Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    The Philosopher-King: A Contradiction in Terms?

    April 8, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    According to Allan Bloom, Socrates makes the first statement by any thinker of the principle of non-contradiction. “It’s plain that the same thing won’t be willing at the same time to do or suffer opposites with respect to the same part and in relation to the same thing” (436b). Socrates is discussing the three ‘parts’ of the soul, but introduces the principle of non-contradiction with physical examples: the man standing still and waing his arms; the top that spins without moving its axis. The principle of non-contradiction is not only a principle of the mind. In Locke, for example, non-contradiction comes in at the sensual level; it isn’t only that there cannot be something shaded ‘blackwhite’ but that such a thing is inconceivable. The principle of non-contradiction inheres in all of being, ‘inner’ and ‘outer.’

    1. Why Noēsis?
    Central to the Republic is 473d, where Socrates makes his most outrageous claim: There is “no rest from the ills of cities” or “for human kind” unless “the philosophers rule as kings” or “those now called kings genuinely and adequately philosophize.” Who are the philosophers? They are “lovers of the sight of the truth” (475e). But, Socrates cautions, it is “the nature of acting to attain to less truth than speaking” (473e). The good regime will be easier said than done. Only a regime ruled by kingly philosophers or philosophic kings would govern with the truth in sight. To see the truth means noēsis or insight—the ‘I got it’ response. Without insight, logical analysis would reduce all things to thought-rubble, and logical dialectic would speculate without end. The mind would be trapped either in infinite regress or infinite, but pointless, progress. In the philosophically-governed city, insight will replace the opinion-icons with which rulers rule everywhere else.

    2. Why I Am So Peculiar

    The one who “from youth on strive[s] as intensely as possible for every kind of truth” (485d) will have weaker desires for other things: a weaker eros for money and for the human-all-too-human generally. This disturbs Adeimantus, who worries that philosophers are at best useless to cities, at worst vicious, and usually damned peculiar. “[Y]ou are telling the truth in saying that the most decent of those in philosophy are useless to the many,” Socrates concedes (489b). Sailors ambitious to rule will call “the true pilot” a stargazer and a prater.  The many want what they want, which is unlikely to be some remote truth. The true pilot is more true than pilot; he is not likely to find work as a pilot.

    3. Why Dialogues?

    This is why Plato writes dialogues. A philosopher, fixing his attention on what is, will want to ignore the ever-changing, petty struggles for ‘power,’ ‘riches,’ and other false goods. But Plato’s Socrates, even when asking his friends to lift their eyes to the stars, never forgets the person in front of him. He does not argue in the same way to Cephalus as he does to Polemarchus, to Glaucon as he does to Adeimantus. Socrates is the first political philosopher. The noble lie is noble because it is the true cure for the variety of souls that are untrue to themselves. Pre-Socratic natural philosophy had supposed that it could brush opinions/conventions aside. Socratic political wisdom, or prudence, seen in his conversations, can mollify most of the many, as the philosopher ranges between the lowest persons and topics to the highest thoughts, from opinion to noēsis—both presented through logos. The truth of what is must be filtered through what one may say, and who is saying it. By doing so, the philosopher avoids naivete about the ability of the human mind to jump beyond itself, to make a fast and easy break with sub-philosophic opinion.

    But Socratic prudence enrages the thumotic few—Thrasymachus, for example—who fear any potential rivals (cf. 493b). In this dialogue, Thrasymachus is tamed (and Cephalus banished, and Polemarchus disarmed). In Athens, certain ‘Thrasymachuses’ were not tamed, and they eventually executed the political philosopher. Political philosophy is a shield because it is politic, but it is a red flag because it is political. Political philosophy raises the stakes een as it plays with a stronger hand.

    4. What Should I Strive For?

    Dialectical inquiry concerning opinions concerning justice lead eventually to “the idea of the good.” What, then, is “the good”? Inquiring minds (like Glaucon’s) want to know. No retreating into professions of ignorance on this one, old boy. Instead, Socrates advances an image: The good is like the sun, which causes knowledge and truth, causes the ‘isness’ of what is. In contrast to the sun and its light there is the cave, where the inhabitants worship false icons, loving what they believe to be their own. The man educated, drawn out of the cave, is a man converted—his soul “turned around” (518c), away from ‘his own’ and toward the good. Never diminished by being beheld, the good underlies the only true communism. The good is what is truly everyone’s own, unseen by those insufficiently erotic and thumotic to make the ascent, unseen by those overwhelmingly erotic and thumotic souls who prefer to rule in the cave than to serve in the light of the sun, as Milton’s Satan almost put it. The difficulty in answering Glaucon’s question directly is clear: noetically to see the good requires soul-turning, conversion; Glaucon is not a philosopher, so his question is as impertinent as it is pertinent. The same goes for Plato’s readers. Plato writes dialogues, not essays, not dictionaries or encyclopedias. Browsers need not apply.

    5. Would Philosophers Rule?

    The many don’t want the philosophers to rule them. So said Adeimantus. Nor do the philosophers want to rule the many. So now says Glaucon, Adeimantus’ superior in mind and heart. These twin, stubborn truths make the ‘actual’ establishment of philosophic rule highly unlikely. The only good ruler is he who does not love ruling, Socrates says. Only in the philosophic city can philosophers be justly compelled to rule, for only there do they owe their philosophy to the city. There is now no philosophic city, except in speech; ergo, there will never be a philosophic city, except in speech, unless the philosophers are unjustly compelled to rule, either by a populace somehow made desirous for being ruled by the apparently useless and peculiar, or by the few who suddenly decide to relinquish their dreams of supreme victory and honor. That is, philosophers will rule when their rule—when anyone’s rule—is no longer much needed.

    6. What Is Going ON, Here?

    Education in truth of guardians—that is, a political-philosophic education—is never more obviously unlikely than in the latter half of Book VII. The ascent of the soul from mathematics to dialectic in Callipolis, the beautiful city, leads to the profoundly undogmatic, and therefore unpolitical, thought that the looks of ultimate things cannot be properly insisted upon, although their existence can be insisted upon. The anger is that young souls trained in dialectic act like puppies; they chew on the carpet. The young should not learn to despise the laws too quickly, if ever; they will become lawless without becoming philosophic—which, in political terms, means that they will not become prudent. Prudence is the one virtue of the soul that is fully natural, not produced by habits and exercise (518e). (In terms of the Protagoras, prudence is the true virtue, as it is a form of knowledge but it cannot be taught, is not technical.) Ultimately, these observations make Socrates conclude that the founding of the beautiful city will require the exile of all except philosophers and children ten years of age and younger. Socrates has founded not a city but a school. This leaves city-founding in any ordinary sense far behind, and is another specimen of Socratic irony.

    7. Why Socrates Is Not a Nice Guy

    “Irony I can get from my children. From my deli man, I expect wisdom.” So said the lady in the radio commercial for a New York City deli, whose owner was portrayed Socratically, that is, as ironic and wise. Ironic children are unhousebroken puppies. Ironic wise men are irritating, not-nice. They may display the most tasty delicacies, courtesans and cakes for the soul. But those goods are always just out of reach for most would-be customers. Irony itself is a sort of lie or untruth, perpetrated by one who thinks he knows the truth better than his interlocutor. Surely our lives would be less troublesome if we simply killed the wise? So thought, and did, the Athenians. The founders of the commercial republic hoped to make the world safe for the wise by claiming that the wise are useful, insisting that they be. This is the noble lie of the Enlightenment. Those who doubt it are not nice.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    Oedipus’ Self-Deception

    April 8, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Before the play, the myth: The first Thebans sprang from the teeth of a dragon, offspring of the war-god. Hera, goddess of (often outraged) wifehood, motherhood, generativity, hated the city. She sent the sphinx to torment the Thebans. The monster with the face of a woman, the body of a lion, and the wings of a raptor asked the Thebans riddles, destroying those who couldn’t guess the right answers. Riddles or secrets are one means by which gods punish, or torment, men. Gods know things men don’t know, particularly those things pertaining to the origin of man.

    The famous riddle—What animal walks on four feet in the morning, two feet at noon, three feet at night?—has a curious answer: Man. Man walks on hands and feet in infancy, feet in adulthood, feet and staff in old age. The answer is curious because the sphinx errs about infancy. Infants ‘walk on six feet: two hands, two feet, and two knees. The sphinx conceives of infants as if they were lion cubs—as if they were her own offspring. She leaves out the ‘middle’ form of locomotion of the ‘middling’ creature, the one between gods and beasts.

    Oedipus solves the riddle because he is a man who thinks like a sphinx. He is ‘leonine’ or thumotic, and therefore a true Theban, a true descendent of the god of war. The Thebans themselves cannot answer the question that might be rephrased, ‘What is man?’ They are not only thumotic but autochthonous, sprung from seeds sown in their own territory. They do not abstract from ‘their own.’ Oedipus is a Theban exposed by ‘his own,’ effectually exiled at birth. If man is an animal that always has at least two feet on the ground, Oedipus is a man ‘unfooted’—first hobbled, then cast out and reared in a foreign city. ‘Swollen-foot’ fits nowhere. He is therefore the only Theban who can—because compelled—’abstract’ from the city. He can think of man, not only of Thebans and Corinthians. But he does not understand the origin of man, the earliest ‘age’ of man, the age in which man is most dependent upon his mother, his city, the earth, most rooted or ‘footed.’ To misunderstand genetic nature, to alienate Hera, may lead to a mistaken concentration on maturity, self-sufficiency. The thumotic quest for self-sufficiency yields self-destruction, prefigured by the sphinx, the thumotic, victory-loving suicide who can’t stand to lose.

    King Oedipus is the ‘footing’ or foundation of Thebes, the city he saved from the sphinx. The plague-stricken Thebans beg him to save them once more. The plague stops generativity; crops nd livestock die, women cannot bear children. Thebans blame the war-god, no friend of generativity. Oedipus hears from his brother-in-law, Creon—who says he heard it from the oracle at Delphi—that Thebes is polluted by the presence of the murderer of Creon’s father, King Laius.

    A murdered king: Surely, a political motive? The suspicion arises from a probabilistic calculation; one suspects such a crime because that’s the way things so often go. To find the presumptive political murderer, Oedipus and the Thebans reason, commonsensically, cui bono? The answer will likely solve the secret of the plotters.

    Creon, the initial beneficiary of the crime, and Oedipus, the eventual beneficiary, are the obvious prime suspects. To reassure the people of his innocence, the (suspiciously) foreign king begins his investigation by announcing that he acts in his own interest in trying to find the murderer(s). To further establish his bona fides, Oedipus calls upon any Theban to tell the truth, offering a (limited) guarantee of clemency. Surely such a king does not deceive his people.

    The prophet Teiresias (recommended by Creon) tells Oedipus: You blame my thumos for my stubborn silence in refusing to answer all your questions, but you do not see your own thumos that lives within you. Under threat of death, Teiresias finally admits that Oedipus has lived thumotically, committing parricide and incest. Parricide destroys one source of his own life, the rightful paternal authority; it is an act of supreme self-sufficiency. Incest is mating with the other source of his life; it is the supreme act of loving one’s own.

    In so informing Oedipus, Teiresias speaks not ‘politically’ but oracularly, as a slave of no man but of the god, Apollo, who, like all the gods, transcends any one city. Nor does Teiresias seek to rule other men by invoking the word of the god; he comes at Oedipus’ request, and essays no commands. Oedipus denies Teiresias’ divine enslavement. He suspects a plot, a deception spun by Creon. The man of thumos who rejects the gods and their ‘plotting’ sees human plots everywhere, all of them directed against him and his own, except those plots that he, god-like, ordains. Oedipus denies the gods, generally. He recurs to his source of political authority, his solution of the sphingian riddle, which, he boasts, he solved by his unassisted human intelligence, not by heeding some god’s revelation. Oedipus is ‘nobody’s fool’ when it comes to oracles. Natural intelligence is his ‘footing,’ not the ground of the city, sown divinely. To rely on one’s own intelligence means that one can be self-instructed. But it can also mean self-deception. Oedipus falsely suspects a human plot where there is a divine ‘plot’ or fatality at work. His very self-deception furthers the divine plot.

    Teiresias says: You will soon be footloose, exiled. You do not know your own parents, your own origin. You know the answer to the abstract question, ‘What is man?’ but cannot answer the concrete question, ‘Who am I?’ Teiresias’ riddle is not the sphinx’s riddle; it is a riddle of origins, which are always cloaked from man, a matter of hearsay not sight, prophecy not reasoning. Thumotically, Oedipus replies: I do not care who I am, so long as my discovery of the murderer saves the city. He is a political man to the core, not a man of the gods. He is a man of this city more than he knows. He is the son of its murdered king and he is the city’s unwitting, salvific sacrifice to the gods.

    Oedipus’ atheism (shared by his mother-wife Iocasta) threatens the city’s foundations. “The worship of the gods is perishing,” the Chorus laments. If atheism is true, chance rules the world, because chance cannot be foreknown with certainty, only probabilistically. If atheism is true, the priests who teach the certitudes underlying moral restraints lack real authority, and men are beasts with divine ambitions, properly thumotic. Oedipus calls himself a child of chance, a moon-child whose fortunes start small, end big, like the growth of a strange infant who can stand on four legs, without ever crawling. Fortune, ruled with a combination of rational calculation and thumotic daring, replaces the gods as well as real human nature’s generativity and growth. The very thumos that rebels against the gods in the name of self-sufficiency eliminates the only potential source of certainty, prophetic hearsay, while at the same time demanding certainty from the human, probabilistic calculation that is realistically incapable of delivering it. (Add to that, that Greek prophecies are typically ambiguous or double-edged, and it cannot be said that traditional Greeks were optimists.)

    Iocasta undeceived remains within the circle of the self by destroying herself, like a defeated sphinx. Oedipus undeceived stands self-cursed and self-blinded. He destroys deceptive sight, which he unwisely trusted more than prophetic hearsay. “What can I see to love?” Deprived of victory and honor, he cannot even love ‘his own’—the other love-objects of the thumotic man. he tells his daughters, “a father seeing nothing, knowing nothing, [begot] you from his own source of life.” They will know their origin, as he did not, but they will be ashamed of it. ‘His own’ are now a sign of shame, as he is for them: the worst punishment for the thumotic or honor-loving man.

    Sophocles teaches that the man of unrestrained thumos dreams of self-sufficiency conceived not as liberty but as tyranny, as contempt for the laws given by gods, promulgated by prophets, supplemented by oracles, guarded by priests. Such self-deceptive dreaming destroys the authority of fathers, thus destroying fathers themselves. Tyrants destroy the origin of authority, contradicting themselves in their deluded rationalism. Tyrants are “realists who know nothing of the realities.”

    Filed Under: Manners & Morals

    Fifteen Truths and a Noble Lie

    April 8, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    In the first four books of the Republic, Plato uses the word ‘truth’ on its derivatives in fifteen passages. He uses the word ‘lie’ in thirteen passages, most famously when discussing the “noble lie.” Lies are mentioned more frequently in the first half of the Republic than in the second half; truths are mentioned less frequently in the first than in the second half.

     

    The Fifteen ‘Truths’
    1. (330E). Cephalus is the first man to mention the true. Old age, he says, brings out the fear that myths of punishment of the unjust in Hades might be true. Cephalus is a caricature of the man of the four cardinal Socratic virtues: He treats old age as a substitute for moderation, piety as a substitute for courage, fatherhood as a substitute for wisdom, money as a substitute for justice (if wealthy, one need not cheat or lie, but perhaps one can bribe the gods). Cephalus is a man impossible to respect who must be respected according to his age and position. Self-deceived, ‘living a lie,’ he half-coerces, half-tempts others to lie to and about him. To speak freely, and perhaps truly, the unwealthy Socrates him to go away.

    2. (331c-d). Socrates is the next to mention the true. He asks Cephalus if justice is simply truth-telling and giving back what one takes. His answer to this question is no; it is permissible to withhold both truth and property from a madman. Truth-telling is not necessarily just.

    3. (335a). Cephalus’ son, Polemarchus, is the third man to mention the true. Polemarchus (his name means ‘war-ruler’) claims that justice means paying one’s debts, helping friends, and harming enemies. He has the impulses of Carl Schmitt with the mentality of the accountant. Socrates compels him to admit that one must distinguish real friends and enemies from seeming-friends and seeming-enemies. The good, therefore, is not necessarily ‘one’s own.’ Is the true?

    4. (3357c). Here Socrates speaks with the “wild beast,” Thrasymachus, who decries Socratic indirection and irony. Socrates exhibits that irony by calling Thrasymachus wise. “Shall I say something other than the truth, you surprising man?” Socrates asks, feigning innocence, on his way to trapping the beast into asserting his own definition of justice without extracting one from Socrates. (This he must do, having scorned Socrates’ holding-back.) Justice is the advantage of the stronger, Thrasymachus says. He openly disdains the self-serving pieties and Cephalus and son, as well as Socrates’ polite evasions. He wants to be seen as a realist, a teller of unpleasant truths, a real man who truly speaks of what truly is.

    5. (349a). Thrasymachus sarcastically says, “Your distinction is very true” (sarcasm being the irony of the thumotic man) in response to Socrates’ summary of Thrasymachus’ opinion: injustice is the way of the virtuous and wise, a thing “fair and mighty.” Socrates questions whether Thrasymachus really is” speaking the truth in so asserting, or only joking. For it is virtuous and wise to be knowledgeable, not ignorant, and the knowledgeable man will always have a certain advantage over the ignoramus, whether or not the ignoramus is politically stronger. Thrasymachus sweats and blushes. He is less interested in learning than in having a reputation for learning. In injuring Thrasymachus’ reputation, Socrates silences him, inflicts a mortal wound—if only in speech.

    6. (365a-b). The next man to mention the true is Glaucon, “always most courageous in everything,” who wants to know if Socrates wants “truly to persuade us” of the superior goodness of justice. Superior goods are those desirable instrumentally and in themselves. Why not merely seem to be just? Is not injustice what is naturally good? If one had the ring of the tyrant Gyges, with its power of making the wearer invisible, why not satisfy all one’s erotic and thumotic longings with no regard to dull inhibition? An entirely ‘invisible man’ would be a god, known only through his voice and works. Why should a god be just? Glaucon radicalizes, gets to the root, of Thrasymachus’ challenge. Glaucon is a potential tyrant and perhaps a potential philosopher. Which way he will go may depend upon Socrates’ ability truly to persuade him. Of course, truly to persuade someone may or may not be to persuade him of the truth.

    7. (362a). Further, Glaucon says, let there be two such rings, and two such men—one just, the other unjust. Make the just man be reputed to be unjust, and make the unjust man seem just. Who is happier? Surely the unjust man, who despises decent conventions and gets what he really wants, “pursues a thing dependent on truth and does not live in the light of opinion.” Surely the unjust man finds happiness, while the pilloried man of justice finds only misery. (Or could there be some ring of Gyges that makes the just man invisible to his enemies? Some true lie to tell them, and preserve himself?)

    8. (365c). The next man to mention the true is brother Adeimantus, seconding Glaucon’s opinion in his own characteristically more measured way. Isn’t the just life simply too much trouble? Lighten up; take it easy; gimme a break. Seeming is stronger than the truth, according to the respected poet, Simonides; so draw a shadow painting of virtue around your clever, manipulative soul, and lay hold of the main chance. After all, the very gods can be corrupted with a show of humility and a few token offerings. If Glaucon loves victory, Adeimantus loves honor; if Glaucon is a lion, Adeimantus is a fox.

    9. (372e). This dual assault on justice causes Socrates to raise the stakes. Let us try to find justice not in the individual soul but in a city to be founded in speech, by us. This proposal (not incidentally appealing both to Glaucon’s libido dominandi and to Adeimantus’ love of honor), takes the dialogue beyond the souls of petty chiselers and even big tyrants, and to the highest (or is it the lowest?) level: the soul of the founder of the city. Is the founder a divine legislator or a supreme tyrant? In so proceeding, Socrates finds Adeimantus easily satisfied with a modest, austere city, a sort of Minnesota-of-the-mind. Glaucon is more ambitious and more erotic. What, no relishes? No “courtesans and cakes”? But “the true city,” Socrates protests, is the healthy, moderate one. He does not protest too much, quickly turning to “the feverish city” of Glaucon’s imagination. Neither tyrant nor philosopher can rest content in the true city, the small town that satisfies the basic animal necessities and nothing more.

    10. (376e). More desires, more wealth: The City now needs guardians, warriors, men not of appetitive eros but of spirit, men who will defend the city without sharing its desires, men who love their own and hate outsiders. This (Socrates playfully suggests) is the philosophic way: to be friendly to the known—a lover of wisdom, a philo-sopher—and unfriendly to the unknown. (It is more likely that the philosopher will be unfriendly not to the unknown but to the incorrigibly unwise, but Glaucon, unwise if not incorrigibly so, doesn’t notice that.)

    Turning to Adeimantus, the more patient brother, Socrates tells him that the discussion of the education of these potentially dangerous guardians will take a long time. Part of “music” education is education in speech. Speeches “have a double form, the one true, the other false”; saying it doesn’t make it so. This double form of speech recalls the (possibly) “true myths” Cephalus feared. Will the guardians believe that punishment in Hades awaits bad men?

    11. (377a). The tales we tell children are double. As a whole they are false, but with “true things in them.” Such tales must precede action, gymnastic, in the smallest children, inasmuch as “the beginning is the most important part of every work,” especially work with the tender and “plastic” young, on whom impressions are easily ‘imprinted.’ The myth-makers or poets must be compelled to tell stories that will incline the young soul to justice. (Suddenly, when speaking of children who are future guardians, Socrates’ skeptical interlocutor is no longer so ignorant of what justice is, or why injustice might be undesirable.)

    12. (382a-b). The most shocking truths poets now tell concern the gods. Gods as liars, thieves, adulterers, gods as changelings and deceivers: You can’t trust such gods; they only weaken the guardians’ needed courage. “Don’t you know,” Adeimantus, “that all gods and human beings hate the true lie, if that expression can be used?” The true lie is the lie of the soul, a falsehood about “what is most sovereign” to oneself. The true lie is ignorance. A spoken lie is a sort of artifact or imitation of a falsity in the soul; inasmuch as no one, god or human, wants anything less than what is good for his own innermost being, the true lie is the true enemy of everyone.

    13. (382d). As for spoken lies, they may be useful, “so as not to deserve hatred.” Real enemies and false friends deserve no better. As for poetic tales, they are lies when poets know what they often cannot know—”the truth about ancient things,” such as human origins—but they can be useful lies when they imitate the truth insofar as it is known. The gods need no lies, as they fear no human enemies and are not ignorant of an ancient things. Sober, respectable Adeimantus readily agrees that poetic tales should depict sober, respectable, trustworthy gods. At the same time, Socrates wants to appeal to the thumoeidetic Glaucon: the gods Socrates presents to the young, aristocratic brothers are ‘idealized’; that is, they partake of the stability and transparency of the eidos, a word first spoken in the dialogue by Glaucon, whose name means ‘gleaming.’ These gods do not hide behind clouds; bright as the stars, like good children, they are seen, not heard.

    14. (389b-c). The guardians’ education for courage eschews poetic tales of Hades, frightening names, divine grief, divine laughter. The guardians’ education for moderation inculcates obedience, requires restraint with respect to diet, sex, and money. Central to this educational list is truth, which “must be taken seriously, too.” Private men must not handle a lie. A lie may be useful to human beings “as a form of remedy”; only “doctors” can be trusted to lie rightly. In politics, the doctors are the rulers; they may lie “for the benefit of the city.” The ruled must not lie about political things to the rulers, any more than a sick man should lie to his doctor about symptoms. Respectable Adeimantus concurs in this unequal distribution of latitude.

    Inasmuch as the Platonic dialogues consist in large measure of conversations between a philosopher and a rogues’ gallery of quacks, creeps, and ignoramuses, not all of them private men, it would be silly to suppose that Socrates does not see the danger of his argument. The problem the argument raises is not so much the danger of spoken lies as the danger of ignorance—of not knowing what is beneficial to the city and the soul, of the true nature and therefore the true good of the city and the soul.

    15. (413a-b). No one wants to lose the truly best by force or fraud. This goes for opinions as well as for objects and persons. “[T]he departure of the false opinion from the man who learns otherwise is willing, that of every true opinion is unwilling.” The guardians must be tested, to see if they guard, hold fast to, the true opinions with which they have been inculcated. Those who pass this testing shall rule the city.

     

    The Noble Lie

    An example of a true opinion is the noble lie. It’s a Phoenician thing: Theban, to be specific—the myth of autochthony, which will induce guardians to defend their city as, literally, native ground. To autochthony Socrates adds the myth of the metals, whereby the guardians are reconciled to a tripartite political structure whereby auxiliaries will serve the rulers, with whom they are allied in ruling farmers, artisans, and merchants. Autochthony makes the city seem more natural, more literally ‘grounded,’ than it is; the myth of the metals makes nature seem more politically stratified than it is. In this, Socrates shows how to make thumoeidetic Oedipus of Thebes useful instead of tragic. The noble lie is a lie because it exaggerates, ennobles, the truth. But it is a true lie, so to speak, in that it ensures that he who tends most to ignore the body—the heroic man, lover of victory and honor, the ‘ideologist’ who contradictorily loves and abstracts from his own but does not know himself—will moderate his ambitions without denaturing his spirit or intellect.

    Self-knowledge is the theme of Book IV, where the word-cluster centered on truth never appears. This may be because the neat division of the soul into three harmonious parts will prove to be in need of correction and supplementation, in the Republic and elsewhere in the dialogues of Plato.

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 148
    • 149
    • 150
    • 151
    • 152
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »