Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Plato–Short, Sweet, and Aporetic

    February 11, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Thomas L. Pangle, ed.: The Roots of Political Philosophy: Ten Forgotten Dialogues. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1987.

    Originally published in Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy. Volume 21, Number 3, Spring 1994. Republished with permission.

     

    Perplexingly inconclusive, Plato’s short Socratic dialogues appear to offer little promise to those who ask, How did the founder of political philosophy understand his own enterprise? The suspect genealogy of the dialogues makes scholarly neglect seem all the more reasonable. Is there really anything to learn here?

    As it happens, there is, and this collection of careful translations and commentaries makes the learning easier to begin and, better, harder to conclude. “To confront, to take seriously, to become captivated by, these shorter dialogues,” Professor Pangle writes, “is to discover a Socrates who shakes the foundations of many of our conventional assumptions about what and how Socrates and Plato might have thought.” It might be noted that some of the scholarly refusal to take these dialogues seriously as authentic Platonic works may stem from a reluctance to take seriously certain Socratic challenges to conventions. Whatever the historical evidence may be, a willingness to read these dialogues as authentic begins to separate thoughtful or potentially thoughtful students from ‘pure’ scholars. The contributors to this volume combine scholarship with thoughtfulness.

    Allan Bloom finds in the Hipparchus a confrontation between a philosopher and a democrat—the latter no fanatic, but simply an ordinary man who loves money in a ‘decent’ or law-abiding way. The dialogue shows how such decency poses a serious threat to the philosopher’s way of life. Both democrat and philosopher love gain. They differ radically in their conceptions of what is truly gainful.

    The conventional decency of law, upon which money rests, concerns Socrates in the Minos. Leo Strauss shows that law, associated with opinion but also intended to guide opinion, is highly problematic with respect to knowledge. At the same time, “The Minos raises more questions than it answers,” thereby offering readers not so much knowledge as doubt and wonder, neither of which conduce to lawmaking in any ordinary sense.

    This leads one to the quest for knowledge, a quest that cannot be sustained without a love of knowledge. Christopher Bruell emphasizes the distinction, in the Lovers, between the noble, which attracts the well-born, honor-loving, youths of Athens, and the good, associated more with the useful. Political philosophy requires study of the noble, although the study itself is more good than noble. When the noble know their own nobility, they transcend mere nobility; political philosophy constitutes “a needed preliminary to philosophizing.” In this sense, decent political life provides the necessary but not sufficient ground for philosophic life, which nonetheless is in tension with it.

    Given this dispensable indispensability of decent political life, can a philosopher or anyone else promote that life by teaching virtue? The Cleitophon, in Clifford Orwin’s words, depicts one of “those surprisingly rare occurrences in Plato, an encounter with a practicing statesman.” The statesman charges Socrates with the inability to teach citizen virtue. Orwin finds in the dialogue tension “between doing what is good for oneself and doing what is good for others.” Socrates avoids answering Cleitophon’s charge; this is “one of the few” dialogues “that never mentions philosophy,” perhaps because Cleitophon’s certitude with respect to the unmitigated goodness of justice cannot, and in a sense should not, be shaken. He requires clarity, answers, while Socrates would raise perplexities, questions. If a sound political regime provides the needed foundation for philosophic life, should a philosopher induce an able practitioner of the political life to philosophize, to examine his own moral guideposts?

    Does wisdom consist of answers or of questions? Thomas L. Pangle considers the Theages, one of the two central dialogues in the collection. the Theages depicts a private conversation, held in the portico of Zeus the Liberator, between Socrates and a father who is also a democratic statesman, understandably worried that his son wants “to become wise.” As Pangle remarks, wisdom may tempt men “to try to escape from the constraints of conventional fair play.” Theages, the son, soon reveals himself as a would-be tyrant; traditional democratic statesmanship has ‘naturally’ brought forth a child who threatens the tradition and the democracy. Socrates tactfully shows that philosophy, the love of wisdom, cannot offer a science of politics to would-be rulers. It can nonetheless strengthen the necessary pieties of political life by showing “how the traditional virtues can be made more consistent, intelligible, and self-conscious” in the face of democracy’s tendency to undermine itself by unrefined eroticism and immoderate ambition. The Theages is the Platonic answer to Aristophanes’ charges in the Clouds.

    The erotic and ambitious young democrat par excellence was Alcibiades. In the Alcibiades I Plato “depict[s] the profound transformation of an interlocutor in the course of a single conversation”—an event “almost unique among the dialogues,” in the words of Steven Forde. Socrates takes a thumotic soul and arouses its latent eroticism, particularly “to get [Alcibiades] to care earnestly for his self-perfection.” The private, though still social, “peering into the soul of another” yields self-knowledge, which includes moderation or good order of “soul and body and the parts of the soul within itself.” Statesmanship, by analogy but also by contrast, “is the proper ordering of the things belonging to many.” Forde regards this apparent resolution as questionable, given “the questionable proof of the soul” that are its foundation, and given the political career of Alcibiades, whose less-than-Socratic eroticism fascinated then repelled the Athenian demos.

    Thumos again figures in the Laches, the dialogue on courage. James H. Nichols, Jr., observes that Laches’ “commonsense, political conception of courage… rests on preserving the opinion that ridicule and disgrace, above all for not fighting bravely for the city, are more terrible than the risk of death.” Political courage thus differs profoundly from philosophic courage, which risks the city’s antagonism by unflinchingly challenging regnant opinion. Nonetheless, because “we humans are complex beings, compounded of soul and body, faced with varying situations in life,” we need to know how to apply intellectual virtue. True courage requires both natural bravery and prudence; political courage, substituting venerable opinions for prudence, will not always suffice. Neither philosophic nor political, divination—the product of “anxious forethought”—will not suffice for either the philosopher or the statesman.

    A discussion of prudence leads naturally to the topic of lying, one way of attempting to be prudent. Lying also relates to poetic myths. In his discussion of the Lesser Hippias, James Leake notes that “To regard lying as morally defensible or necessary to bring about the good, one must recognize that the good is of limited efficacy”—a recognition resisted by earnest youth of all ages—”not simply triumphant in human affairs or the cosmos.” This knowledge of limits, an instance of prudence and of moderation, forms “a necessary part of the art of politics or ruling insofar as it enables one to deal with those who are incapable of listening to reason”—enemies and friends alike. In this philosophy needs to be politic.

    Is beauty a kind of lie, or deception, and truth (like Socrates) ugly? It would be Epicurean to say so. One might read David R. Sweet’s commentary on the Greater Hippias as a suggestion that Plato anticipates Epicurus to some degree. In the dialogue, the unnamed stranger, who is Socratic, distinguishes precise speech and knowledge from conventional speech and “knowing beautifully.” “Hippias knows precisely how to speak beautifully”—and that is all he knows. The charm of beautiful things “acts as a deterrent to knowledge and prevents a man such as Hippias from seeing beneath the surface of things to the intelligible structure beneath.” The dialogue serves as “a chastening supplement to the Symposium,” which shows how beautiful things can lead the soul ‘upward.’

    Allan Bloom writes the collection’s last commentary, framing a book to which so many of his former students have contributed. One of the funniest dialogues, the Ion presents the spectacle of an utterly conventional cosmopolitan; panhellenic opinion of antiquity, like ‘global thought’ today, may well guide itself by a rather low common denominator. Bloom describes  the rhapsode Ion as book-bound; by questioning him, Socrates tests the claims made for authoritative books, specifically Homer’s books, as worthy educators of the Greeks. Socrates tests “the Greek understanding of things, particularly of the gods.” His “divine possession” argument amounts to “a tale designed to appeal to Ion’s needs and wishes”; small wonder Shelley took it seriously. In fact poetry is an art, an intelligible activity concerned with intelligible objects. Ion’s self-misunderstanding somewhat resembles that of political men. Like so many political men, people voice their fears and desires, especially with respect to their own futures. “Overcoming this concern with oneself” is philosophy’s precondition. Philosophy requires a concept of nature, permitting meaningful general speech. Philosophy permits the mind to see a cosmos or harmony, a kind of peace. Poetry, a veil for chaos or war, ultimately stops at the political level, the highest particularism.

    Plato’s Socrates carefully distinguishes the city from the philosopher. Gain-as-moneymaking versus gain-as-learning; decent laws versus knowledge, wonder, and doubt; citizen virtue versus questioning; politics versus self-perfection; political courage versus philosophic courage; poetic lies versus prudent lies; apparent beauty versus intelligibility; divine possession versus reason: Socrates explores these antinomies, defending philosophy while never forgetting the need for the city.

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    Frost and Oliver: Poets of Nature

    February 9, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Why garden? Why poeticize?
    Robert Frost and his much younger contemporary, Mary Oliver, both distinguished themselves as poets of nature, and also as poets whose audiences have far exceeded college classrooms and highbrow bookstores. This 1993 essay compares two of their best-known poems, Frost’s “Mending Wall” and Oliver’s “Writing Poems.”

     

    Gardening, human beings govern nature with art. Human art mediates between the gardener and nature. Poetry mediates among the poet, nature, and readers.

    Robert Frost knows this. His neighbor tells him, “Good fences make good neighbors.” It is Frost’s neighbor’s father’s saying, a specimen of traditional or folk wisdom. “He will not go behind his father’s saying,” Frost says of him, who repeats himself, and his father. Were Frost’s neighbor a scientist, he would study cloning, an art of exact replication. Frost’s neighbor’s soul finds its deepest satisfaction in remembering. Memory can have the drawback of mischaracterization. Frost’s neighbor calls a wall a fence, and pronounces it good.

    Frost’s deepest satisfaction lies elsewhere. Frost wants the exact word, the one that fits the nature of the thing. Frost wants to go behind the sayings of the father. Frost knows of something older than fathers, and the conventions or traditions of fathers. Nature is older than the oldest human father, even older than the oldest remembered human father.

    “Something there is that doesn’t love a wall.” Nature is what doesn’t love a wall. Nature in its entropy acts beyond human seeing and hearing, undoing the work of even the most vigilant and industrious men. Nature is somewhat mysterious, and behind it might be some greater mystery.

    Nature’s entropy does not so threaten human works as to force men into a grim struggle for survival. Mending walls is “just another kind of outdoor game.” Together, men and nature play the outdoor version of Penelope’s indoor game of weaving and unweaving. But in Frost’s outdoor game there are no threatening suitors, no need for a rescuing hero.

    Frost wants to know, Why play? He wants to know the reason for the game—what he’s walling in or out, and whether someone will take offense at his handiwork. His neighbor, “like an old-stone savage armed,” divides the world into his own and yours, us and them. He respects ancient divisions of politics and property. Frost is not so respectful, seeing the nature shared by all.

    A poem, as much an artifact as a wall, another sort of line built on another form of sand, traditionally marking out the wisdom of fathers, limning the spiritedness of political men. In the Iliad the Muse sings of the high-hearted rage of Achilles, indignant at an instance of unjust, conventional rule in a war sparked by erotic disappointment, that is, by both the frustration of erotic nature and an affront to convention. Is there also something that doesn’t love a poem?

    As a poet, Frost must wonder at the playful entropy of nature. Will it undo his artifacts? He approaches nature lightly, shrewdly, circumlocutiously, even as he questions human artifice and convention. He takes care not to question too blatantly. He lets his neighbor have the last word, lest a good neighbor become a savage and not merely resemble one, on occasion. The poet-gamesman plays the game in order to moderate the latent savagery of the convention—therefore ordinary, therefore natural—man.

    Mary Oliver takes a less prudent tone. She does not question convention. She dismisses it in two sentences, each a kind of negative command. “You do not have to be good” and “You do not have to walk on your knees” are thou-shalt-nots disputing efforts founded on another set of thou-shalt-nots. Eros replaces spiritedness or thumos, and does so directly, without conventional guides. Let “the soft animal of your body love what it loves”; “the world offers itself to your imagination” as a complaisant lover does. You are part of “the family of things,” a nature unmediated by the wisdom of fathers. This unusual family has no parents, only siblings. It is as pliable to desires as one’s imaginings are. Olivier assumes imaginings to be benign. She does not see that if all things constitute a family, all corporeal eroticism is incest. Or if she does, she regards that as just another taboo to be negated.

    Oliver’s optimism comes from her replacement of Frost’s natural law, the Second Law of Thermodynamics, the law of dissociation, with the law of love, the law of association. Bees go to rhododendron flowers in Eros’ “invisible line”; “otherwise death is everywhere.” It’s as if she’s taken Neoplatonism and made it corporeal, in the way Marx took Hegel’s dialectic and made it material. Her problem is even more acute than Marx’s, and idealism of corporeality being even less plausible than a materialist dialectic.

    The bees are like poets, Oliver supposes; they appear in a poem titled “Writing Poems.” Oliver wants poetry to be natural or erotic, not a wall against death but a beeline or a lifeline through it.

    Of these two poets, Frost is older, tougher, probably wiser. He knows that poems are artifacts, no matter how natural the impulse urging poets on. If nature is the deepest human satisfaction, and human beings can apprehend nature directly, what need is there for poems? Oliver’s left hand does not know what her writing hand is doing.

    Oliver wants to say, nature associates as well as it dissociates, lives as a precondition of dying. Poems are on the side of spontaneous life, the eros that always says yes. But she says this in a poem, not in a spontaneous outpouring. Idealism of the body leads to a didacticism of the erotic.

    The canny gamesman Frost smiles at Oliver, the earnest erotic. Eroticism is no substitute for moralism, he tells her; trying to make it that will only confuse the poet. Poetry must never go in a beeline. A one-liner isn’t a poem, and one-line poems teach aphoristically, with an indirectness resembling the dialogues composed by Plato, the wisest erotic. A poet who tries to make a poem go in a beeline will remove the reasons for poetry’s existence.

    This is also why gardeners exclude most animals from gardens. This goes for animal bodies soft and hard. Who rules? If not human beings, then it’s no longer a garden. (A garden governed by God would be another matter, and is another story.)

    The question, then, is: On what terms will human beings, whether poets or gardeners, govern nature?

     

    Filed Under: Manners & Morals

    Ideology and Literary Studies: PMLA 1930-1990

    February 9, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Originally published in altered form in Academic Questions, Volume 6, Number 1, winter 1992-93.

     

    The Controversy

    In 1970 the New Left’s critique of American literary studies reached the pages of PMLA, the journal of the Modern Language Association. Professor Frederick Crews of the University of California at Berkeley charged that literary studies in the United States had been “significantly affected by an ideological bias” (Volume 85, Number 3, p. 423). ‘Cold War’ American was “comfortable” and “corrupt.” Its universities tolerated the “perversion of scholarly research to purposes of exploitation and conquest” (423). This was occurring because capitalism had perfected “a socially manipulative style of thinking” whereby social evils were concealed from perpetrators and victims alike (423).

    This “style” of thinking, Crews argued, was exemplified by PMLA. Literary scholars did not usually bend their labor to overt service in ‘Cold War’ projects, as many university scientists did. Instead, members of the Modern Language Association drifted through life in a state of “remarkable political innocence,” ignoring “racism, imperialism, and monopoly” in favor of “myths, motifs, and morals” (424). This lack of political ‘consciousness’ exacted “an ideological cost” seen “less in what [scholars] say than in what they refuse to consider” (424). The dominant political liberalism mistook “ideological consensus for neutrality” and failed to “question capitalism itself” (426). Liberalism is at most merely reformist. It is not radical; it does not get to the root of capitalist evils. Liberalism misses the “true and important” insight that “literature conveys class meaning” (426).

    Crews wanted a literary criticism that would acknowledge socioeconomic causes of literary production, a criticism regarding literary works as “contingent, imperfect expressions of social and mental forces” (428). “[J]ustice and passion” deserve precedence over “order and sophistication” (427). Crews insisted that he did not want the “socialist” style of criticism seen in such places as the Soviet Union. Despite his obvious Marxist leanings, Crews dismissed Soviet literary criticism as “simpleminded and venal” work which made “political correctness the touchstone of esthetic value” (426). With other New-Left opponents of Soviet-style communism, Crews evidently viewed the Soviet regime as the ossified corpse of a Marxism gone wrong.

    Today, Crews’ warning resonates ironically. Appropriated not by those who heeded his call but by their critics, the phrase ‘politically correct’ has become the staple taunt of those who claim that literary studies in the United States have become ‘politicized.’ These critics charge that a leftist academic agenda, associated with such movements as multiculturalism, radical feminism, and socialism determine the articles selected for publication in PMLA. This is so, it is alleged, despite the language of PMLA‘s “Statement of Editorial Policy,” reprinted in every issue, describing PMLA as “receptive” to “all scholarly methods and theoretical approaches.” [1] Other scholars dispute these charges and defend PMLA, saying that critics exaggerate the degree to which the journal conforms to a ‘politically correct’ line. [2]

    In order to determine whether or not there is substance to the critics’ accusations, I examined the complete contents of each of nine volumes of PMLA from 1930 to 1990, selecting volumes in ten-year intervals from 1930 to 1970 and at five-year intervals thereafter. There were 457 articles in all. I classified each article in these volumes, first according to the type of critical approach it represents and also according to its ideological orientation, if any. Before presenting the results of this research, I shall briefly discuss the criteria of classification I employed.

     

    Classification
    The more important of the two kinds of classification is ‘ideology.’ For this I needed a definition of ‘ideology’ that would not predetermine the results of the study. For example, the assumption that ‘everything is political’ would lead to the result that all of the articles must be ideological, directly or indirectly—a conclusion one may all too conveniently draw without bothering with any evidence. The claim that everything is political rests on the prior claim that ostensibly apolitical scholarship in fact supports the social, political, and economic status quo by doing nothing to change the status quo. Literary scholars who write on myths, motifs, and morals—so Crews’s argument goes—ignore racism, imperialism, and monopoly, thereby leaving those evils unchallenged. Scholars who suppose themselves to be engaging in innocent study unknowingly reinforce injustice. Many are well-meaning liberals whose mildly reformist politics never get to the roots of the capitalist overgrowth. Radical scholarship, by contrast, can save the study of literature from an unintendedly reactionary irrelevance, first of all by being openly and honestly political.

    The argument fails even on its own political terms. An ‘irrelevant’ article need not support the status quo at all. ‘Objectively’—as Marxists used to say—such scholarship supports the most active, well-organized faction within the university. This may not be the faction that wields power today. It may be the one that will wield power tomorrow. The man who warned that the triumph of evil in the world will be assured if good men do nothing was no leftist radical. As a slogan, Burke’s words can be used to ‘mobilize’ support against any putative evil—’Left,’ ‘Right,’ or ‘center.’ Faculty withdrawal from campus politics or from politics generally can as easily contribute to the successes of the radical ‘Left’ as to the liberal-reformist inertia deplored by the ‘Left.’ The criticism of traditional scholarship as reactionary requires the accuser to know whether a given act of scholarship will make the success of a certain ideology more or less likely. This puts an extraordinary demand on the accuser’s powers to discern causal connections between scholarship and its practical consequences. Nor does it offer much guidance on how to find and apply such scientific and/or prophetic principles as are needed for the tasks, particularly in view of doubts concerning the predictive power of such constructs as ‘scientific socialism.’ Absent such guidance, there is nothing to prevent different people from coming to different, arbitrary conclusions about the political meaning of any particular scholarly work.

    While avoiding this or any other excessively broad definition of ‘ideology,’ I also wanted to avoid any definition that is too narrow. One such definition limits ‘ideology’ to explicit statements of political affiliation or overt arguments for a political agenda. This would exclude all writers who possess even a minimal degree of perspicacity and tact. No scholarly article in PMLA to date has called for a lettuce boycott or a vote for Angela Davis for President. It is nonetheless fair to look for subtler clues . Whereas the excessively broad definition of ideology would be unable to aid in the detection of change (by saying that everything is and always was political), the excessively narrow definition would guarantee in advance that no article likely to appear in a scholarly journal could be called ideological. This too would prevent the perception of change, as it were ‘on principle’ or ‘by definition.’

    According to the leftist critics of modern language scholarship in the late 1960 and the ‘neoconservative’ critics today, there is something happening here. In order to be able to see if they are right, this Mr. Jones has done something that takes much less intelligence than the prophetic approach required by the broad definition of ideology, and somewhat less obtuseness than is required by the narrow definition. I have availed myself of a conventional definition of ideology, classifying PMLA articles according to the well-known ideological categories of the times in which they were written. Resisting the temptation of pornography critics who can’t define the stuff but insist they know it when they see it, I glanced first at the history of the term ‘ideology,’ which dates from the late eighteenth century. As used by such writers as Condillac and Destutt de Tracy, ideology means the department of philosophy or psychology dealing with the origin and nature of ideas. As used by Napoleon (and cited by John Adams), the term soon took on a pejorative cast, meaning an airy, abstract speculation of the sot that (according to critics) prevailed in French politics since 1792 or thereabouts. Eschewing the pejorative but retaining the political connotation, recent political scientists define ideology as any system of sociopolitical convictions and aims, as distinguished from the occasional, more or less random political animadversion. [3]

    I classify as ‘ideological’ those articles that, first, allow me reasonably to infer the author’s system of sociological opinions (‘reasonable’ meaning, at least in part, with reference to all such systems then current). Second, I classify as ‘ideological’ articles whose plausibility in some way depends upon one’s assent to a system of such opinions. That is, a random comment matters much less than a discernible (even if unstated) political opinion that determines the content of an article. [4] I do not classify as ‘ideological’ articles that take a moral as distinguished from a sociopolitical stance, inasmuch as a moral system may fit any number of ideologies—e.g., one might be a Christian and a political conservative, a liberal, a socialist, or even (if sufficiently vexed) an anarchist. Instead, I classify such articles as ‘borderline-ideological,’ inasmuch they often do suggest an ideological orientation; a critique of capitalist greed frequently if not invariably registers a ‘progressive’/socialist ideological leaning, for example.

    On the level of ‘theory’ any set of criteria can of course be subjected to the most exquisite dialectical wrangles. In practice, however, the criteria I employ are easy to apply and lead to results that at least in principle earn the concurrence of those not predisposed to disagree. For example, it isn’t hard to classify Edith Philips’ article, “French Interest in Quakers Before Voltaire”—a historical account of French literary opinion on the “Trembleurs,” as they were called, as non-ideological (Volume 45, Number 1). Similarly, no one could seriously (i.e., nonpolemically) dispute the ideological character of Suvir Kaul’s article, “Why Selina Drowns: Thomas Gray and the Domestication of the Imperial Idea”—a description and critique of the “mechanisms of social and ideological consolidation” deployed by “mercantile capitalism” (Volume 105, Number 2). Philips could be just about anything, politically. Kaul could not. He is indisputably ‘a man of the Left.’ To be sure, there are borderline cases, and I have taken these into account.

    The other, less important, system of classification is a typology of critical approaches. These I divided into historical, thematic (including ‘history of ideas’), esthetic/formal, linguistic, editorial, and theoretical—categories that suggested themselves to me as I read the journal. By a ‘historical’ article I mean one that describes events surrounding a literary work or works, including biographical, social, religious, and political events, as seen in Sanford Brown Meech’s “Chaucer and an Italian Translation of the Heroides” (Volume 45, Number 1), which shows hat Chaucer had the opportunity to read Filippo’s translation during a 1378 visit to Italy and reports textual echoes of Filippo’s work in Chaucer’s writings. By ‘thematic’ I mean he description, with or without evaluation, of the ideas of an author, as in Walter Clyde Curry’s “Destiny in Chaucer’s Troilus” (Volume 45, Number 1), which discusses “Nature-as-destiny” in Troilus and Criseyde and criticizes Chaucer’s epilogue as advancing contradictory expressions of Christian piety and heavenly mercy for a pagan hero.

    ‘Esthetic/formal’ refers to studies such as George Pope Shannon’s “Nicholas Grimald’s Heroic Couplet and the Latin Elegiac Distych” (Volume 45, Number 2), which describes the poet’s pioneering use of the heroic couplet in English and his poetry’s stylistic affinities to the poetry of neoclassicism. An esthetic/formal approach concentrates on diction, genre, metaphor, and other stylistic devices in order to show how these produce a given effect.

    ‘Linguistic’ studies focus on grammar—as seen in Charles Barret Brown’s “The Passive-Reflexive as Applied to Persons in the Primera Crónica General (Volume 45, Number 2). ‘Editorial’ studies present an edited version of a work previously unpublished or corrects an error of some previous editor—e.g., Charles Caroll Marden’s “Berceo’s Martirio de San Lorenzo from and Unpublished Manuscript (Volume 45, Number 2).

    Articles on ‘theory’ present and argue for some general understanding of literature itself. An early example is Charles Edward Whitmore’s “Some Comments on ‘Literary Theory'” (Volume 45, Number 2), with its refreshing diffidence concerning the question of whether literary theory is possible. A recent example is Susan Winnet’s “Coming Unstrung: Women, Men, Narrative, and Principles of Pleasure” (Volume 105, Number 3), which criticizes an “erotics of reading” based exclusively upon the model provided by male sexuality.

    As even these short descriptions suggest, the categories usually overlap in practice. It would be a dubious effort indeed to discuss Chaucer’s ideas without engaging in description and interpretation of contemporary historical events and without showing considerable sensitivity to his literary style. The fact that many articles mix these various critical approaches in nearly equal proportions complicates matters still further. The classifications are, then, only attempts to identify the predominant approach seen in each article.

     

    Results of the Study

    The survey resulted in three sets of statistics. One set measures the frequency of appearance in each volume of the various critical genres or approaches. The second set measures the frequency of ideological or borderline-ideological articles. The third set measures the political orientation of the ideological articles.

     

    TABLE 1: Types of Critical Approaches

    1930: 48% historical; 23% thematic/’history of ideas’; 10% linguistic; 8.5% editorial; 7.25% esthetic/formal; 1.5% theoretical.

    1940: 42% historical; 29% thematic; 14.5% esthetic/formal; 8.5% editorial; 0% theoretical.

    1950: 41% historical; 26% thematic; 18.5% esthetic/formal; 13% editorial; 1.5% linguistic; 0% theoretical.

    1960: 62% thematic; 20% historical; 10% esthetic/formal; 4.3% editorial; 1.5% linguistic; 1.5% theoretical.

    1970: 62% thematic; 16% esthetic/formal; 14% historical; 4% theoretical; 2% linguistic; 0% editorial.

    1975: 59.5% thematic; 16% historical; 13.5% esthetic/formal; 8% theoretical; 3% linguistic; 0% editorial.

    1980: 50% thematic; 29% esthetic/formal; 16.5% historical; 4% theoretical; 0% linguistic; 0% editorial.

    1985: 50% thematic; 37.5% esthetic/formal; 4% historical; 4% theoretical; 4% editorial; 0% linguistic.

    1990: 69.5% thematic; 16.5% esthetic/formal; 8% historical; 5.5% theoretical; 0% linguistic; 0% editorial.

     

    As mentioned above, few articles are ‘pure’ specimens of any one genre, and most are a mixture of genres. The above classifications merely represent judgments respecting the predominant approach taken in each article. There are articles in which two or more critical approaches are so evenly mixed that the classification is arbitrary. Still, this is not the case so often as to invalidate the overall trends shown.

    There was a marked shift from historical to thematic and esthetic/forma studies in the 1950s and 1960s, probably reflecting the increasing popularity of ‘New Critical’ methods and concerns. Theoretical studies have become more numerous in the past twenty years, but the percentages do not fully show the nature of their influence—the inevitable consequence of a ‘quantitative’ survey. Theories have become more elaborate, and literary scholars have become more self-conscious about theories. This is best illustrated by statistics cited by 1980 PMLA editor John Canarroe, who reported that Derrida, Barthes, J. Hillis Miller, and de Man were the four most frequently-cited authors in 35 papers submitted to the 1979 editorial board (Volume 95, Number 1).

     

    TABLE 2: Percentages of Ideological Articles

    1930: 0% ideological; 4% borderline-ideological.

    1940: 1.5% ideological; 1.5% borderline-ideological = 3%.

    1950: 3% ideological; 1.5% borderline-ideological = 4.5%.

    1960: 1.5% ideological; 15.5% borderline-ideological = 17%.

    1970: 10% ideological; 10% borderline-ideological = 20%.

    1975: 5.5% ideological; 11% borderline-ideological = 16.5%.

    1980: 41.5% ideological; 12.5% borderline-ideological = 54%.

    1985: 50% ideological; 12.5% borderline-ideological = 62.5%.

    1990: 52.5% ideological; 19.5% borderline-ideological = 72%.

     

    The designation ‘borderline-ideological’ refers to articles whose content was significantly determined by moral concerns but without discernible political content. (Thus a writer might show approval of a poem because it celebrates married love, but this would not tell us if the critics were an oligarch or a democrat.)

    The trend toward ideology gathered in the 1960s and achieved a decided ‘breakout’ by 1980. Comparing Table 2 with Table 1, it is notable that the ideological acceleration was preceded by the decline of the number of historical articles and, more immediately, by an increase in ‘borderline-ideological’ or moralizing articles.

     

    TABLE 3: Left-Right-Center

    1930: No ideological articles.

    1940: 1 ideological article, centrist.

    1950: 2 ideological articles, centrist.

    1960: 1 ideological article, center-rightist.

    1970: 5 ideological articles, 2 center-leftist, 3 leftist.

    1975: 2 ideological articles, leftist.

    1980: 10 ideological articles, 1 center-leftist, 9 leftist.

    1985: 12 ideological articles, leftist.

    1990: 19 ideological articles, 3 centrist, 16 leftist.

     

    The categories are conventional. “Centrist” means pro-democratic-republican; “center-rightist” means conservative; “center-leftist” means liberal. The shift to the left side of the spectrum from 1970 through 1990 is marked.

     

    From Scholarship on Ideology to Ideological Scholarship

    The earlier numbers of PMLA feature many non-ideological discussions of ideological issues in literature. PMLA writers have never neglected political issues. One difference between the scholars of 1930 (and for that matter, the vast majority of scholars before 1980) and many scholars publishing in the past twenty years is the tendency to move political/ideological opinions to the foreground of scholarship. When reading Professor Donald C. Dorian of the New Jersey College for Women on the “two-handed engine” in Milton’s Lycidas—the engine symbolizing “Christian liberty” as vindicated by Parliament against men Milton regarded as self-seeking clergy (Volume 45, Number 1, p. 207), one can find no hint of Dorian’s opinion of Milton’s opinions. The same is true of Professor Chanon Berkowitz of the University of Wisconsin, writing on how Mesonero and Jouy both deplored “the respect for social distinction” that results in a denigration of native culture and the imitation of foreign cultures (Volume 45, Number 2, p. 562), and of Sister Eugenie of St. Mary-of-the-Woods College, discussing Coleridge’s dreams of “Pantisocracy” in America (Volume 45, Number 4), and of Professor William Wister Comfort of Haverford College on the political and cultural struggle between the French and the “Saracens” as depicted in French epics (Volume 55, Number 3), of Professor W. Gordon Zeeveld of the University of Maryland on Tudor propagandists (Volume 55, Nos. 2, 4), of Professor Judith H. Anderson of Cornell University on the Knight of Justice in Spenser’s The Faerie Queene (Volume 85, Number 1), and of literally dozens more. There were even a few scholars publishing in PMLA as late as 1990, for example Andrew Galloway, a Ph.D candidate at the University of California at Berkeley, who wrote on choice and fate in Beowulf with impressive learning and no discernible ideological slant (Volume 105, Number 2).

    This scholarly approach contrasts markedly with the well-articulated ideology or constellation of ideologies dominating recent issues of PMLA. Current PMLA writers almost uniformly condemn hierarchy and authority in whatever form. The use of the word ‘subversive’ and its variants evidently gives PMLA writers a frisson they find hard to resist, as when Professor Joseph Litvak of Bowdoin College argues that Jane Austen’s “most subversive” insight is that all society is a fiction, a game (Volume 100, No. 5, p. 769). The well-known techniques of ‘deconstruction’ serve PMLA writers as tools in the advancement of this project, and ‘deconstructionism’ provides useful ideological materials as well. If, as 1974 MLA President John H. Fisher contended, “Reality is communication” (Volume 90, Number 3, p. 361), and communication refers to nothing ‘out there’ but only to the human will, then reality, including social reality, may be deconstructed and reconstructed ‘as you like it.’ Condemnation of physical punishment and other techniques of social ‘discipline’ goes with this, as these are inconvenient reminders of phenomena both nonverbal and hierarchic. Because their condemnation issues from an antipathy for hierarchy in any form, PMLA writers cannot distinguish tyranny from (for example) the practices of the Tudor and Stuart monarchies. [5]  (That there might be important political distinctions between the Tudors and the Stuarts lies even farther beyond the PMLA perspective.)

    The incapacity to make certain real-world political distinctions serves PMLA writers when they turn their hostilities toward the bourgeoisie. The bourgeoisie, you will understand, are a very bad lot. They are the sort of people described by Dickens in Little Dorrit as constructed by Professor Dianne F. Sadoff of Antioch College: “Orphanage and bastardy,” she explains, constitute “the central motivation that unites social patronage, exploitation, petit-bourgeois capitalism, and murder” (Volume 95, Number 3, p. 238). ‘Patriarchalism’ also comes in for frequent, predictable bruisings, and is explicitly linked to the imperialist bourgeoisie by Professor Suvir Kaul of the University of Delhi, who unmasks the sinister ideology of Thomas Gray’s “Ode on the Death of a Favourite Cat, Drowned in a Tub of Gold Fishes” (Volume 105, Number 2). As a rule, PMLA writers can be depended upon to know nothing about the Filmer-Locke controversy, of the opposition of real patriarchy to commercial republicanism.

    Dovetailing with the attack on hierarchy is the rejection of the concept of trans-‘cultural’ human nature and of reason, which makes knowledge of human nature possible. PMLA writers, usually alert to the ‘contradictions’ of their political enemies, give themselves much more latitude. They dismiss the principle of non-contradiction in favor of a conflation of rhetoric, ‘epistemology,’ and historicism, as in Professor Thomas Mermall’s article on Unamuno (Volume 105, Number 2). Imagination fueled by eros or desires (themselves confused with the will) replaces reason. Perhaps there is no better proof of these writers’ willfulness or arbitrariness than their conscription of Nietzsche and Heidegger into a left-communalist ideological army. [6] The most striking evidence of this ‘transvaluation’ may be seen in the appropriation of what were once the rightist obsessions with race, class, and ‘gender’ for a leftist political agenda of ‘multiculturalism.’

    PMLA writers praise oral as distinguished from written culture a vehicle for ‘multiculturalism.’ This allows them to praise non-Western, pre-modern ‘cultures’ while firmly channeling them into the correct ideological stream. Orality, they maintain, is egalitarian (you can talk back), fluid, communal; writing is legalistic, rigid, tending toward hierarchy—according to Cynthia Ward of Stanford University in her article on the African novelist Buchi Emcheta (Volume 105, Number 1). The preference for orality comports with the interest of some writers in a politics of consensus without force, in Habermas’s neo-Marxism. If this strikes some readers as utopian, PMLA writers would not blink. A politics of the imagination, a sort of poetic politics (the counterpart of Heidegger’s poetic philosophy) can ‘work’ in the ‘real’ world because the ‘real’ world is the stuff of fable. Physical power is real but brittle, depending upon mystification. What the bourgeoisie has done can be undone. Social realities are only relative to whatever mental constructs are currently believed. ‘The personal is the political,’ and what is more personal and (if you want) communal that the imagination? [7]  Imaginative (de)construction serves as almost exactly the same function as much-abominated Cartesian rationalism. It is a means of conquering sociopolitical conventions and even biology, as seen in Ann E. Hostetler’s “The Aesthetics of Race and Gender in Nella Larsen’s Quicksand” (Volume 105, Number 1). Human life, one learns here, is truly free only if self-created, resistant to any ‘alien’ or externally-imposed structures. At the same time (one must notice) because the personal is the political, individual freedom is assumed to be consistent with a soft form of totalitarianism or egalitarian communalism, a totalitarianism conflating politics and culture not in the manner of Leni Riefenstahl but more along the lines of Woodstock.

    The PMLA ideology can produce the most delicious combinations of rhetoric and reality, as when Professor Carolyn G. Heilbrun reached for an applause line in her 1984 Presidential Address: “If we lift our eyes beyond our profession, the sight of Geraldine Ferraro still dazzles” (Volume 100, Number. 3, p. 282). But for a more comprehensive example nothing excels the work of Professor Melba Cuddy-Keane of the University of Toronto. Her article, “The Politics of Comic Modes in Virginia Woolf’s Between the Acts” (Volume 105, Number 2) serves as a veritable compendium of PMLA assertins and assumptions. Cuddy-Keane begins by reaffirming that “the personal is the political” (272). By “political” she means “the dynamic of power relations in society” (273). This conception of politics is identical to that of Hobbes, and Cuddy-Keane shares Hobbes’s egalitarianism. Her recommended means of obtaining maximum social equality differ, however, from Hobbesian despotism. Virginia Woolf’s “revolutions in narrative form,” Cuddy-Keane writes, “demonstrate a continuing protest against hierarchical power structures” (273), even structures designed to promote equality.

    She explains. In Woolf’s novel, “politics and genre are fully integrated in her use of comic modes to subvert and overthrow prevailing assumptions about the role of leaders and the nature of groups” in “Western patriarchal society” (274). In this society groups are centered on the ‘leader’ or primal father; they are animated by beliefs supporting that structure. Patriarchy culminates in Hitler. Woolf’s alternative is a “decentering of authority” (274). She uses narrative to suggest that “fragmentation permits a new and fluid sense of community” (274). The title refers to the chorus (representing the community, not the individual) ‘between the acts’ of Greek tragedies. To redirect readers’ attention to the chorus “subverts the habitual dominance of the leader figure” and erases “the insider-outsider dichotomy,” both of which cause conflict (275).

    Not tragedy but comedy “provides the chorus with its true identity,” and comedy is Woolf’s genre (275). She avoids satire in this novel because satire is exclusive, aiming at the destruction of the other. Woolf writes “amiable comedy” (277), restorative not disciplinary. Women generally should be “outsiders in opposition to society’s competitive hierarchy”; Woolf’s protagonist participates in society without “changing her nature as an outsider” (279). Woolf thus “redefines inclusiveness,” rejecting social homogeneity for a “social dynamics of heterogeneity,” “celebrat[ing] an irreversible dismantling of order and actually advocat[ing] permanent instability” (279-280). Woolf’s envisioned community is a “fragmented, questioning, contradictory, but fully collective voice” (280). “The resulting ‘chaos’ is not apocalyptic but revolutionary, and in a fully political sense”—”an undifferentiated and participatory communal form” (283). The “collective voice” that is the new community is “communal without being coercive,” hence “more individualist than the voice of the spokesperson” or ‘leader’ (283). The community is “not an identity but a process” (283). It all reminds me of the floor of the New York Stock Exchange, maybe without the money exchanged.

    In a journal governed by a set of principles that attempt to square the circle of heterogeneity or personal freedom and egalitarian communalism, the most telling practical test will come in the way dissenters are treated. In the PMLA ‘community’ a few dissenters are permitted. Most of them are old, distinguished, middle-of-the-road. They merely react to the actions of the ‘Left.’ In a recent volume, Wole Soyinka, the 1986 Nobel Laureate for Literature, condemned the murder of cultured Africans by African tyrants, erstwhile anti-colonialists (“the catalog of betrayal by our own kind is lengthy,” often longer than that of colonial oppression [Volume 105, Number 1, p. 117]); the distinguished novelist Mario Varga Llosa attacked historicism and tried to rehabilitate Popper’s concept of verification (Volume 105, Number 4); Professor Victor Brombert of Princeton University delivered a Presidential Address criticizing the rejection of epistemologies of apprehension for epistemologies of assertion, noticing that a politics based upon the latter foundations will never remain pluralistic for long, whatever its intentions or protestations (Volume 105, Number 3).

    Two other dissenting articles were noteworthy. The Shakespeare scholar Richard Levin attacked the Marxist-Deconstructionist nexus and added a few criticisms of “feminist Neo-Freudian critics” for good measure (Volme 105, Number 4). Both neo-Marxists and feminists use deconstructionist techniques to make Shakespeare into a mouthpiece for themselves. What was remarkable was not so much the article itself as the reaction it provoked. Discipline swift and sure followed in PMLA’s letters section. Professor Daniel Boyarin of the University of California called Levin’s article (“to speak generously”) “disingenuous in the extreme,” characterized by “demagoguery” and “sophistry” (Volume 106, Number 2, pp. 314-315). Critics of Levin’s “ilk” “serve only the continued dominance of a particular gender [male], class [the bourgeoisie], and culture [Western]” by appealing to pleasure in literary study (315). Professor Jeffrey Williams of East Carolina University scored Levin’s “tone of condescension,” his “disturbing and disempowering” argument (Volume 106, Number 3, p. 531-532). And Professor Margot FitzGerald condemned “Levin’s sneering and nastiness,” so typical of “capitalist boosters” (Volume 106, No. 5, p. 1173). [8]

     

    Conclusion

    In a 1990 article introducing an issue of PMLA devoted to the issues surrounding literary criticism, Professor Herbert Lindenberger of Stanford University called “ideological analysis” a “particular generational style of thought” (Volume 105, Number 3, p. 406). This “style,” he opined, amounted to a reaction to “the unusually conservative regimes that reigned”—”reigned,” yes, one must admire the mastery of the rhetorical turn—”throughout the 1980s in Great Britain and the United States” (p. 406). Notwithstanding the putatively devastating effect of conservative governments on sensitive literary academics, the contemporary PMLA New Left began its project well before then. The decade of leveraged buyouts and Adolfo fashions may have thrust much grit into professorial oysters, inducing such pearls of scholarship as I have reviewed, but the oysters themselves hatched twenty years earlier in beds provided by unusually liberal governments in the United States.

    To be sure, ideological influences on PMLA writers go back even further than Crews and New-Left neo-Marxism. A 1940 article by Professor John Blankenagel of Wesleyan University summarized the principal sentiments and aims of German Romanticism. He cited Friedrich Schlegel, who wanted to blend poetry, philosophy, and rhetoric, “creative genius and criticism” (Volume 55, No. 1, p. 3). This synthetic effort, this “effacing of border lines,” reminded Blankenhagel of a secularized form of medieval Catholicism, and no wonder, given the Romantics’ admiration for the medieval romans, and their distaste for Enlightenment rationalism.

    The German Romantic synthesis (to use a word they popularized) went beyond a synthesis of forms. “Poetry becomes a symbol of the infinite,” and “life is poetry” (3-4). Ergo, life is infinite: “The very soul of romanticism was infinite longing without goal, limit, or object” (6). Unlike medieval Catholicism, German Romanticism did not restrict the object of this longing to another, better world than this one. “To become God, to be man, to develop one’s faculties, are one and the same thing” to the German Romantics (6). In religion these impulses led to immanentism, as distinguished from Christian creationism. In politics, they led to nationalism; in Fichte and Kleist “the idea of totality and of organic development held by early romanticists was now applied in a new and more realistic manner to the state, society, and history” (9). In literary matters, the German Romantics held that “One of the finest flowers of creative imagination was the fairy tale”—’folkish’ and oral, not sophisticated and written-down (9). So much of this resembles the preoccupations of the PMLA today that it is likely that German Romanticism, as filtered through Heidegger and ‘synthesized’ with Marxism, deserves credit as a wellspring of PMLA sentiment. The nationalism is of course out of favor, but it has been replaced by what is effectively a democratized plethora of nationalisms called ‘multiculturalism.’

    Much nearer to home was the 1962 Port Huron Statement, that seminal document of the New Left. The Statement excoriated “the hypocrisy of American ideals.” The American Founders’ declaration that all men are created equal “rang hollow” in a country where civil rights were denied to a racial minority; America’s “proclaimed peaceful intentions” were belied by “economic and military investments in the Cold War status quo.” Americans’ “contentment amidst prosperity” was really “a glaze above deeply felt anxieties,” anxieties that could only be removed by “truly democratic” ways of life. “Participatory democracy,” unlike representative democracy or republicanism, could end the various existential maladies afflicting our “human relationships,” including “loneliness, estrangement, and isolation.” The authors of the Statement simultaneously insisted that their society could “be organized to encourage independence” and the “creative spirit” in individuals. Because “the university is located in a permanent place of social influence,” because it is “a crucial institution in the formation of social attitudes,” the “new left” should recruit “younger people” there, while working toward a “political synthesis” of socialism and liberalism. The New Left “must import major public issues into the curriculum—research and teaching on problems of war and peace is an outstanding example.” Then, “from its schools and colleges across the nation a militant left might awaken its allies, and by beginning the process towards peace, civil rights, and labor struggles, reinsert theory and idealism where too often reign confusion and political barter” (emphasis added). Frederick Crews transferred these sentiments to the pages of PMLA, and they continue to fuel the agenda of today’s academic ‘Left.’

    The New Left’s attempt to maximize liberty, equality, and fraternity all at the same time never made much sense, but neither did the even grander syntheses proposed by the German Romantics. Put in American terms, the professors love Whitman, the all-inclusive individual, but they resemble Emerson. Professors are of a priestly not a prophetic nature. Modern bourgeois life has been hard on priests because it tolerates them, neither fearing nor hating them. Seeing comedy in this is perhaps too easy. Surely there is also a certain poignancy in seeing persons so thoroughly unfitted for the modern world, bravely insisting that they can yet be unacknowledged or even acknowledged legislators of humanity. Be this as it may, it is fair to conclude that behind PMLA’s pluralism with respect to race, class, and gender resides a variegated but nonetheless thoroughgoing political monism, firmly left-wing. [9]

     

    NOTES

    1. For a recent, representative statement against “the multiculturalist imperative” among MLA members, see Roger Kimball, “The MLA in Chicago,” The New Criterion, Volume 9, Number 6, 8-17.
    2. See Michael Abramowitz, “Literature Professors Look Inward and Find Scant Evidence of ‘PC,'” The Washington Post, January 3, 1992.
    3. See John K. Roth and Robert C. Whittemore, eds.: Ideology and American Experience: Essays on Theory and Practice in the United States (Washington: The Washington Institute Press, 1986), p. 6.
    4. For example, in the 1930 volume, Walter Clyde Curry suggests that Criseyde’s attempts to defy Fortune may be an expression of “feminine childishness” (Volume 45, Number 1, p. 149). (He less-than-evenhandedly refers to Troilus’ “childish railings”—but not ‘masculine childishness,’ a few pages later (p. 153). Forty years later, John I. Ades slights “middle-class morality” (Volume 85, Number 4, p. 526). Such passing remarks raise suspicions that ideology may be present, but in neither case does ideology govern the article as a whole.
    5. See for example Karen Cunningham, “Renaissance Execution and Marlovian Elocution: The Drama of Death” (Volume 105, Number 2) and Bruce Thomas Boehrer, “Renaissance Overeating: The Sad Case of Ben Jonson” (Volume 105, Number 5). Boehrer’s article is an especially flagrant example of the conflation of monarchism, the bourgeoisie, and “totalitarian politics” (p. 1078).
    6. See for example Victoria Kahn on Habermas (Volume 105, Number 3). For a critique of Heidegger’s attempt to meld poetry and philosophy for political purposes see Nicholas Rand, “The Political Truth of Heidegger’s ‘Logos’: Hiding in Translation” (Volume 105, Number 3).
    7. See Morris Eaves on William Blake and the Romantics’ “society of the imagination” (Volume 95, Number 5, p. 795). See also Elissa S. Guralnik on radio and the imagination (Volume 105, Number 2) and C. Christopher Soufas on Calderon’s La vida es sueño; the latter article opposes imagination, sensuality, and sociopolitical ‘participation’ to rationality (Volume 100, Number 4).
    8. In an earlier article, Levin had criticized a particular strain of feminist critics he called “gender thematists,” who hold the view that women as such are healthy but men as such are sick (Volume 103, No. 1, pp. 125-137). He was chastised in a letter signed by 24 professors accusing him of committing “pseudohistory,” paternalism, and “crude Aristotelianism” (Volume 104, Number 1, p. 77). Among other points,  Levin noted in response that he was a member of the National Association of Women. The whole spectacle impelled Professor Ward Parks of Louisiana State University to write that Levin, “as an established academic and an unusually courageous man, maybe be able to survive such treatment, but new scholars who need to get published and to find jobs very probably could not” (Volume 108, Number 2, p. 353).
    9. The 280-page study upon which this article is based is on file at the offices of the National Association of Scholars, Princeton, New Jersey.

     

    2018 Note

    After this article was published in a heavily-edited version by Academic Questions, the editor of PMLA, Domna C. Stanton, was quoted in a brief piece published in The Chronicle of Higher Education as calling it “pitiful,” a term egalitarians deploy when they really mean “contemptible” but, being egalitarians, prefer not to appear to enforce a social hierarchy. The Chronicle kindly published my reply in its April 7, 1993 issue:

    To the Editor:

    Thank you for publishing a report (‘In’ Box, March 3) on my article, “Ideology and Literary studies: PMLA 1930-1990,” which appeared in the most recent issue of Academic Questions. 

    In the report, PMLA editor Domna C. Stanton was quoted as describing my article as “pitiful,” on the grounds that “Everyone from Euripides to Eudora Welty is ideological.” She added that PMLA employs more than 500 scholars in its peer-review process.

    I am always grateful for any expression of human sympathy directed at my work, Mrs. Stanton’s pity included. I tenderly return the sentiment with respect to her comprehension of my article. I never claimed that prominent authors are not “ideological.” I claimed that articles about them need not be, and that most recent PMLA articles are.

    To say “Euripides was a Socratic,” or “Eudora Welty was influenced by Southern Agrarianism,” is to make a non-ideological statement concerning ideology. Writers in PMLA once put perception and description ahead of ideological gesticulation. In increasing numbers they no longer do.

    As for that demi-legion of peer reviewers, the demonstrable results of their efforts show just how ideologically motivated many in the profession have become.

    So far, no one has made the really damning case against my article: that it betrays an inordinate expense of time and effort in attempting to prove the obvious.

    Will Morrisey

     

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 167
    • 168
    • 169
    • 170
    • 171
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »