declaration of Independence in the Gettysburg Address but also the “mystic cords of memory” in his First Inaugural Address because “the principles and way of life animated by the spirit of 1776 is both felt and believed in,” felt especially in “a particular geographic location, among a particular culture, and among a particular people.” Conservatives have long admired Edmund Burke’s invocation of the “little platoons” that foster humane sentiments, sociality without ‘socialism” and indeed without any ‘ism,’ any ideology (very much including racism) that abstracts from the humanity of humans. Such little platoons need to be tempered by reasoned thought, both prudential and theoretical, if they are not to become thoughtless. Americans have reasoned together in the past, and they are capable of doing so again.

     

    Note

    1. On ‘values clarification’ and its ideological uses, see Paul Eidelberg and Will Morrisey: Our Culture, ‘Left’ or ‘Right’: Litterateurs Confront Nihilism (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1992), chapter 5, “Self-Made Moralism: John Dewey and ‘Values Clarification.'” The main difference between values clarification and diversity training is that values clarifiers assumed a pose of moral relativism or neutrality, as befit latter-day heirs of modern rationalism, while diversity trainers wear no such mask, as befits ‘postmodernism.’

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Regime Changes in Local Government: Democracy in America?

    October 23, 2024 by Will Morrisey

    Everett Kimball: State and Municipal Government in the United States. Boston: Ginn and Company, 1922.

    Alexis de Tocqueville: Democracy in America. Volume I, Part 1, Chapter 5. Harvey C. Mansfield and Delba Winthrop translation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press 2000.

     

    In the United States, Tocqueville remarks, the people are the rulers, and it is local government that gives Americans the political experience to make their rule reasonable—unlike the circumstances of France after its revolution, where a centralized state under a monarchic regime had foreclosed such experience, leading to catastrophe when the people attempted to rule. Even more fundamentally, local government matters because it embodies political life itself. “The township is the sole association that is so much in nature that everywhere men are gathered a township forms by itself—so much so, that the township “appears to issue directly from the hands of God.” With Aristotle, Tocqueville regards human beings as political by nature.

    Nevertheless, freedom in a township is “rare and fragile.” The township is coarse, not entirely civilized, less based on reason than on experience. It “develops almost secretly in the bosom of a half-barbaric society.” It may well begin as a regime not of the people but of a chieftain, or of a warrior-oligarchy. Still, it is “in the township that the force of free peoples resides,” since township institutions “are to freedom what primary schools are to science,” schools of “political education.” It is small enough (in America, usually about 2,000 in population) for the people to rule it directly, thereby “habituat[ing] them to making use” of freedom,” to cultivate “the spirit of freedom.” True, the people are “the source of social powers” everywhere; even in an empire ruled by a tyrant, they might rise up and overthrow their tormentor. “But nowhere do they exercise their power more immediately,” nowhere else are they “a master.” 

    New England townships exemplify this direct rule by the people. No municipal council, no elected representatives, legislate for the township; the people do, in the annual town meeting. The representatives or “selectmen” elected at the meeting administer the laws without enjoying any authority to set policy or to impose taxes. They are personally responsible to the people for their conduct in office. A township may have fewer than twenty selectmen, including parish commissioners (who make expenditures for worship services), a constable, a clerk, a cashier or treasurer, an overseer of the poor, and a road inspector. None of these men receives a salary, only commissions. Residents obey them because they are necessary and useful to the maintenance of the township—matters involving personal injury or the need for cooperation—but they otherwise rule themselves in the many matters concerning only themselves. In New England, “political life was born in the very bosom of the townships; one could almost say that each of them at its origin was an independent nation”—rather like the poleis or ‘city-states’ of antiquity. And they remain independent in relation to the states, except when the need for cooperation arises; to meet such needs, the state can require townships to collect taxes for its legitimate purposes. That is, the township’s relation to the states parallels the individual’s relation to the township. “It acts, it is true, in a circle that it cannot leave, but its movements within [that circle] are free.” It is “a free and strong corporation that one is a part of and that is worth his trouble to seek to direct”; it conduces to political rule. Americans are citizens, not subjects of the state. 

    Under the British Empire, the American colonies partook not of aristocratic freedom—full political life for the few—but of what Tocqueville calls bourgeois and democratic freedom. The people exercised the right to vote, including the right to vote for or against the taxes they paid; the authority to impose responsibility on those who governed them; individual freedom; the right to be policed by persons selected by the residents; the right to trial by a jury of their peers. To borrow the title of James Monroe’s book, the people were the sovereigns. [1] From 1650 on, townships were organized before the counties, counties before the colonies (the eventual states), and colonies-states before the Union. Unlike the colonial governments, they were always democratic and republican. But the people are far from unruly democrats. The existence of locally ruled parishes shows how the people transmit moral principles from one generation to the next. “In America, it is religion that leads to enlightenment, it is the observance of divine laws that guides man to freedom.” The eminent New England clergyman, Cotton Mather, defined freedom as Aristotle did, not as doing as one likes but in doing what is just and good. The spirit of religion comports with the spirit of individual and political freedom, with “Heaven in the other world and well-being and freedom in this one.” Political life in America is a “field left by the Creator to the efforts of intelligence.”

    As a result, with the American Revolution, “the dogma of the sovereignty of the people came out of the township and took hold of the government” of the states and the federal government. And the sovereign people were well thus prepared for self-government at the state and federal levels.

    Writing more than eighty years after Tocqueville, looking back over the Civil War and the subsequent Constitutional amendments (especially the Fourteenth), the municipal reform movement, and Progressivism, Smith College political historian Everett Kimball describes municipal institutions as they were in New England and throughout the country in the early years of the regime and as politicians altered them in subsequent decades. Evidently in light of those events, unlike Tocqueville, he regards the states as “all-important in determining the powers and responsibilities of the smaller units of local government”; the right of popular sovereignty has shifted its locus to the state and national populations. Perhaps as a result of this partial centralization of government, “all constitutions have grown longer” and professionalized civil service has partly replaced government by political party appointees. (In 1890s New York City, he shudders, not only did Tammany Hall receive substantial monetary contributions from business corporations but it established “regular tariffs” for “saloons, gambling-houses, and houses of ill-fame. Pickpockets actually “paid for the privilege of operating unmolested in certain localities”—an arrangement, one suspects, that may prevail to this day in languorous New Orleans.) The United States has seen a “changed spirit” of the laws. “Rightly or wrongly, the demand has been made upon the state that greater and increasing care should be given for the public safety, the health of the community, the poor, and the defective, as well as for the conservation of the public resources and improvement of public comfort and well-being.” [2] Institutionally, this has led states to establish “a constantly increasing number of new boards and commissions.” Operating under “a changed conception of the function of government,” officials staffing these new ruling offices “perform the multitudinous functions which the modern state undertakes,” along with substantially more numerous (and almost always unelected) administrators within the several departments of the executive branch. State government functions now include law enforcement, education, public charity, prisons, public health, agriculture, labor law, and corporate law (“the regulation of industrial relations and the whole law of labor is a modern development,” superseding “the doctrine of noninterference” that prevailed for most of the nineteenth century). “The most striking and alarming feature of state finance is the rapid increase of state expenditures.” At the time Kimball wrote, revenues for these efforts came primarily from property taxes, but states were also taxing income, inheritances, and corporate profits. 

    How have county and municipal governments adapted themselves, and how have they been adapted by the states, given the accumulation of ruling authority within the state and federal governments? Kimball begins his history of local government in the United States with the Saxon shire. With the fifth-century Anglo-Saxon settlement in Wessex and the subsequent spread of Anglo-Saxon rule throughout England, shires were governed by royally appointed “shire reeves” or sheriffs, complete with courts, pervaded the country. The counties (which “grew out of the shire”) “retained a large degree of administrative control” of the royal subjects, thanks to 20 to 60 “justices of the peace” who tried civil but not criminal cases and oversaw roads, bridges, county property, and levied taxes. The counties wielded no legislative powers, however. As Tocqueville saw in America, parishes served as parallel ruling institutions, eventually (when Henry VIII established the Anglican Church against Rome), assuming “care of the poor” but also recruiting armed men for the crown, thus illustrating the Machiavellian-statist propensities of the Tudor dynasty. Parish officials were elected by local landholders, and while in England such local control of local government declined with state centralization in the seventeenth century, in the American colonies it remained as before.

    In those colonies, county governments settled into three patterns corresponding to the three geographical regions. In the South, freeholders elected delegates to the general colonial assembly, which “took no part directly in the management of the affairs of the county,” which was administered by a lord lieutenant, a sheriff, and justices of the peace, as in England. “In theory and practice the government of the counties was undemocratic and oligarchical,” since the courts “became almost self-perpetuating corporations” and the judges “suggested to the [royal] governor the candidates for lord lieutenant, sheriff, and their fellow justices.” Such regimes made sense in the absence of large towns and the consequent inconsequence of a middle class; “the plantations were large and scattered, and each planter on his estate assumed many of the duties which were ordinarily performed by agents of local government.” That is, plantation oligarchs resembled, and often thought of themselves as the equivalents of, feudal lords. The parishes “had few duties other than ecclesiastical and were overshadowed in local administration by the powers of the county.” In New England, by contrast, towns rather than counties predominated, governed by the people in the meetings Tocqueville admired and administered by the selectmen, constables, and town clerks Tocqueville describes, a few decades after Americans won their independence. Kimball observes a similar civic effect, as well, deeming discussions at the meetings of his own time to be “have great educative value in self-government,” with participants exhibiting “great native shrewdness and often considerable skill in debate.” For their part, the Middle Colonies saw “a mixed system of local government,” with “the towns [being] more important than the parishes in the South” and enjoying “a considerable degree of autonomy.” Kimball focuses on New York, where elected county boards of town supervisors consisting of one freeholder elected from each town in the county “supervis[ed] the levy and assessment of the local taxes for country purposes.” The county elected the colonial legislators. The Middle Colonies also saw the formation of boroughs “chartered by the colonial governor as the crown’s representative.” The borough’s charter “prescribed the form of government”—typically consisting of a mayor appointed by the governor, borough councilmen elected by the freeholders, and aldermen appointed by the councilmen, all meeting in a borough council. In New Jersey to this time, many local municipalities are called ‘boroughs’ and are governed by borough councils.

    “The colonists were fairly well satisfied with their system of local government; they had as much control over their affairs as did the people of England, and in New England it was even greater…. Consequently, after the Declaration of Independence and the formation of the state governments, few changes were made in these institutions.” As Americans pushed westward to the Mississippi, they took their local government institutions with them, “following the parallels of latitude”: settlers in the Northwest Territory (including Abraham Lincoln’s and Stephen Douglas’s Illinois) saw democracy in the form of town meetings; Indiana and Ohio “adopted the mixed form of local government”; Kentucky and Tennessee “took over the Virginia system of country government.” However, event in the ‘middle’ and southerly territories and states, “the principle of popular election was emphasized, and the governments were far more democratic,” with “the choice of the local officials” firmly placed “in the hands of the whole people rather than in those of the taxpayers.” The regional factions that eventuated in civil war may be seen in these local regime differences of northeastern, middle, southern, and western states, with the latter providing the military and political ‘tipping point’ during the war and the decade prior to the war.

    Although by Kimball’s 1920s, “centralizing tendencies are everywhere seen,” with “state control or supervision [making] great headway,” a substantial degree of decentralization remains, more so “than [in] any other country.” Urbanization concentrates populations, leading to levels of disease and poverty difficult for cities to address by themselves; corruption also sparks demands for outside assistance from higher authorities. “In the South the presence of large negro populations has led the state authorities to exercise closer supervision and greater control in the interests of efficient administration of law and justice.”

    Within each state, the county remains “the largest district for local administration.” Counties are established by the states “and may be erected without the consent of the inhabitants”; they are in effect agents of the state, local but not locally controlled. Their primary duties are judicial, but they also have the power to tax, and they bear responsibility for organizing and supervising elections. Although they do have elected boards of directors, their legislative functions “are rather closely restricted” by state statute. Outside of the northeastern states, they often run poorhouses, although state institutions are beginning to replace those. When it comes to law enforcement, “the sheriff is an agent of the state” but enjoys substantial scope of action, a power Kimball deplores. “In criminal cases the sheriff as keeper of the county jail has custody of the prisoners confined there and guards and delivers prisoners sentenced to other institutions.” He is aided by the county coroner, “the oldest of all elective country officers.” His duties “involve technical knowledge of two sorts: he needs to be both a lawyer and a physician, able to make a correct diagnosis weigh evidence, and preside over his jury.” Since “a man of these abilities is seldom chosen, and coroners’ inquests have traditionally been subjects of derision,” the state of Massachusetts has instituted a system of medical examiners; they report the cause of death to county prosecutors when they detect signs of foul play. In the South, counties are divided into school districts and precincts; the latter elect members of the county board. That is, Southern counties “have wider functions than those in New England,” taking up some of the responsibilities municipalities undertake elsewhere. This is due to the more dispersed populations in the South and also to “the presence of the negro population, which is generally debarred from the privileges of taking part in government,” a circumstance which “prevents the development of the active local governments found in the North.”

    Moving to the municipalities, Kimball defines villages or boroughs as “small, compactly built districts possessing charters of incorporation” established by a popular vote and recognized either by the county court, the county board, or the township supervisor. Some of these are actual municipalities, independent of township. Boroughs are governed by elected councils, which pass ordinances within the confines set down by state statutes, construct and maintain roads and public works, funded by property taxes. American cities are much bigger municipal corporations; they nonetheless “derive all [their] powers” from the state. Although many of the early cities were associated with forts, which protected them from hostile Amerindians and any European imperial holdings nearby, most “have been founded and developed as the result of trade or industry,” facilitated by such transportation routes as seas, rivers, and lakes. “The growth of cities is a modern phenomenon,” especially in the United States, “where the rapid growth of cities has surpassed that in all other counties.” Between 1880 and 1920, urban populations here had more than tripled (thanks mostly to migration and to improved sanitary conditions), now accounting for more than half the national population. Most urban residents live in the smaller cities, those with populations less than 25,000. Most of those who have moved into the cities are unskilled workers looking for jobs, especially in factories. European, Asian, and African-American migrants have “complicated” governance of the cities. “Reformers have frequently found it impossible to gain the combined support of different groups of foreign-born citizens because of their unwillingness to unite with other nationalities and their fear that some cherished custom might be interfered with by a political change.” In addition to overcrowding and the hazards of factory work, “the general wear and tear of urban life tend[s] to increase the death rate,” although this has been more than counterbalanced by in-migration. And while crime rates in the cities exceed those in rural areas, so do charitable and humanitarian efforts. Thus, “the cities present the most violent contrasts; in them extremes meet.” All this costs money: government expenditures have “more than doubled between 1903 and 1919,” the last period for which Kimball could obtain statistics.

    Municipal government has changed substantially since English settlers arrived. The first boroughs in the colonies were established in Maine in the 1640s. Then and subsequently, the charters were granted by governors, not by popularly elected assemblies. Mayors were also appointed by the colonial governor and councils were self-perpetuating, not elected by popular vote. Boroughs were judicial, not so much administrative organizations; indeed, “few of the modern municipal functions were performed.” They did govern markets and streets, water supply almost never, inasmuch as most water came from wells. “There were no public schools in any of the boroughs, no parks, no libraries, no administration of charitable relief,” and, accordingly, no taxes, revenues being “derived mostly from fines, licenses, and fees for the markets, ferries, and docks.” 

    “The establishment of independence of the United States brought about significant changes in municipal government,” as charters were now granted by state legislatures and charters were amended to guarantee governance by councils elected by the people. By the 1790s, “the influence of the national Constitution was clearly felt, and the forms of national government were bodily transferred to the cities.” These forms included separation of legislative and executive powers and, in Baltimore, a bicameral city legislature. Cities were small, with only thirteen having more than 8,000 residents; the urban population made up only about five percent of the U. S. population. The next thirty years—the years of Tocqueville—saw further democratization of municipal politics, with popular election of mayors, the elimination of property requirements for voting and for serving in office, the development of the spoils system by well-organized political parties. Municipal governments took on functions demanded by their ever-increasing constituencies, including control of the water supply, fire protection, and general power to tax. The two decades after this saw the institution of paid police and firemen, improved care of the streets, and poor relief. Such increased responsibilities diminished local control because “many cities were forced to appeal to the legislature for additional powers in order to perform the functions which were necessary and particularly, to finance these functions.” This reinforced the already existing tendency of state legislatures to regard “the cities as merely subordinate areas of administration and the city charters as mere statutes subject to amendment at any time.” Indeed, “a municipal corporation, like all other corporations is the creation of the legislature of the state,” “entirely subordinate” to the state legislature, owing its legitimacy to a state-granted charter. States also established special commissions or boards appointed by themselves, such as the state park commission in New York city and state police boards in New York, Baltimore, and Chicago. In New York, such commissions “went so far as to control five-sixths of the municipal expenditures.” Within the municipalities, and particularly the cities, government became bigger and more complicated, with new departments, “independent of the municipal council,” whose heads might be chosen by popular vote. 

    Kimball applauds the commissions because, in his judgment, the political parties that controlled municipal governments under the mayor and council system were inefficient, often corrupt, and unstable inasmuch as they were prey to the vagaries of the election cycle. “The spoils system was pretty thoroughly fastened upon the cities before the beginning of this period” and “the patronage of a large city was a prize which both parties were anxious to obtain.” The civil service reform movement of the nineteenth century’s last three decades derived from this, and from the increased complexity of urban municipal government, which made the professionalization of civil service more attractive. “Certain cities appealed to the legislature for protection against their own government.” More immediately, however, city charters were altered to give mayors more power, particularly the power to appoint. “This opened the door to trading and logrolling, but on the whole it was an advance over the system either of popular election” [of administrative offices] or of state-appointed officers.” At the same time, “state after state passed civil-service laws and established commissions for the supervision of municipal appointments,” appointments obtained by competitive examination. This practice was not instituted in the majority of states by the end of the nineteenth century, however.

    Overall, municipal reforms until 1900 “were aimed at special abuses or tendencies, rather than any radical change in the form of government.” On the verge of bankruptcy caused by a disastrous flood, Galveston, Texas introduced the first “commission form of government,” whereby lawmaking and administration were combined in one body, as seen in corporate boards; the reasoning was that a ‘business model’ would be more efficient and honest than a ‘political’ one.  (This distinction between ‘business’ or ‘administration’ and ‘politics’ only holds if ‘politics’ means government in accordance with the institution of separated powers. It is sometimes extended to a distinction between ‘administration’ and government by elected representatives, but in America the commissioners that governed cities in Kimball’s time were usually elected officials.) At that time, about 350 cities in the United States, many of them in the Midwest, had adopted this system. In a similar move, about 200 cities had adopted a city manager form of government, again on the grounds that a professional chief executive would be more efficient and honest than an elected one, especially given the need for “vast waterworks and sewage-disposal systems” along with complex transportation networks and increased public charity—all consequences of the sharp increases in population caused by mass immigration. The children of immigrants needed education, beginning with education in English and culminating in job training; this, too, increased the responsibilities of local government while simultaneously interesting state governments in education. Although “no legislature can hope to foresee all the wants of all the cities,” it can “lay down simple and comprehensive rules vesting in administrative authorities the power to apply these rules with such variations as the needs of the cities require.” This “idea of administrative control originated in Europe, and much of the success of municipal government in Prussia is due to the relative absence of legislative control and the prevalence of administrative control.” Kimball applauds: “Although administrative control has not developed to the same extent in this country that it has in England or in Europe, yet the results are generally excellent.” That is, although Kimball isn’t a Progressive ‘all the way down,’ in terms of the practices he recommends he might as well be.

    One governmental response to urban size and complexity has been city planning. “Up to about 1910 city planning was of the most casual character”; the first permanent planning commission had only been established in 1907, in Hartford, Connecticut. Such commissions “face many difficulties.” The United States Constitution and the state constitutions limit ‘takings’—government seizure of private property for public purposes. Further, “city planning is expensive; particularly is this true in the reconstruction of streets and the remedying of mistakes made by previous administrations.” Since “streets are the most important portions of the city’s territory and its most valuable property,” “bear[ing] the traffic and business of the city” and covering water, sewers, and gas mains, “the life of the city depends upon” them, inasmuch as “there would be no access to private property, no means of communication, no method of providing light and air for the buildings” without them.” Under contemporary conditions, city planning is both much needed and much vexed. [3] 

    So is public education. In Massachusetts, it predated independence by more than a century, as the Great and General Court decreed that any township with more than fifty householders must establish an elementary school and that any township with more than a hundred families must establish a grammar school, both kinds to be funded by taxation. But it wasn’t until after the Civil War that the policy became universal, with school boards independent of the overall municipal governments, their members usually chosen in at-large elections. “Experts have no place on the school board,” which should represent ordinary citizens. A school superintendent, analogous to a city manager, selects the teachers with the approval of the board, “frames the course of study,” which is submitted to the school board for criticism and approval, and oversees “the discipline and promotion of the teachers,” again with board approval, which is usually pro forma. Although the superintendent may well “make himself a powerful influence in the community,” he should scrupulously refrain from undertaking “political or partisan action”—again, meaning participation in election campaigns. “The backbone of the school system is the body of teachers,” often “the most permanent of the city employees.” Professionalization of teachers has increased, with many school boards now requiring that job candidates pass qualifying examinations. Some of these are competitive, with only those with the best scores eligible for hiring. “The tenure of the teacher is practically during good behavior, and dismissals are extremely rare.” 

    Kimball turns to a description of the aforementioned three varieties of municipal government prevalent in the United States: mayor-and-council, commission, and city-manager. The mayor-and-council, generally with a weak mayor and a strong council, was “the English type of government” imported by the colonists. Administrative functions were undertaken by committees of the council, which either oversaw professional administrators or administered departmental affairs directly. “As a rule the American municipal government as evidenced by the city council is not to be condemned so much for its corruption as for its stupidity and inefficiency.” After protests to state legislatures against the spoils system resulted in stronger state ‘oversight’ of city governments, which in turn resulted in what many city residents regarded as overbearing state interference in local affairs, the countervailing movement toward ‘home rule’ did not return full powers to the councils but instead increased the powers of the mayors. Since the middle of the nineteenth century, “the powers of the mayor have steadily grown at the expense of the city council.” At the same time, what amounts to a de facto elective monarchy must itself become overburdened in a large and complex city. Decentralization of powers by dividing the city and its government into wards addresses this problem but causes another: overall city interests may not be served when there is a strong ward system—hence the pejorative term, ‘ward politician.’ 

    This led to the adoption of the mayor-and-commission system in many small and medium-sized cities. Under this system, the mayor is elected by popular vote and therefore is not usually a professional administrator. The mayor wields not only the power of appointment but often the power of veto over ordinances passed by the council. But insofar as a new city charter empowers a commission, the executive powers wielded by the mayor give way to the combined executive and legislative powers of the commission, which consists of three to seven members. Each commission member, elected at-large in nonpartisan fashion, supervises one administrative department. Commissioners are not expected to be experts in the areas ‘their’ departments govern, but they “are expected to be intelligent executives who are able to see that their departments run.” The mayor merely presides over commission meetings, although there is a tendency to enhance his powers, given the need to coordinate the activities of the departments. “Government by commission is a radical departure from the time-honored form of municipal government,” with its separation of powers. This has led to the enactment of such safeguards as initiative, referendum, and recall as democratic controls over what amounts to an elective oligarchy. Given the combination of legislative and administrative powers that characterizes the commission system (the commission is “all-powerful to act for better or for worse”), “it is not unreasonable that an opportunity should be given the voters to correct the errors which perhaps were made at the original election.” Overall, Kimball writes, “the open and undisguised responsibility which each member of the commission bears may frequently prevent the secret and sinister influence which interested parties formerly exerted upon individual councilmen and may cause the commissioners to act for the good of the city rather than at the dictates of a special interest.” 

    But if the concentration of responsibility for city governance is the goal, why not go still farther, from quasi-oligarchy to quasi-monarchy? This is the point of the city-manager form of municipal government. Under this form, a council or commission sets general policy but “the administrative functions are concentrated in a single executive chosen by the commission [or the council] and designated as the city manager,” who takes over the power of appointing department heads. This rids the city of “the friction and delay which might result from the majority of the commission overruling the action of the commissioner in charge of a special department,” carrying “the form of commission government to its logical conclusion” by providing for “a small policy-determining body and a professional, expert administrator.” Although having no vote in determining policy, “the city manager exercises great influence in his advisory capacity,” inasmuch as he knows the workings of the city better than any other one person. Staunton, Virginia was the first municipality to institute the city-manager system, and “the movement has spread rapidly,” although again “largely confined to the smaller cities.” Kimball regards this as “a logical development of the attempt to place the government of our cities upon a business basis.” 

    In the United States, then, “the general tendency is toward self-contained administrative departments, which, to a large degree, are beyond the immediate control of the city council,” in contrast with mayor-and-council government but similar to the strong-mayor system. This notwithstanding, “the city council under every form of government should control the policies of the various departments,” especially given its power to set taxes; “it is ridiculous to expect that an elected body endowed with these powers will surrender them entirely to appointive officials.” “The real problem is how this control can best be exercised so that the council shall freely exercise the policy-determining power, and the administrative departments be equally free in carrying out this already determined policy and in conducting their affairs without interference on the part of the council.” Although “theoretically, administration by council committees has much in its favor, practically, it has failed to work satisfactorily in the United States” due to amateurish incompetence in the face of novel governmental complexity. But it remains true that “it is a legitimate function of politics to control both the lawmaking and law-executing bodies of the state or city,” determining “what the law shall be” and keeping “the administrative officers in harmony with the lawmaking officers.” The division of power Kimball endorses, then, is a division not exactly between legislative and executive powers as between legislative and administrative powers; the struggle in the commission and city-manager governments will be between the council, which may want to push administrators into granting special favors to their constituents or friends, and administrators, who may want to seize control of policy, de facto if not de jure. “The city-manager type of government attempts a radical divorce of administration from politics,” a divorce Kimball would sanction, while continuing to worry that the political branch of the government will not exert, or attempt to exert, “improper political influence” over administration. It does not occur to him that corruption might also seep into the administrative branch, or that political and administrative officials might collaborate in order to corrupt the citizens, offering them ‘spoils’ in the form of substantial government ‘programs’—in effect, a new form of vote-buying, one that denatures citizenship and fosters habits of mind conducive not to popular sovereignty but to popular subjection, not very far removed from what Tocqueville called “soft despotism.”

     

    Notes

    1. See James Monroe: The People, the Sovereigns, reviewed on this website under the title, “Monroe’s Understanding of the Sovereignty of the American People” under the category, “American Politics.”
    2. Although sympathetic with reformers, Kimball does not share the Progressives’ historicism, retaining the Founders’ idea of natural rights: “the right of personal security is the right to life which is recognized as the natural right of every man unless his existence has become a menace to the state or unless his life is needed for the protection of the state. This right is the most fundamental one.” “Personal liberty” (including not only “mere freedom of movement” but “freedom of thought, speech, and the right to pursue any lawful calling”) and “the pursuit of happiness” are “moral rights,” not necessarily legal rights. So, for example, “in a state where slavery exists…by law,” legal personal liberty might coexist with it among non-slaves. For Kimball, then, ‘History’ is not the source of right. 
    3. For further consideration of city planning and zoning, see “Municipal Planning and Zoning in the United States,” on this website under the category, “American Politics.”

    Filed Under: American Politics

    The City in the Commercial Republic

    August 14, 2024 by Will Morrisey

    Stephen L. Elkin: City and Regime in the American Republic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987.

     

    The American Founders designed a democratic and commercial republic. Cities are centers of commerce, very often arising in places where the geography favors the construction of ports, as exemplified in the original United States by Boston, New York, Philadelphia, Baltimore, and Charleston, soon to be followed by New Orleans. Cities also feature concentrations of people, and so can exhibit popular self-government, mob rule, or any of the gradations in-between. Elkin regards “the political institutions of the city” as “potentially crucial in helping to prepare the citizenry to operate the commercial republic that the founding fathers set in motion.” The relations between governments and commercial markets, the status of property and especially of modern business corporations in America’s national life, may well be studied in cities, not for the sake of narrowly ‘academic’ interest but with a view to establishing and maintaining “a political way of life” fitting the regime as a whole. 

    A few decades after the American founding, Alexis de Tocqueville and John Stuart Mill both “approached the study of politics in cities and towns as part of a more general inquiry into the possibility of popular government,” popular government being (then and now) a matter of sharp controversy, a regime with critics and indeed enemies. Both philosophers considered municipalities, and not only or even primarily cities, as schools for self-government, for political liberty rightly understood. To maintain a republican regime, citizens need to achieve certain habits of mind and heart that enable them to truly inhabit such institutions as legislative bodies, executive offices, and courts, to use those institutions instead of abusing or losing them. Elkin finds that his contemporaries among political scientists have narrowed the scope of their study, focusing primarily on the questions of political and economic equality in the cities and the efficiency with which cities use available resources. Whether ‘capitalist’ or Marxist, such writers tend to reduce politics to economics, “not sharing Tocqueville’s and Mill’s interest in the larger political whole.” What is “the desirable political order,” the best practicable regime, for a city in the United States? And if it is to be a miniature commercial republic, what specific features will make it a better one? 

    Before prescription, description. Elkin identifies seven major features of city politics. They are: electoral contests, interest groups, business owners, elected officials, bureaucracies (“central actors in city politics”), the federal and state governments, and races/ethnic groups (“pervasive and endemic features of city politics”). Given these features, and given the commercial character of cities, he grounds his study on what he calls “the division of labor between state and market,” with “market” standing in for the more general notion of civil society because “city politics is a profoundly economically oriented enterprise.” He nonetheless rejects an economics-driven interpretation, whether Marxist or ‘capitalist,’ insisting on the political character of what was indeed once called political economy. Admittedly, “in market-dominated mass democracies, concern with material well-being—its overall level and distribution—is virtually certain to be central” to political contestation. “But liberal democracies are unlikely to flourish if they rely on the view that politics is simply economics carried out in non-market settings.” Beyond Karl Marx, beyond Adam Smith (Hayek, von Mises), “Tocqueville and Mill are helpful” because they see that political institutions don’t merely foster or discourage economic prosperity; “they are also formative of the citizenry.” The structure of ruling offices provides a framework wherein citizens relate to one another, thereby developing certain habits of mind and heart that differ from one regime to another—what Elkins calls “our procedural morality.” Although “the idea of political institutions as formative is no longer a prominent theme in contemporary theorizing about politics,” it should be, inasmuch as “a certain sort of citizenry is needed if liberal democracies are to flourish,” a citizenry that sustains “a political regime that is worthy of us,” a citizenry “with a lively sense of what I shall call the commercial public interest.” The public interest amounts to more than the concatenation of private interests, in particular the interests of business owners. It is a matter of “how we stand in relation to one another” and how we exercise “political judgment.” Judgment can (or should) imply reasoning; political life affords an opportunity for citizens to deliberate together, not only an opportunity to assert themselves with vehemence, although of course that happens, too. Elkin will argue that “for us to be the commercial republic that we say we wish to be requires both substantial democratization and significant alteration in property rights.” He wants Madisonian democratic republicanism, but with more democracy.

    Democracy entails sufficient civic equality among citizens to establish majority rule. In a commercial civic society, private individuals control most of the means of production; as a result, public officials “cannot command economic performance, only induce it.” This requires the establishment of “structural factors” that guide the relations between property owners and governments, including the powers each is entitled to wield, the organization of public authority, and a federal system of national government whereby each city is left with “the task of competing for private resources” with other cities. City governance changed in the decades between 1870 and 1920; “it was then that the modern municipal corporation took shape, in a protracted effort to create city governments that suited the political actors who had emerged on the stage of the industrial city”—industrialism itself being a product of nineteenth century economic development, first seen on a large scale in Manchester and other English urban centers, but rapidly imitated in the United States, especially in the North. 

    American cities were never “sovereign bodies,” but the idea that their governing powers are granted by state governments, that “cities are understood to be creatures of states,” was only recognized by courts in the early years of the twentieth century, thanks to the jurisprudence of John Forrest Dillon. Born in 1831 in upstate New York, Dillon first received a Doctor of Medicine degree from the University of Iowa, but then read and practiced law in the 1850s, eventually becoming a judge on the Iowa Supreme Court in the 1860s. In the following decade he served on the United States Circuit Court for the Eighth Circuit, appointed by President Grant. It was in an 1868 Iowa case, Clinton v. Cedar Rapids and the Missouri River Railroad, that he formulated “Dillon’s Rule”: “Municipal corporations owe their origin to, and derive their powers and rights wholly from, the [state] legislature,” which therefore may create, destroy, abridge, and control municipalities. He elaborated on this rule in his 1872 treatise, Municipal Corporations. Dillon thereby opposed “Cooley’s Doctrine,” enunciated by Thomas McIntyre Cooley, Justice and then Chief Justice of the Michigan Supreme Court from 1864 to 1885. In The General Principles of Constitutional Law in the United States of America (1868), Dillon wrote that “It is axiomatic that the management of purely local affairs belongs to the people concerned, not only because of being their own affairs, but because they will best understand, and be most competent to manage them. The continued and permanent existence of local government is, therefore, assumed in all the state constitutions, and is a matter of constitutional right, even when not in terms expressly provided for. It would not be competent to dispense with it by statute.” Dillon’s Rule prevailed over Cooley’s Doctrine in the 1907 Supreme Court case, Hunter v. Pittsburgh. Its logical corollary was established in Trenton v. New Jersey, decided in 1923, when the justices ruled that states could carve out areas of self-government for municipalities, at the discretion of the legislatures. The courts distinguished, in these cases, between public corporations and private corporations, the latter enjoying property rights similar to those of individual persons, who enjoy such rights, under the American regime, not only by conventional law but as a natural right endowed by the laws of nature and of nature’s God.

    Elkin characterizes Dillon’s rule as “an attempt to resolve the dilemma of what to do with corporations in a liberal polity.” When northeastern North America was a set of British colonies, municipalities were understood as sitting between the state and individuals, “bodies politic” that governed individuals while protecting residents “against state power,” which might encroach upon individual liberty. Before Dillon, American jurists under the United States Constitution had already defined municipal corporations as public entities, “a counterpart” to “the private business corporation.” But where did the rights public corporations possessed come from? Did they come from “the right of association on the part of the people who composed the city”? If so, they might exercise majority tyranny, putting property rights at risk within their boundaries. Dillon determined to avert this danger by asserting the power of the state over the municipalities within it, enabling states—both legislatures and courts, although not executives—to reach into cities to prevent socialist or other illiberal encroachments on property rights. Dillon staked out three municipal powers: “those granted in express words”; “those necessarily or fairly implied in or incident to the power expressly granted”; “those essential to the accomplishments of the declared objects and purposes of the corporation—not simply convenient, but indispensable.” This makes municipalities more or less like administrative agencies of the state governments while leaving private corporations at liberty to exercise property rights, an exercise that provides them with “a substantial sphere in which their ability to shape the life of the city will be largely unrestricted and unchallenged.” For example, if a private corporation engages in heavy industry, that activity will surely exert a strong effect on a city’s residents’ way of life, with respect to employment but also noise, air quality, transportation, even the content of the education children are likely to receive.

    Elkin next describes the character of city governments in the industrial cities within this legal framework. In the decades immediately following the Civil War, “industrialists and commercial entrepreneurs, saloon keepers and workers, homeowners and utility magnates, all dealt with each other through a set of political institutions that were both expensive to operate and ramshackle.” Unlike today’s cities, with their strong mayors and/or city managers, the cities of that time were governed by city councils that “were very large by contemporary standards” and often bicameral. Much of the day-to-day business was conducted by city council committees or by boards and commissions whose members were appointed by the council. Electoral politics was organized by coalitions, such as New York’s Tweed Ring, loosely aligned with the Democratic Party. Leading up to the turn of the century, the political parties took firmer control, as seen in the figure of George Washington Plunkitt, the New York State legislator who specialized in what he called “honest graft,” profiteering on real estate in ways that both enriched himself and served some sort of public good (for example buying real estate he anticipated New York City would want, then selling it at a fine profit). Private corporations navigated this complex political structure as best they could. As Elkin puts it, drily, “the difficulty from the point of view of local businessmen was that the bargains struck often had a short lifetime.” Patronage politics, graft, money doled out to the poor to ensure voting support, all combined with inefficient means of revenue collection, brought the industrialists to advocate stronger executive government, empowering mayors and professionalizing the budget process. Corporate eminences John D. Rockefeller and Andrew Carnegie also intended to prevent control of city government by political radicals who enjoyed some success appealing to the ‘proletarians’ under the magnates’ employ. Such men found allies among utilities executives, merchants, and middle-classes worried about bad morals and high taxes. Among the middle classes were professionals, appalled by governmental inefficiency, and social workers, enemies of the ward politicians who doled out ‘relief’ to the poor in exchange for votes. “The beneficiaries of the existing arrangements were no match for this whirlwind of dissatisfaction, reform proposals, and political energy.”

    Results of reformists’ efforts were mixed. Mayors were indeed empowered to appoint department heads; the departments were staffed more and more by professionals instead of patronage hires. “Consolidation, centralization, and efficiency were the bywords.” Political parties strengthened their control over elections, but the new, professionalized bureaucracies sought further independence from the parties by cultivating allies within the “clientele groups” they (increasingly) ruled by serving. 

    Meanwhile, city governments still needed revenues, especially if they were expected to provide social services as a matter of professional obligation instead of political tradeoffs. They needed credit from the financial men, along with such state and federal aid as they could find. Absent a “national system of aid to cities” that guarantees their financial solvency, cities were very much subject to the demands of their creditors. By the post-World War II period, understanding city politics “is largely an exercise in grasping the implications of the structural factors that define (1) the powers of cities, (2) the prerogatives of asset holders, and (3) the relations between them.” City governments “have few powers of their own to stimulate economic growth”; dissatisfied corporate executives can move their business elsewhere; if business moves elsewhere, credit dries up. Thus, local business owners and city governments usually work in alignment with one another to spur the economic activity that provides revenues for the politicians to spend. But the bureaucrats, largely unconcerned with the exigencies of electoral politics, are free to take actions that “impinge on the efforts of the alliance between public officials and local businessmen to promote city growth.” Elkin wants to find a way to break the close alliance between city governments and business owners without further empowering, and perhaps even reducing, the power of the bureaucrats.

    He still has more descriptive work to do, however. He centers his study of city economics on land-use patterns, inasmuch as major land-use projects enhance the reputations of the politicians who promote them. To promote private investment in cities, city officials must provide infrastructure (roads, tunnels, bridges) and amenities (parks, playgrounds); seek investment funds; offer tax incentives; avoid or reduce regulations that stifle regulations, “including zoning requirements”; improve the education system by insuring it “will produce an attractive mix of work skills”; and “help with land assembly.” Infrastructure and amenities, zoning and planning, and land assembly are all elements of land use, which Elkin regards as more important than the other elements of business-friendliness. “City officials will naturally gravitate toward an alliance with businessmen particularly land interests, and such an alliance will naturally be devoted to creating institutional arrangements that will facilitate investment in the city.” To win elections, such officials prefer to avoid “controversies over such matters as schools and police” and “stick with what concerns them most,” namely, land use and allocation of the non-bureaucratic city jobs they still control. Mayors are well positioned for both tasks as the focus of electoral attention and as the negotiators of land-use deals. For their part, landowners care about city budgets, which affect the creditworthiness of the cities, taxes, and city services. 

    There have been three types of “political economies” resulting from the interactions between city governments and business interests in America’s post-World War II decades: “pluralist,” “federalist,” and “entrepreneurial.” The pluralist political economy predominated in the two decades following the war, emphasizing the prosperity of downtown business districts, transportation networks, the sustenance of a middle-class population, a wide set of partners in development efforts, and the establishment of private development corporations with some public members on the boards of directors. As middle classes moved into the suburbs, however (taking advantage of those improved transportation networks to become commuters), the “federalist”—more exactly, centralist—political economy took over, with direct grants to cities increasing sixfold in the 1970s, enabling local politicians to win votes from the remaining, poorer, residents and supporting city employees, now unionized. By then, the urban poor were usually racial minorities. “If federal dollars had not been available to keep minority leaders engaged in the politics of the service bureaucracies, it is not inconceivable that they would have turned to matters closer to the heart to of the land-use interests and city politicians anxious to see a continuing stream of investment in the city.” This has empowered the bureaucracies, recipients of federal largesse, while weakening the patronage powers of the elected officials. This was the model seen in most American cities at the time Elkin wrote his book, and it remains intact in many cities today.

    Dallas was the exemplary entrepreneurial city of the day. It had a city-manager system, not a mayoral system. In those systems, the bureaucracy aligns with the business interests, which regard city-manager governance as the one that “best suit[s] their concerns,” providing “government that [is] efficient, professional, and administered by experts” while reducing the power of elected officials who too often look for votes among the poor, who are no friends of private corporations. For their part, elected officials satisfy themselves with those limited powers, leaving the troublesome administrative details to the bureaucrats. In Dallas, this has been a success story, at least in terms of the economic prosperity all interested groups want. “The essential point of difference between this sort of political economy and the pluralist and federalist types is that the behavior of public officials in the entrepreneurial version is not as much shaped by the building of electoral organizations and political coalitions,” city managers being unelected. City managers behave (it might be said) rather more like public school administrators, working to ensure that elected officials are friendly and somewhat infantilized demi-citizens obedient. Not that Elkin goes that far. “Insofar as citizens play an active role in political life” in the entrepreneurial political economies, “they are drawn into politics either to speak for their neighborhood, ethnic group, or some other interests”—as demanding children, a curmudgeon would say) “or as a bureaucratic client” (an older child, home from college, returned to the nest).

    Nonetheless, in all these political economies, “citizens stand in relation to one another both as potential bargainers in a set of political institutions that work to aggregate interest, and as clients of city bureaucracies.” And just as parents often favor one child over another, so city managers and bureaucracies will “consistently favor some interests and impede others,” often by adroitly setting the agenda for public discussion. “Considerable effort goes into fending off the attentions of outside politicians and businessmen,” thereby maximize freedom for executive but especially bureaucratic maneuver. Because executives and bureaucrats share an interest in promoting economic prosperity, the land-use agenda stays “heavily tilted toward the land interest of the city,” with officials ever ready to “rearrang[e] land use to promote city growth,” inasmuch as “land is capital for those who own it or manage it, a context for the day-to-day lives of the citizens who live in the city, and a source of political benefits and revenues for the officials who govern the city.” This circumstance is relatively easy to maintain because even if advocates of “popular control” push forward, preventing “the land-use alliance” from “engineer[ing] major land-use changes” “for the moment,” the alliance “is still in a position to prevent the emergence of any other conception of the use of city powers.” When economic, social, or political problems arise, the range of policy choices is accordingly narrowed and ‘the many who are poor’ largely excluded from direct political participation on behalf of themselves. 

    The impasse stated, Elkin recurs to Tocqueville and Mill, to the question of the regime, beyond political economy. Within the regime of democratic and commercial republicanism, “city political institutions have a specific role to play and therefore an intrinsic significance.” Cities are not sovereign, but they are regimes within the overall regime under whose governance they operate. Regimes are, among other things, ways of life. “What political way of life do we wish to form?” What is a regime?

    Regimes typically lay down laws. There is an “internal morality of law,” as “citizens and lawgivers learn to organize their affairs according to law by attempting to do so,” by attempting to live according to the laws and their internal morality, what Montesquieu calls the spirit of the laws. Laws shape “the form of political activity and thus of the citizenry acting within them,” habituating them to certain ways of acting, thinking, and feeling that differentiate them from persons living under a different kind of regime. Homo Americanus was not Homo Sovieticus. In the ancient world, an Israelite was not a Canaanite, and neither was a Persian; the legal structures, the ruling institutions, and the spirit or “internal morality” of their laws differentiated them. Regimes as sets of rulers, as ruling offices or institutions, as ways of life (both in actions and in speaking), have a formative character on those living in accordance with them. And they aim at purposes, ends: “They teach the lesson of what those most visible in the society consider as valuable.” 

    Elkins describes the regime founded by Americans as guided by “a concern for individual rights and the promotion of a commercial society,” with popular sovereignty in the form of democratic republicanism serving those ends. He has a narrow understanding of individual rights, however, boiling them down to political liberty in Montesquieu’s sense, “a tranquility of mind arising from the opinion each has of his safety.” This formulation ignores the Declaration of Independence, which enumerates three natural rights, among others: life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. That is, even if one defines the pursuit of happiness as a reformulation of Locke’s right to property, Elkin has untied property rights from human nature; and if one defines happiness and its pursuit more broadly, as seen in such Founders as Washington and Jefferson, and such allies as the Marquis de Chastellux [1], he has untied it from the fuller conception of human goods and (therefore) of political ends than the Founders upheld. 

    Elkin correctly identifies the problem James Madison identifies in the tenth Federalist, the problem of majority tyranny. Political liberty wedded to political equality yields majority rule, which can lead to assaults on minority rights by factions (or sometimes, by minorities aiming at weakening or overturning majority rule), groups “united and actuated by some common impulse of passion, or of interest, adverse to the rights of other citizens, or to the permanent and aggregate interests of the community.” In order to secure property rights, the Founders framed not only a democratic but a commercial republic, one in which a majority would own, and therefore seek to guard, property rights. Commercial civil societies produce not only widespread property ownership but diversified forms of property, each pursuing its particular interest, blocking other propertied factions from achieving dominance. And commercial civil societies also promote the virtues of commerce, including thrift and sobriety—ballast steadying popular passions. In all this, the Founders nonetheless “did not mean that public officials were to take their direction from commercial men,” who “would at a minimum be inclined to strangle competition, be inattentive to the safety of the nation, and be uninterested in finding way to mitigate the bad effects of commercial expansion.” The Founders understood that “the primary value of a commercial society was political,” seen in such a society’s disinclination to run off into endless wars for the aggrandizement of generals or the advance of a religion, both of which motives had wracked Europe for centuries. In so understanding the importance of commerce, the Founders saw that commerce itself, the minds and hearts of commercial men, could lend itself to faction, even if to a less immediately dangerous kind of faction than a disposition to make war. “Officials should not assume that impact on economic growth is the primary criterion in judging policy initiative that affect the distribution of property and wealth in the society.” While securing “private rights,” those occupying the ruling offices of democratic and commercial republics must see to it that government controls itself and also to secure the ruling authority they wield from “powerful private interests” that may arise with the intention of violating the private rights of others, thereby overturning the regime, the “commercial republic that we want.” “The commercial public interest,” the maintenance of the regime and of the principles that animate it, that give it its purpose, “is not what businessmen say it is”—the pursuit of happiness misdefined as material self-interest alone. Although in a commercial republican regime businessmen are not “a ruling class dominating the state,” as Marxist contend, neither are they “merely a particularly powerful interest group.” They are positioned to be somewhat difficult to govern, precisely because the democratic republic is democratic in the modern way, the way that has converted the many who are poor into the many who are middle-class, aspiring to ever-increasing wealth and not always hesitant to resist corporate alliances with governments.

    “Can a regime dedicated to popular control work so as to respect individual liberties, promote a commercial society, and give it concrete meaning in the course of defining the commercial public interest?” Elkin carefully distinguishes the commercial public interest from commercial interests. Commercial interests incline toward cutting down competition, monopolizing markets for the sake of immediate self-interest. Commercial public interest means, first, the maintenance of commercial liberty itself, minimizing the monopolistic practices commercial men aim at, the form of libido dominandi toward which businessmen’s souls incline. How can the American regime prevent “public authority from being the tool of private interest”? While “try[ing] to avoid reducing the confidence of businessmen” by offering them such inducements to invest as tax incentives, government research money and research findings (the latter seen in the disclosure of certain aspects of computer technology, invented for military use, to businessmen), and punishing “rapacious officials.” While critics of the regime decry government efforts to “promot[e] capital,” ‘capitalists’ themselves decry “an expansive state” that constrains their activities “There is some truth in both observations.” In the American regime overall, “the decline of Congress and the rise of the administrative state” has done little to assuage either of those concerns, even though the administrative state arose precisely in order to bridle private corporations, who had, according to Progressives, New Dealers, and Great Society men, corrupted our legislative halls of fame. As it has happened, the “managerial mode” of rule wielded by public bureaucrats in private corporations may find friends among the private bureaucrats in private corporations, even as some of those public bureaucrats may irritate their private counterparts with their minute and stringent regulations.

    We Americans have “largely failed to maintain the distinction between the essentially political reasons for a commercial society and how to contrive a happy environment for businessmen” because “officials lack strong incentives to think beyond business inducement.” Elkin proposes five ways of providing such incentives: lowering “the barriers to dissent”; reducing incentive for businessmen to seek “official inducements” by “reducing business concentration”; reducing “the advantages businessmen have in the collection and dispersal of political money”; “curb[ing] the tendency of officials to use whatever discretion they have to facilitate business inducement”; and to “improve officials’ grasp of the considerations that should guide their efforts to give content to the commercial public interest” and especially to the connection “between a commercial society and republican government.” On the citizens’ side of the equation, “a lively sense that inducing business performance does not exhaust the meaning of the commercial public interest” will also be needed. Only then will public officials, elected and unelected, have a strong incentive to understand and to strengthen republicanism. “Without a citizenry able to grasp that the commercial public interest is not exhausted by inducing business performance, no other reforms will work at least if those reforms are not to be worse than the disease.” As Madison asked, in what was then an indignant tone, but now strikes the ear as plaintive, “Is there no virtue among us?” 

    And what can cities in particular do to recover the Founders’ regime? Citizens in them will need to cultivate “a disposition to think of political choice as involving the giving of reasons” about “what is beneficial to us as a political community,” not only as a marketplace. “Arguments are to be tested, reworked, and withdrawn, not asserted as if their blinding rationality compels assent,” and not as if they were an exercise in geometry. “Politics educates judgment,” what the Greeks called phronēsis. Here, however, Elkin departs from Aristotle. In “the classical Greek conception, in which political and moral (as moderns would say) life are inextricably bound together and the broad purpose of politics is thought to be the promotion of virtue,” what is good for human beings by nature, Elkin subordinates the virtues to the regime of democratic and commercial republicanism. But more, although he invokes what contemporary scholars call “the civic republican tradition,” whose “central concern is the primary role that civic virtue must play in the workings of free government,” this too is more “demanding” than what he has in mind. He contends that “the public interest will emerge from argument born of diverse starting points,” with citizens only needing “to be disposed to believe that there is something more to public choice than combining private interests.” In order to get them to be so disposed, the political institutions “must place citizens in relation to each other as deliberators or reason givers, not, for example, as bargainers engaged in exchange” with executives and/or bureaucrats. Those institutions will therefore be legislative, primarily, not executive in either the ‘strong mayor’ or the ‘city manager’ form of government. That is, city governments would return to the institutional form, the politeia, which predominated in the American English colonies and in the decades up to the Civil War—city council government. The motives of citizens engaged in this form of city government would be concern for concrete local issues (schools, land-use patterns in the neighborhoods, “features of their work lives”) and “the deep interest that each of us has in enjoying the esteem of others.” This “desire for the esteem of others”—invoked by the young Abraham Lincoln in a campaign flyer he distributed when he first ran for the Illinois legislature—can be turned “into a disposition to act politically by the giving of reasons.”

    “The danger, of course, is that the desire for esteem will mean the tyranny of a dominant opinion,” inasmuch as speakers in council will want to play to the crowd. Elkin hopes that the commercial character of the “commercial public interest” will exert some discipline upon speakers. To achieve commercial prosperity needed to win the esteem of your fellow citizens, demagoguery will only get you so far. Real-world exigencies will bridle big talk, in the long run. Elkin admits, however, that “there is no easy solution here.” A major barrier is what he calls “corrupted liberalism,” that is, liberty extended to corporations, now legally treated as if they were individual persons. Its existence, together with the existence of a substantial professional bureaucracy, makes for a confrontation of “those devoted to the defense of the business corporation and those devoted to some version of an expanded state in the service of social welfare.” Corrupt or “corporate liberalism” attempts to define the commercial public interest in terms of “the inducing of business performance”; its public-bureaucratic rival attempts to define the commercial interest, or the public interest generally, in terms of a new sort of property rights, rights to tax-supported social and economic benefits controlled by the bureaucrats. Under bureaucratic rule, “rights language will then become a rhetorical cover, directed not at justifying a sphere in which individual autonomy can flourish but aimed instead at providing a new principle of social decision in which businessmen will have no advantage, regardless of whether this is in the service of individual autonomy” (itself a specimen of corrupted language, a replacement for natural right) “or not.” The corporate-liberal justification of corporate property rights is no less rhetorical. “Whatever the [American] Founders’ intentions, property rights have already been significantly altered throughout our history.”

    Against this, Elkin would institute a regime that makes “citizens more intelligent about public life, not more moral” in the private sense, strengthening “the disposition to engage in public-regarding debate and struggle” in “a marriage between liberalism and democracy, with the latter in the service of the former.” Institutionally, he recommends neighborhood assemblies “with significant powers,” citywide referenda, and city legislatures, “also with significant powers.” To avoid majority tyranny, he would structure referenda questions to offer multiple choices, not yes-no choices, in order to encourage deliberation and to make it more likely that a winning proposal really would command votes from a well-informed majority. Today’s public corporations (cities) and private corporations feature executive regimes, and this would change those regimes, revolutionize the cities, giving far more authority to the people, ‘the democracy.’ Such authority would include the power to govern land use, to “take land for specified public purposes.”

    Why, Elkin asks himself, would neighborhood and citywide assemblies not “feel compelled to attract investment to their areas,” just as mayors and city managers do in the existing city regimes”? “Land interests would likely prove only too happy to oblige and seek out allies from among neighborhood residents.” That is, “what will prevent small-scale versions of what presently occurs in city politics?” Nothing would prevent it, but land-use decisions made by legislative majorities are at least more likely to bring benefits more widely distributed than decisions effected by deals between public and private corporate executives. Elkin fully understands that “regardless of their merits, the prospects of such reforms occurring are slim,” and so they have proven to be.

    Undeterred, Elkin calls property “the Achilles’ heel of the American regime” because it has been redefined since the time of the Founders, redefined as a right to property held by corporate ‘persons,’ a right based on legal fiction instead of nature. However, Elkin proposes not a return to the Founders’ understanding of property as a natural right to be secured by a constitutionally limited government but as “fundamentally a public matter.” Properly understood, “property is a political concept and openly to begin its redefinition as a political act is itself an effort that cuts deeply into the core of a liberal regime.” He proposes this re-redefinition to oppose “the present form of socialized property” (socialized in the sense that it corporations are in fact civil-social units within the larger civil society) found in the large-scale business corporation.” While so proposing, he understands that the Progressive-New Deal hope that an ‘administrative state’ or public bureaucracy would serve as an adequate counterweight to the private corporate bureaucracies has weakened the democratic character of democratic republicanism. Neither does he want socialism, “state ownership of assets.” In all of this, “the most worrisome point of all is that it may be impossible to sustain the public-spiritedness necessary for a liberal regime to flourish.” 

    His own “political” answer is insufficient, partaking too much of the Progressivism it (sort of) seeks to confront. He cites with approval the Hannah Arendt-George Kateb “conception of a constitution”: “a constitution is not a program or policy”—true enough—but “it has no goal; it does not make an object,” but rather “is the creation of a frame of institutions for indefinite future possibilities of political action,” an act of “procedural morality.” Inasmuch as it has a goal, that goal is “to be the best of its kind.” This begs the question, What is the best? And that begs the question, What is the good? According to Elkin, “our foundational aspiration is to be a popular regime,” as “we wish to be a popular regime first and foremost, even before we wish to be a commercial rights-bearing one.” The democratic “political way of life” is rightly superior to, although not properly destructive of, the commercial way of life insofar as commerce is now oligarchically structured. But what, then, governs democracy? Having abandoned natural right defined by the laws of nature and of nature’s God, Elkin can only offer whatever comes out of political contestation. As he concedes, “the core” of his understanding of “political science as practical science” requires “an account of how the various institutional pieces” of the regime “can be made to fit.” This “must be an effort to hold fast to two principles that are not easy to reconcile: (1) that the basic organizing principles of the society must, in some form, be subject to political decision and (2) that the state must not be allowed to arrange the daily lives of individuals.” The problem is that practice, or political science, depends on theory, or political philosophy. 

     

    Note

    1. On Chastellux, see “Chastellux on ‘Public Happiness’ in the Ancient World” and “Chatellux on ‘Public Happiness’ in the Modern World” on this website under the category, “Philosophers” and “Chastellux in America” under the category, “American Regime.”

     

     

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • …
    • 74
    • Next Page »