Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World
  • What’s So Funny About the Law?

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    French Factionalism

    December 14, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Charles Tilly: The Contentious French. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1986.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, May 13, 1987.

     

    Traditional history is political history. Herodotus and Thucydides record popular customs, but they concentrate their attentions on the politikoi, the men of the polis—rulers or statesmen. But in the last two centuries, as democracy and its attendant egalitarianism have advanced in Western Europe and the Americas, historians have looked more carefully at ‘the commons.’ Jules Michelet, the great oratorical historian of the French Revolution, titled one of his books, simply, The People, and such later Frenchmen as Fernand Braudel and his followers have in many respects continued this populist emphasis.

    Because the people do not rule directly in modern republics, and have not ruled at all in most previous regimes, democratic historians tend to shunt politics aside. Social and economic life concern them proportionately more. With Marx, some call politics superficial, ‘epiphenomenal,’ a thing determined by underlying socio-economic ‘forces.’

    Charles Tilly refutes the Marxist or neo-Marxist view. His refutation is all the more convincing for its being inadvertent. Tilly gives every evidence of believing himself a neo-Marxist of some sort, but his scholarly diligence surpasses his apparent ideological assumptions, and corrects them.

    He begins in the approved neo-Marxist style: “‘Sedition,’ ’emotion,’ ‘mutiny,’ ‘riot,’ and ‘disturbances’ are terms of disapproval, power-holders’ words.” He prefers “contention,” and indeed no sane person ever denied that the French are contentious. Tilly shows how the forms of popular contention in France changed with the economic concentration of power in capitalism and the political concentration of power in the modern state.

    His “point of reference… differ[s] greatly from that of most political history.” He believes “that a new era has begun not when a new elite holds power or a new constitution appears, but when ordinary people begin contending for their interests in new ways.” Perhaps because it would be difficult to call attention to modern “statemaking,” as Tilly does, and then to relegate politics to the status of mere ‘superstructure,’ he avers that almost everything is political: “politics concerns power in all its guises.” (Thus do feminist neo-Marxists speak of ‘sexual politics’ and ‘the politics of the family,’ realms usually regarded as private.)

    Tilly gives his study a useful specificity (Marxists say, ‘concreteness’) by attending to five diverse regions of France: Burgundy, Anjou, Paris and its suburbs, Languedoc, and Flanders. The largest portion of his book concerns the seventeenth century, but he carries his narrative into the 1980s.

    Seventeenth-century France saw the consolidation of monarchic authority at the expense of what remained of the feudal aristocracy. Louis XIII and Louis XIV unified France by war: the combined pressures of foreign enemies, French military power, and domestic taxation, dissolved the independent authority of the aristocracy, fusing it to the central state. Before mid-century, peasant food riots (Tilly calls them “grain seizures”) often had the support of anti-royal aristocrats; after the Fronde, the aristocrats were co-opted and the peasants were on their own.

    In this, Tilly shows, capitalism was royalism’s tool. To finance wars and to circumvent the aristocracy, the Crown deliberately promoted taxable commerce. French capitalism grew because the kings wanted it to. Truly, “waxing capitalism and growing state power walked hand in hand,” but more than that, politics led economics by the hand.

    Rebellion did not disappear. It became “more plebeian.” “Class war was on the way.” In marking the transition from monarchy to the republic in the eighteenth century, Tilly slights Alexis de Tocqueville. In The Old Regime and the Revolution, Tocqueville likewise shows how absolute monarchy brought on republicanism, which then brought on Bonapartism, by centralizing political power and by replacing the rule of law and guidance by clergy with (not to put too fine a point on it) money. Tilly’s analysis suffers badly in contrast to Tocqueville’s, as the latter carefully measures political and intellectual currents along with social and economic ones. Tilly labors under the simplistic, Marxist dichotomy between material interests, which are “real,” and principles (“natural rights and reason”), which are said merely to “clothe” the “real” interests. Tocqueville commits no such crudities; as a real politician, he knew better.

    Tilly observes that while monarchic state-building tended toward standardization in language, administration, laws, and forms of coercion, capitalism tended toward differentiation, with different geographic regions specializing in different products. This may partly explain why capitalism survived and indeed thrived after the 1789 revolution, while its progenitor, the Old Regime, died—this, despite the fact that capitalist management of food distribution caused at least as much resentment as royalist conscription and taxation.

    Republicanism in one sense accelerated political centralization. “If there was any quintessentially revolutionary act in France as a whole, it was the seizure of power in municipalities by committees acting in the name of the nation,” committees linked to “a national network centered in Paris.” “No king ever built such a structure,” which included direction intrusion into local church prerogatives and strong, pervasive police powers. That it also included, after Bonaparte would again include, political representation of the people on all levels of government, is a fact our neo-Marxist historian prefers not to stress.

    Popular contention changed with these political changes, but slowly, reactively. Not until 1848 did the old forms of contention—”grain seizures,” temporary occupation of privately-owned land, protests against tax collectors—finally give way entirely to rallies, strikes, and demonstrations. (That food riots declined because “capitalist agriculture” actually feeds more people than pre-capitalist agriculture does not find its way into Tilly’s account.) And while he rightly points to the decline in agricultural population, particularly in the twentieth century, Tilly neglects to say that this means his “ordinary people” are no longer ordinary, that commercial republicanism satisfies new types of “ordinary people,” that rallies, strikes, and demonstrations therefore rarely threaten the commercial republican regime itself, although they may help to topple a government. The heart of a neo-Marxist throbs softly to the beat of sentimental populism, to a half-imaginary past of agrarian virtue and hardy independence. Neo-Marxism amounts to the syncopation of revolutionary ardor with nostalgia.

    Tilly’s egalitarianism animates his scholarship. This serves his readers well more often than not, as he uncovers and reports masses of illuminating information that might otherwise gather dust in regional archives. When that egalitarianism overwhelms his scholarship, he may unwittingly mislead those vulnerable to losing their way in data. Tilly denigrates the forms of ‘elite’ politics, and of political institutions generally, even as he uncovers the decisive effects of those forms. The French have been so contentious because they have contended over regimes, and such struggles are harder to settle by compromise than food shortages or even property rights. And in focusing so exclusively on popular contention, he obscures the success of commercial republicanism, the regime wherein “ordinary people” feel most at home, once they know its forms by experience.

    Filed Under: Nations

    Adams on Madison

    December 14, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Henry Adams: History of the United States of America during the Administrations of James Madison. New York: The Library of America, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, April 8, 1987.

     

    ‘Leadership’ obsesses political commentators today. Strong leadership is good, weak bad. ‘History’ is said to be going somewhere, and leaders are to take us there, quickly and efficiently.

    But leadership is not statesmanship. A statesman may lead; he may also follow, or seem to. More than that, he cultivates. He cultivates the character and circumstances of citizens, with a view to a particular achievement of the human good.

    Henry Adams’s history of James Madison’s presidency shows us an unusually intelligent, careful historian who is also a historicist—one who believes that ‘History’ wholly encompasses individuals—as he tries to assess a statesman who was no historicist. Adams exercises his considerable wit by turns sneering at leader-worship and deriding inept leaders. He overlooks statesmanship.

    Adams wants to do justice to Madison: “always a dangerous enemy, gifted with a quality of persistence singularly sure in its results,” Madison “rarely failed to destroy when he struck.” But Adams’s judgment of Madison, and of what constitutes doing justice to him, is low. He complains of the “colorless character” of Madison’s oratory, while conceding it was “intended to disarm criticism,” not to quicken some historian’s pulse. A poor administrator, “never showing great power as a popular leader,” Madison lacked la grande passion . For that reason, Adams, devotee of force, falls rather out of patience with “this circumspect citizen”—who, unaccountably by Adams’s lights, “paid surprisingly little regard to rules of consistency or caution” when pursuing some “object which seemed to him proper in itself.”

    Completed in 1891, the full, nine-volume History spans the administrations of Jefferson and Madison. There can be no question: It remains the most gracefully written, scrupulous, and penetrating major history ever written by an American. Adams shows how the Jeffersonians won resounding victories against the Federalist Party, then gradually adopted Federalist principles in practice. What began as a movement for states’ rights, ended by strengthening the Federal government. Adams takes this to illustrate the historicist thesis, that social and economic forces finally overwhelm the intentions of statesmen, and that historians therefore should study not individuals so much as society, in “the same spirit and by the same methods” as other scientists study “the formation of a crystal.”

    In Jefferson’s case, Adams may well be right. All his life, Jefferson condemned centralized government, yet his Louisiana Purchase was a Hamiltonian exercise of presidential power at the service of (sound) geopolitical calculation if ever there was one. Madison, however, presents a more complex problem.

    After all, Madison had collaborated with Alexander Hamilton years before, writing the two most important essays in The Federalist. His conduct throughout the 1787 Constitutional Convention promoted energetic national government and vigorous commerce—the bonds of union, not of ‘states’ rights.’

    By the year 1809, when he succeeded Jefferson in the White House, Madison had of course publicly associated himself with Jeffersonian doctrines. How strongly did he believe them? If Jefferson could prudently relax his doctrinal muscles, the better to catch Louisiana, might not the circumspect Mr. Madison permit himself even less partisan dogmatism?

    Eight years of Jeffersonianism had left the War Department in a shambles and the Treasury almost bankrupt. Mediocrities peopled both Congress and the Executive branch. Madison at first did little, and perhaps could do little, to resist the decline. Adams suggests that by 1811 the federal union itself was in jeopardy.

    Madison “did not want a distinct issue of peace or war with England,” which had been harrying American shipping and impressing our sailors. He pursued a policy of “peaceful coercion”—commercial restrictions of English trade—so that American commerce could develop its own strength at its own pace. The English didn’t cooperate, and the War of 1812 began with the American Army guided by generals who combined the exhaustion of old age with the ill judgment of inexperience in war.

    “The process by which a scattered democracy decided its own will, in a matter so serious as a great and perhaps fatal war, was new to the world; bystanders were surprised and amused at the simplicity with which the people disputed plans of war and peace, giving many months of warning and exact information to the enemy, while they showed no signs of leadership, discipline, or union, or even a consciousness that such qualities were needed.” The United States may have been the first nation in history “to hope that the war itself might create the spirit they lacked.”

    Madison prosecuted the war energetically. The spikes of Adams’s criticism cannot quite puncture the statesman’s tough hide: “If a strong government was desired, any foreign war, without regard to its object, might be good policy, if not good morals, and in that sense President Madison’s war was the boldest and most successful of all experiments in American statesmanship, though it was also among the most reckless.” Because strong government was Federalist Party doctrine, not Jefferson’s, Adams doubts that Madison had this in mind. But Madison had read his Montesquieu, and had lived through the Revolutionary War. He knew war’s centralizing tendency, could not have been so naïve as to suppose America to be exempt from it, and, while perhaps not intending war, did not abase himself in order to avert it. When it occurred, he put it to use.

    The first two years of conflict actually weakened national unity, bringing the Anglophile Federalists of New England one step away from secession. But “little by little the pressure of necessity compelled Congress and the country to follow Madison’s lead.” He sent his best men to negotiate a peace treaty with England, and they did–after battlefield events convinced the British government to accept reasonable terms.

    Madison underlined the lesson in his 1815 Message to Congress: “Experience has taught us that neither the pacific dispositions of the American people, nor the pacific character of their political institutions, can altogether exempt them from that strife which appears, beyond the ordinary lot of nations, to be incident to the actual period of the world”—the period of the Napoleonic Wars. “Experience demonstrates that a certain preparation for war is not only indispensable to avert disasters in the onset, but affords the best security for the continuance of peace.” And the preparation for war that secures peace requires a strong federal government.

    Madison had known these truisms twenty-five years before the War of 1812. Had he forgotten them in the 1800s, only to relearn them as president?

    It is more plausible to think that this quiet little man, “always treated by his associates with a shade of contempt as a closet politician,” more theorist than man of affairs, waited for years, with a farmer’ vigilant patience, for the seeds of 1787 to mature into the harvest of 1815. Then peace and prosperity” “put an end to faction.” In 1787, James Madison had predicted the diminution of faction’s effects, if not its “end,” thanks precisely to the soothing effects of peaceful commerce, prospering under the aegis of Constitutional union. By then, experience had taught Americans lessons that Madison and the other Founders arranged for our political conditions to teach.

    And it may be that the resolutely unheroic Mr. Madison moved unobtrusively among such forceful men as Hamilton and Jefferson, allowing them to use him, the better to use them, in rather the same way Madison’s Constitution invites us to use it, pursuing our own purposes but bending them to our own good. Henry Adams admires force, albeit with a touch of irony. James Madison understood force, and used it for the good of his country. His “new science of politics” excels Adams’s newer science of history, because it is a genuine science, one that never confuses men with crystals.

     

    2017 Note:
    For the last decade, Robert Eden of the Hillsdale College Politics Department has been preparing a study of Adams’s History in which he will argue that Adams himself partook of a sort of literary statesmanship that featured exactly the sort of prudent indirection Madison practiced in politics. I happily expect to ‘stand corrected’ by Bob’s interpretation, as it should raise Henry Adams even higher than before, to or even in a sense above the level of the great men he studied.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Fascism in France, Misunderstood

    December 13, 2017 by Will Morrisey

    Alice Yaeger Kaplan: Reproductions of Banality: Fascism, Literature, and French Intellectual Life. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, May 27, 1987.

     

    Neo-Marxism means Marxism plus whatever’s trendy. It has colonized many university departments in the United States—mostly in the social sciences but increasingly in the humanities, as well. Alice Yaeger Kaplan’s study of fascism among French intellectuals before the Second World War excels many products of this ideology. She writes what she calls “progressive” literary criticism, trying to nudge fascism into refuting itself. But her lively mind is so honest, it allows readers to nudge neo-Marxism into refuting itself, too.

    Almost every extended act of literary criticism today begins with a discussion of ‘theory,’ the scholar’s beliefs about language and ‘texts.’ Because almost no literary scholar today has any real knowledge of philosophy, these exercises incline toward confusion. Kaplan burns the obligatory incense before such idols as psychoanalysis, feminism, the Frankfurt School, and ‘deconstructionism.’ She is best when her intelligence ascends from the cave of academic fashion and sees for itself.

    She notices the many contradictory elements in fascism: elitism and populism, modernism and primitivism, paternalism and “mother-bound feelings,” ‘Right’ and ‘Left.’ But she also wants to show how fascism—the world derived from the Latin fasces, the axe with rods bundled around its handle, symbol of authority in ancient Rome—could bind together disparate ideas and sentiments, make them into a usable instrument of political power—the ‘totality’ of totalitarianism, that word Mussolini invented to name a new form of tyranny. She patiently looks for coherence beneath the apparent contradictions, eschewing the partisan histrionics that mar so much Marxist writing.

    She does find several coherent patterns, but presents them in a way that reveals her ideology’s defects. Following the neo-Marxist cultural critic Walter Benjamin, she accurately observes that many fascist intellectuals veil economic and political reality with esthetic categories. Such men can even “describe objects that are used to kill as if they are purely creative.” She concedes that this strategy “is not necessarily fascist; we have seen it since.” She does not say where. She might be thinking of the less extreme ‘New Left’ rhetoric of the 1960s and early ’70s. (“Small is beautiful,” they claimed.) If so, estheticism does not distinguish fascism from other ideologies, including at least some variants of neo-Marxism.

    The same criticism weighs against many other insights Kaplan offers. Yes, as the fascist state establishes itself, “the populist ideal” of revolutionary fascism “mutates toward an elitist one”—but the same is true under communism and even, to a much lesser degree, in republics. True, the lack of a strong middle class made Italy and Germany more vulnerable to fascism than was France—but the same held true for the conditions of Marxist victories in Russia and China. Granted, fascism used intellectuals, then swept them aside after gaining power—as did Marxists, who used ‘fellow travelers’ in exactly the same way (and this doesn’t make the latter Marxists, or even proto-Marxists). Unquestionably, fascists use language to subvert truth—as do totalitarians of the ‘Left’ and, more moderately, almost all rhetoricians. Fascists did indeed “place invective on the side of science” (or maybe vice-versa), but in this they could teach nothing to Stalin and his Lysenko.

    I do not suggest that Kaplan should have written as extensively about communists, or French communists; authors need not be taxed for the books they choose not to write. But by almost entirely omitting any reference to communism, she goes too easy on her own Marxism and fails properly to ‘frame’ her picture of French fascism. She sees that fascism “was conceived by its enthusiasts as a new form of revolt, competitive with Marxism,” but she neglects to show concretely how this—so to speak—dialectic worked.

    The neo-Marxist emphasis on political economy, psychology, and esthetics neglects the moral dimension of politics. Her dismissal of “moralism” serves Kaplan fairly well in her chapters on Marinetti and Céline, but it spoils her chapters on Sorel and Drieu la Rochelle, and weakens those on fascist broadcasters and film critics. Sorel’s notion of the general strike, for example, appeals less to estheticism than to a kind of morality: to heroism, and particularly to the refusal of vengefulness even within a violent revolution. Drieu la Rochelle’s anti-feminism, along with his admiration for ‘masculine’ warrior virtues, likewise comes from a moral impulse; he does not so much celebrate killing (as Kaplan would have it), but risk, self-sacrifice.

    Kaplan makes much of the “banality” of French fascist writing, by which she means its apparently “unserious” character, the unthreatening frivolity that makes it easy to ignore but also easy to disseminate among the unwary. This is oversophisticated. Not “banality” but fascism’s undeniable appeal to the spirited virtues neglected in modern democratic life—courage, honor, manliness—makes it dangerous. Without that, and left with only the likes of Céline, fascism would have little or no attractive force, even among intellectuals.

    And even insofar as fascist writers were “banal” or unserious, does that really set them apart from much of the inter-war Parisian literary scene generally? Only racism and economic conservatism appear to distinguish fascism from communism. On economics, Kaplan asserts that fascism subordinates it to “ideology.” This is true, but not in the way she means it: in Germany and Italy, “the economic structures of the fascist state are basically unchanged from those of the capitalist one.” Obviously, no major aggrandizement of the state can leave an economy “basically unchanged,” a fact embarrassing to Marxists, whose states never get around to withering away (as promised by Lenin) precisely because they too put ideology above economics.

    This leaves racism, or at least nationalism. Because Kaplan’s neo-Marxism prevents sympathy for nationalism, she cannot begin to account for its appeal to French intellectuals. Without that account, she cannot adequately explain the virulently racist nationalism of the worst fascists.

    “Fascism seems to be about making life into art—a transformation that promises to give artists an enormous role.” This appearance pleases certain notable inclinations both intellectual and French. Yet Marxism in its own way also wants to transform life into art. So, in a different way, does capitalism. And what of ‘post-modernism itself? Does it not attempt to The whole modern enterprise, beginning with Machiavelli, is ‘about’ using human art to conquer nature. If this is a problem, and I think it is, then neo-Marxism cannot solve it. Neo-Marxism cannot get past its own deeply modern presumptions.

    Filed Under: Nations

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 186
    • 187
    • 188
    • 189
    • 190
    • …
    • 225
    • Next Page »