Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem
  • Hitler’s Intentions
  • The Derangement of Love in the Western World

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Political Authority: Resistance and Obedience, Socrates and Hobbes

    April 27, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    The Apology and the Crito present the reader with a contradiction and a paradox. The contradiction is that Socrates advocates resistance to political authority in one dialogue, obedience in the other. The paradox is that Socrates advocates resistance in public, before the Athenian jury, whereas he advocates obedience in the privacy of his jail cell in a one-on-one conversation with an old friend.

    The contradiction is easy to resolve. Socrates advocates resistance to public authority for ones like himself, for philosophers. If the soldiers at Gettysburg died so that the nation might live, Socrates at Athens died so that philosophy may live. He provokes the Athenians to kill him so that the philosopher as a human type will be admired and defended as a man of courage and not merely as an ‘intellectual’ by spirited and influential men who may have their own reasons for resisting the sway of public opinion. such men may come to identify with philosophers, offer them protection.

    Crito is just such a man—wealthy, politically connected, a born ‘fixer.’ What he is not is a philosopher. (When the Hollywood movie producer Darryl F. Zanuck heard that Ronald Reagan wanted to run for governor of California, he protested, “No, no! Not Ronald Reagan as governor! Ronald Reagan as the governor’s best friend!” Crito is, or at least wants to be, the philosopher’s best friend. A man lacking philosophic wisdom may still admire the philosopher’s wit, justice, and courage.) Socrates does not want wealthy citizens like Crito to get into the habit of evading the law. On the contrary, Socrates’ argument in the Apology depends upon his own refusal to evade the law or the punishment attached to it. If Socrates were to consent to Crito’s plan, his words before the Athenians would ring hollow: For once, the ironic smile would play on the lips of the Athenians and not on the lips of Socrates. the Athenians would be victorious over philosophy if they were cheated out of killing the philosopher.

    In solving the apparent contradiction between the dialogues one also removes the paradox. Socrates defies public authority by refusing to stop philosophizing; he provokes the death sentence that will make him, as the type of the philosopher, immortal by insolently asking for a reward for his philosophizing. (He then offers to ‘negotiate down’ to the payment of a trivial fine.) “The unexamined life is not worth living” is the final insult to the Athenians: Your lives are not worth living without me, the one who examines you, the one who prevents you from drifting off into the dreamy sleep of the quotidian. “I would rather die having spoken in my manner, than speak in your manner and live.” Dying life—philosophizing is practice of how to die—is preferable to living death—thoughtless, impassioned, mistaken.

    The philosophic quest, animated by the eros for the good, renders Socrates unshakable. But what might render a decent non-philosopher like Crito unshakable, even as he fulfills his role as a friend and ally of philosophers? No public opinion, which will tolerate, then condemn, then regrets its condemnation of Socrates. Crito should rather be attached to the laws, as well as to a philosopher who abides by the laws. True, the laws themselves depend upon public opinion and its mood swings, but if enough citizens can be persuaded to revere them, public opinion itself will become less fickle. If the rich and well-connected become ‘conservative’ not only inasmuch as they seek to conserve their wealth but seek to conserve the laws, their conservatism will provide ballast for a ship too much buffeted by demagogic winds, by the tyranny of the majority as incited by malicious rhetoricians. If he rich instead decide, as Crito initially has decided, to regard the man wronged by the city as free to retaliate, then the rich will undermine the city, seek to rule it on their own terms. Their contempt for the law will infect the people, and violent factional strife—leaving peaceful philosophers maximally exposed to suspicion on both sides—will roil the city forever. This is the criticism Publius makes of ancient democracies. And so Socrates pretends that the laws are his parents—surely, as Peter Ahrensdorf notes, the most extreme form of ‘conventionalism,’ so extreme as to be deliberately parodistic of conventionalism. [1]  Philosophically-minded reads will see the joke. Crito will not, and that is all to the good, both for him and for the Athenians. In this, Socrates earns his title as not only a wise man but a just one.

    Thomas Hobbes presents a different, sterner, and seemingly more doctrinaire view. The difference may be accounted for in terms of philosophy—his different account of nature—and in terms of politics—specifically, the advent of Christianity and its collision with secular rulership.

    Far from being orderly, nature as a whole exhibits dissociation (Leviathan I. 13). Nature is atomistic. By nature, human beings war with one another, like colliding atoms. But the atoms themselves do have a certain discernible order, a structure of passions with the fear of violent death as its capstone, but also the desire for the things hat make life commodious and the hope to attain those things. Therefore, each atom obeys nineteen natural laws: among these Hobbes lists the inclination to seek peace and follow it; to defends its own existence by all available means; to seek peace by establishing “justice,” i.e., contractual agreements to recognize the “rights” of (more accurately, desires for) life, liberty, and the property that makes life and liberty sustainable.

    The establishment of an effective contract for peace, with security for each one, requires that some power be instituted with sufficient capacity to enforce that security—else “every man will, and lawfully rely on his own strength and art” (Leviathan II. 17). Therefore, no right to revolution exists. For the sake of civic peace, the sovereign must be the soul judge of the actions and desires of the subjects. To challenge the power of the sovereign is to return to the dissociational nature of all objects above the ‘atomic’ level, and so to threaten the existence of the ‘atoms,’ the members of the civil society themselves. “Sovereign power is not so hurtful as the want of it” (II. 18). Civil obedience is absolute: “Nothing that the sovereign representative can do to a subject, on any pretence soever, can properly be called injustice, or injury” (II. 21); only if the sovereign fails to protect his subject, plunging the subject back into the natural war of all against all, will the subject’s obligation to his sovereign dissolve.

    Hobbes lists fifteen “infirmities” of commonwealths leading to what we now call a ‘failed state.’ Central to the list is the imitation of foreign nations (II. 29), perhaps because a false prophet is one who teaches “any other religion than that which is already established” (III. 32); Jesus apparently did not do so, as Hobbes observes that He expounded the Mosaic Law (III. 42). However, Pauline Christianity, based upon Jesus’ command to take the Gospel to all nations, clearly does violate Hobbes’s rule. Evangelizing Christianity, which at bottom recognizes no nations, denying the distinction between Greek and Jew, has introduced dangerous novelties wherever it has gone. This can be seen more concretely in Behemoth, Hobbes’s dialogue on the English civil wars, “the many shiftings of the supreme authority” which occurred between 1640 and 1659. [2]

    In Hobbes’s telling, seditious factions caused these bloody wars. Presbyterian ministers, Catholics, and the various ‘dissenting’ sects (central to the list being the Fifth-Monarchy men, who envisioned the imminent return of the Christ to earth); liberally-educated parliamentarians infatuated with classical republicanism; businessmen enamored of a foreign nation, commerce-minded Netherlands; the poor, avid of money; and the people, “ignorant of their duty” to obey the sovereign: all these groups, some averse to one another, fired the ambition to rebel against the monarchy and the established Church of England (Behemoth, 4). Because “the power of the mighty hath no foundation but in the opinion and belief of the people,” heterodoxy is civic poison (16). “The Universities have been to this nation as the wooden horse was to the Trojans” (40), serving as “the core of the rebellion” (58). Is it not an outrage that a man “will trouble himself and fall out with his neighbors for the saving of my soul, or the soul of any other than himself?” (63)  This spiritual effort he could very well keep to himself, without disturbing the public peace. The privatization of religion divides and conquers all religion, except for the civil religion of the State, the doctrines of which are identical to the will of the sovereign. (In this matter as in others, Hobbes wastes little sympathy. To kill 1,000 Presbyterian ministers would be a “great massacre,” but the “killing of 100,000” in a civil war ignited by ministers “is the greater” [95].) “[C]onverse with these divinity-disputers as long as you will, you will hardly find one in a hundred discreet enough to be employed in any great affair, either of war or peace” (144). Better to keep them as private men.

    Where does this leave the philosopher? Philosophy and divinity both yield “the advancement of the professors,” which Hobbes associates with the priestly caste throughout history. True philosophy “can never appear propitious to ambition, or to an exemption from the obedience due to the sovereign power” (96). In this, Hobbes adopts the teaching of the Crito with Socrates’ self-defense or apologia subtracted. But what of the defense of philosophy, given the fact that Hobbes is so evidently a philosopher?

    For this one must turn to A Dialogue Between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England. Given the character of law as command and of philosophy as reasoning, law and philosophy might seem to be at odds, the philosopher’s supposedly unquestioning obedience to the laws of the sovereign open to question. But Hobbesian reason differs in nature from that of the common lawyers, even as it differs in character from the reason of Aristotelian philosophers, with their emphasis on prudence, an inclination the lawyers attempt to emulate. Hobbesian reason rests on ratio—that is, on proportion, on geometric certitude. Ancient philosophers suffered from “a want of method”: “there is not one of them that begins his ratiocination from the definitions, or explications, of the names they are to use; which is a method that hath been used in geometry: whose conclusions have thereby been made indisputable” (Leviathan I. 5). To treat all reason as if it were mathematics brings Cartesianism to Hobbes’s famous discovery of Euclid.

    Hobbesian reason can partake of the authority of law, can in fact revise existing laws, because it alone cannot be questioned—unlike the flickering light of prudence, now seen to be unphilosophic, a thing of mere experience and not of true reasoning at all. It might be added that the certainty afforded by ‘mathematized’ reasoning applied to all of human life, the assurance of those confident of having received divine revelation finds a rival. Hobbes carefully suggests, through the person of the philosopher in the Dialogue, that the sovereign king is actually subservient to the public safety, and thus open to criticism by the true reason based on the true axiom of nature, self-preservation.

    The Hobbesian political philosopher differs from the Socratic not so much in his apparent teaching of conformity to the law, but in instantiating a new kind of  philosopher-king, a man who makes rigorous deductions from right axioms. The philosopher-king is no ironic construct as seen in Plato’s Republic, who ends by lording it over a population of children, but a man who holds the scientifically-irrefutable keys to the real political kingdom, whose reasonings are commands because they are accurate deductions from right axioms.

    The strength of the Socratic approach is its flexibility, the way in which it can adopt philosophy to concrete circumstances, and so to enable philosophy to survive in a world that is never philosophic. The Socratic approach as dramatized by Plato exhibits the prudence so often not found among the ranks of the highly intelligent.

    The weakness of the Socratic approach, at least if kept within the fairly restricted horizon of Apology-Crito, is its apparent inability to say what might be done to remedy the defects of a very bad regime. In that case, mere law-abidingness is not enough. For such considerations, one must turn to the Statesman, or perhaps to the regime analysis in Book IX of the Republic.

    The strength of the Hobbesian approach is that it cuts the chatter. The seditious chatter of the Christian universities and parliaments of his time and place resembled in its virulence the seditious chatter of mosques and madrassas in our own century; the rule of such absolute monarchs as the Atatürk of Turkey, Shah of Iran, the Nasserites of Egypt, Hussein of Iraq, all their regimes replaced, all might well be preferred to the fanatics who have founded new regimes in those countries. And regarding philosophy, Hobbes distinguishes dialogue from chatter, rather as Socrates distinguishes philosophy from sophistry and rhetoric. Hobbes invites ‘intellectuals’ to a repast of humility, without requiring them to humble themselves to God.

    The weakness of Hobbes’s approach is in its confidence in geometric reasoning, particularly as it might be applied to politics. Push prudential reasoning aside as irrational is imprudent, and might well undermine the very discretion Hobbes himself commends. Although Hobbes assures us that no monarch is “so inhuman” as to command a son to murder his own father (51), both prudential reasoning and experience strongly suggest otherwise. There is no real-world evidence that geometrizing despotism would remain benevolent, as distinguished from a more liberal, though far from conflict-free republican regime. There Locke was right to break with Hobbes. Whether le sage Locke would have broken with him under the circumstances Hobbes faced in England, circumstances prevailing in many parts of the world today, is a matter to be gauged by prudence, not geometry.

     

    Notes

    1. Peter J. Ahrensdorf: The Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato’s Phaedo. Albany: State University of New York Pres, 1995, 171.
    2. Thomas Hobbes: Behemoth. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    The French and American Revolutions Compared

    April 25, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Lecture delivered at Hillsdale College, Hillsdale, Michigan
    February 3, 2000

     

    Why bother to compare the American and French revolutions? What do events that occurred so long ago have to do with us, now or in the future? Even granting that the American Revolution still matter, as we live under most of the provisions of the 1787 Constitution, framed in its aftermath, why should we still care about the French? Why compare their old debacle with the longstanding success of American republicanism?

    Because the French and not the American Revolution is often regarded as the modern revolution, the precursor of the Leninist and Maoist revolutions, themselves long believed to be harbingers of the future world order. Whereas the American Revolution was merely a political revolution (the claim goes), the French Revolution was also a social revolution—so much more profound.

    The collapse of Soviet communism dampened this enthusiasm. But even after the Soviet empire collapsed, the new Russian regime has rejected the commercial republicanism or liberal democracy of America and western Europe. Not only Russia, but a number of the regimes founded in the following decades can be classified as what one scholar has called illiberal democracy—regimes in which real democratic elections are held but the economic and civil liberties that we associate with republicanism scarcely exist. Russian Acting President Vladimir Putin has said, “all possible support for new Russia’s democratic institutions is the only guarantee” for “set[ting] up an insurmountable barrier. to the dark past.” But he added, “Russia will not soon become, if ever, a second copy of, say, the United States or England, where liberal values have deep historical traditions…. Among us, the state, its institutions and structures, have always played an exclusively guiding role in the life of the country and the people. A strong state for Russians is not an anomaly, not something that must be fought for or against, but on the contrary is the source and guarantor of order, the initiator an driving force of all change.” ‘Illiberal democracy’ resembles the French revolutionary regimes far more closely than the American regime.

    Finally, we compare the French and American revolutions because we want to know not only that new republics differ so sharply from ourselves, but why they do so. Considering the American and French revolutions together—events thoroughly studied by generations of scholars—can serve as an exercise in how to ‘do’ comparative politics. Comparing and contrasting the social, political, and economic institutions of one country with those of another, comparing and contrasting the kinds of statesmen who rule those countries and the kinds of citizens (and subjects” who inhabit them, can help us to isolate ‘probable causes’ of political life—why things turn out for the better or the worse–and so guide us as citizens and as scholars in trying to understand the world.

    To think about these two revolutions, the first thing we need to know is: What, exactly, is a revolution? ‘Revolution’ is a metaphorical word. To understand it, one must know what it is that has revolved. Aristotle explains that it is the regime of a country that changes in a revolution. A regime or politeia is the organization of the most authoritative offices of the country, the ones that shape its distinctive way of life, serving the purposes set by those who rule it. The system of authoritative institutions is founded and embodied by the politeuma or ruling body—those individuals who wield authority in the country. Aristotle classifies regimes into six types based on quantitative criteria (rule of the one, the few, or the many) and qualitative criteria (the good and the bad). Within each of these types there can be many sub-types, based on what we moderns would call socioeconomic factors: for example, a democracy consisting mostly of farmers and warriors will differ significantly from one consisting mostly of artisans and traders. A revolution, then, is a change of political form, a change of kind and not merely of degree: from oligarchy to democracy, democracy to tyranny, and so on.

    To Aristotle a revolution did not involve seizing something called ‘the state.’ There was little in the way of any permanent institutional structure to seize. Typically, one faction would overthrow another, establishing its own institutions and replacing the previous rulers. The ancient Greeks did not have a term like our ‘state.’

    Various modern writers define ‘state’ variously. I define the modern state as a set of bureaucratic institutions, separated from the society it rules, a society occupying a clearly defined territory. A modern bureaucracy is a rule-bound, impersonal organization, as distinguished from the older governing organizations in which the allegiances were personal, based on patronage. A state also contrasts with a private corporation. General Motors has a centralized locus of authority and is assuredly bureaucratic, but it rules no territory, and it can only tell you what to do as long as you’re on the clock.

    As objects separated from society, states are instruments desired by the ambitious. States are useful to states-men because states enable them to mobilize and concentrate the human and material resources of a given territory, for whatever purposes statesmen may conceive.

    Beginning roughly in the year 1500, state-building in modernity has had several consequences that we now see all around us: extensive, uniform administration of large territories by central bureaucracies that have been expanded and regularized; a split between military and police functions; sophisticated systems of taxation and of finance; the disappearance of mercenaries, accompanied by civilian control of the military; the development of something called ‘nationalism,’ sometime by states in order better to rule social groups, sometimes in reaction against states by those social groups. The French Revolution serves as an excellent example of state-building. In 1789, the French monarchy controlled a fairly large state, by the standards of the day: 50,000 men staffed Louis XVI’s bureaucracy. By 1796, French bureaucrats numbered nearly 250,000—most of them appointed during the period of the Terror, in 1792-93. This apparatus has endured throughout the many changes of regime subsequent to 1796.

    The state complicates but does not erase class classical regime theory. A polity may still be tyrannical or monarchic, oligarchic or aristocratic, ‘mixed’ or democratic. But the state may persist through such regime changes, making for a remarkable sight: The political regime may undergo revolution but the state itself may as a consequence change or stay the same in size and strength.

    When speaking of state organization, one needs terms in addition to those descriptive of ‘regimes.’ With states the key terms are not ‘the one, the few, and the many’ but: 1) degree of centralization; 2) degree of bureaucratization; 3) size of territory ruled. The major political feature of modernity, ‘stateness,’ complicates revolution considerably. Revolutionaries now seize control of ‘the state.’ They do so ostensibly to serve certain social constituencies according to the purposes and the standard of moral judgment revolutionaries actually seek to enforce. Once in control of the state, revolutionaries become part of a different ‘class,’ so to speak, namely, the state’s men and the state’s women. They seize the state but the state in a way seizes them. Their interests may now differ from the interests of the very social classes from which they arose. When Lord Acton warns that power tends to corrupt, he may be considering a symptom of just this phenomenon.

    While the French Revolution continued the monarchic state-building project under several regimes, ending with that of Napoleon, the American Revolution ended such a project. To be sure, our revolution resulted in a national government, a government strengthened between 1787 and 1791 by the framing and ratification of the U. S. Constitution, and for several years thereafter by the able and prestigious administration of George Washington. But this government was hardly a state apparatus by European standards. Such an apparatus was not fully consolidated in this country until the New Deal, and to this day it is not as extensive as its European counterparts.

    What is more, whereas both American and French revolutions were violent, and resulted in the confiscation of the property of the political enemies by the revolutionaries, the French Revolution was really several revolutions in a row—from the liberal regime of 1789-91, to the terror-driven regime of Robespierre, to the liberal but somewhat authoritarian regime of the Directorate a couple of years later, and finally to the orderly tyranny of Napoleon in the early years of the nineteenth century. Each of the first three of these regimes disposed of its predecessor violently, causing the Spaniard Goya to paint his sickening image of the revolutionary monster which devours its children.

    Why do we see this nexus of violent regime instability and state-building in France, contrasting with the freer, more stable outcome in America? (In this, of course one must acknowledge the catastrophe of the U. S. Civil War; nonetheless, over the two centuries following their revolutions, Americans had a less troubled political life, with no thoroughgoing regime changes.)

    American conservatives have long had an intelligent answer to this question, written in 1800 by the Prussian Friedrich Gentz, who by then was serving as an advisor to Prince Metternich of Austria. John Quincy Adams translated Gentz’s book, The French and American Revolutions Compared, as a sort of very high-level political campaign pamphlet. His father’s opponent in the 1800 presidential election, Thomas Jefferson, had enthused over the French Revolution several years longer than had been wise, and Gentz’s book must have looked like a pretty good snowball to aim at the liberty cap of the Sage of Monticello.

    Gentz argues as follows: First, the American revolutionaries were colonists; that matters because the rights of sovereignty of an imperial power are so often dubious. States found colonies for the benefit of the state, not for the benefit of the colonists. By contrast, the French revolutionaries overthrew a king on his native soil; major reforms could have been legally undertaken, but not without the king’s consent, in accordance with the constitution. Instead, one group—albeit by far the largest one, the Third Estate, the commoners—declared itself to be representative of the whole nation. A part that claims to be the whole is really a faction, a usurper. Therefore, Gentz concludes, the difference between the American and French revolutions was the difference between right and wrong, legitimate and illegitimate.

    Second, the American Revolution was defensive, a matter of stern necessity. The revolutionaries demanded no new rights, exercising a “glorious moderation,” sticking to “a fixed and definite purpose,” namely, independence under the rule of law. Because it was factitious, the French revolution was offensive, animated by demands for new rights hitherto imagined only by philosophes and publicists. It was not a moderate but an “insatiate revolution,” always pushing ahead to demand more, always destroying everything in its path in a march toward “the unbounded space of a fantastic arbitrary will.”

    Third, the American revolutionaries maintained governmental continuity. The colonial legislatures remained, while the monarch and his colonial governors were replaced by governors elected by the people or their representatives. The American revolutionaries thus avoided “the deadly passion for making political experiments with abstract theories and untried systems.” In France, each faction had its own conception of what the revolution should be. The revolutionaries there appealed to abstract natural rights rather than to the strict limits of constitutional law. Such grand appeals to big ideas, fueling and fueled by factionalism, resulted in civil war. Further fueled by the fear of reprisal for their crimes, the revolutionaries’ passions turned by cruel, resulting in the Terror of Robespierre and a series of offensive wars against much of Europe—wars that, in the years after the publication of Gentz’s book, would see Napoleon conquer, then lose, the continent.

    Looking back from the perspective gained by two hundred years, Gentz’s analysis holds up very well in many respects. Especially telling is his observation on the moderation of the American Founders, their respect for law even as they revolutionized.

    Nonetheless, Gentz evades or minimizes one key point. In replacing a king with elected governors, the Americans asserted popular sovereignty. In this the American revolutionaries were one with the French. Both upheld popular sovereignty limited by natural and civil rights, “the rights of man and the citizen,” as the French styled them. The problem in France was rather a matter of emphasis. The French declaration says that “ignorance, forgetfulness or contempt of the rights of man are the sole causes of public misfortunes and of the corruption of governments.” This is as silly and doctrinaire a statement as might be imagined, leaving no role in politics for prudence or ‘common sense,’ the ability to establish and maintain institutions that secure natural and civil rights. In this, the Americans and the French parted company. Popular sovereignty framed by natural and civil rights is no political impossibility, as the Americans proved. But you couldn’t prove that by the French of the 1790s, or for many decades to come.

    This corrected version of Gentz’s analysis is as good as far as it goes. But why did the two sets of revolutionaries diverge at this point? What inclined the Americans toward a politics of prudence, the French away from it? Here we need to look not so much at ideas—although I’ll do that, too—but at structures—social, political, and economic institutions.

    To look at those structures, you need to know something about the development of the French state. As Tocqueville observed in The Old Regime and the Revolution, French state-building began centuries before the revolution, under the monarchy. State-building occurred under conditions of tension between the landed, titled aristocrats and the French kings. The aristocrats needed the kings’ troops to help control the peasants, who periodically rebelled against aristocratic exactions. But the kings also competed with the aristocrats for the revenues to be extracted from the peasants.

    In contrast, there were no native-born American aristocratic or monarchic lines among the English settlers. Class distinctions, yes, but no estates, no social groups ‘born to rule.’ Also, America had no peasants, although of course there were slaves. As for warfare, which so often built up the state in Europe, much of it was conducted by colonists imbued with the English tradition of the militia—citizen-soldiers, not professionals or conscripts.

    Let me separate these two points: warfare and socioeconomic antagonism. With respect first to war, the German historian Otto von Hintze wrote, “Absolutism and militarism go together on the [European] continent just as self-government and militia do in England.” State-sponsored standing armies were used by monarchs in order to extract revenues from subjects and to acquire new territories, new subjects, new revenues, from foreign rivals. Monarchs initially had no way to govern conquered territories directly, but the aristocratic allies they employed for this purpose had aristocratic self-interest too prominently in mind for monarchic tastes. Gradually, monarchs began to solve this problem by putting their own hired officials into the provinces—by establishing a centrally-controlled proto-bureaucracy—and by separating police from armies, thus freeing the latter for more wars and regularizing the collection of taxes and the enforcement of tax collection. This formula eventually succeeded, reaching its apogee in France under Louis XIV, more than a century before the revolution. Civil and foreign war helped monarchs to build the absolutist, monarchic state. No wonder the American revolutionaries were suspicious of the civilian agents sent by George III “to eat out our substance,” as the Declaration of Independence puts it, and of standing armies as well.

    What is more (and often overlooked), the peasants who were both the foundation of the economy and the ones who were being squeezed, enjoyed some political self-government, via the village assemblies. Peasants could, as we now say, ‘network’ among themselves. Given their subordination to the various armed classes above them, such networking usually led only to violent but ineffective rebellions. But given a crisis among their rulers, they had the basis for an organized revolt.

    Under the process of state-building, French monarchs extracted revenues for warfare and political control by offering royal privileges in exchange for those revenues—guild privileges, sale of offices, municipal privileges, and the like. Once granted, a privilege cannot be granted again; revenue from the sale of an office is what policy wonks of today call a ‘one-shot revenue enhancer.’ Therefore, it’s not just a play on words to say that there is a certain static quality to statist economics. Entrepreneurial dynamism need not apply. The only entrepreneurialism is seen in the state-builder himself, who ‘grows’ the state in order to ‘grow’ his income. In addition, in times of economic distress, discontent falls not on ‘the economy’ but on the state itself. Statism thus tends to turn on itself, undercutting its own authority and its own revenues even as it attempts to gather authority and revenue to itself.

    Absolutism contradicted itself. It encouraged men to think of France as one thing. At the same time, it needed to use the carrot of privilege and the stick of military coercion in a policy of divide and rule, of disunity. When the tensions so caused were strained by the economic crises of the late 1780s, the regime left itself vulnerable to challenges from within and ‘from below.’ The Revolution began as an aristocratic attempt to capture the state—a modern version of the factional struggles that tore ancient Rome. But the Third Estate, especially its middle-class segment, soon co-opted the revolution, allying itself with the urban poor and the simmering peasantry.

    So that’s why the French Revolution started. But why did this large set of social groups embark on a career of extremism, unlike the Americans?  The answer has several levels: political thought, political experience, foreign policy, economic class, and religion are the most significant.

    On the level of political thought, the French never solved the problem of faction. In the tenth Federalist, James Madison shows how faction might be used to stabilize, not ruin, a republican regime by the means of such institutions as representation, division of power, and federalism. The French weren’t listening. Almost to a man, they insisted on cultivating one national will expressed in a unicameral legislature. In a way, they needed to reinforce unity more than the Americans did, because French social divisions were estates, not classes—sharper divisions, legally enforced, tied up with political authority. But the French attempt to replace royal patriarchy with republican fraternity simply could not work in such a large territory, among such a large and diverse population. The French national assembly was a novelty, with no ties to, and therefore no support from or authority over, local governments. In this it resembled the first American constitution, the Articles of Confederation. A federal structure like that seen in the American Constitution wasn’t considered, and would have been difficult to design and to establish; that structure is what makes Madison’s extended republic possible. ‘Fraternity’ was the inadequate ideological substitute for the resolutely non-ideological pursuit of happiness.

    By contrast, the Americans got rid of the vestiges of anti-republican politics by breaking free of the king—who kept his head and his throne—and exiling his Tory allies to Canada. Class conflict, rather than estates-conflict, more easily lends itself to Madisionianism. Class conflict can lead to balanced sharing of power; estates-conflict more likely produces factions with claims to rule that are more rigidly exclusionary.

    On the level of political experience, both the French and the American revolutionaries featured young lawyers and government officials rather prominently. But the French revolutionaries had experience only in the politics of a statist monarchy. The Americans had extensive experience in the republican politics of routine colonial life. As a result, when the French became self-governing, many of them simply did not know what to do. They had loved ‘Enlightenment’ from afar, worshipped ‘Reason’ as a goddess, but had no practice at the self-government they preached. As the Italian historian Guglielmo Ferrero argues, such inexperience led to fearfulness; fearfulness led to the commission of political crimes; crimes led to guilt and fear of retaliation; these led to the Terror. In a psychological pattern that became familiar in this past century, fear among the rulers resulted in state terrorism against the population. French politics remained prey to regime-threatening factionalism, for the next 180 years. In the United States, the quasi-aristocratic Southern planter class very nearly sundered the state, for precisely the same reason; they posed a regime threat to commercial republicanism in North America.

    On the level of foreign policy, a further, equally futile attempt to forge national unity was warfare, a standard ploy of monarchs commended to ‘the prince’ by Machiavelli. The French republicans waged offensive war against a continent full of monarchs, even as French kings had done. Here again, fear ruled: The revolutionaries invented something very much like what we call ‘total war’—complete with mass conscription, maximum feasible mobilization of all national resources, and propaganda—all out of the fear that France might become another Poland, divided and conquered by enemies of the republic foreign and domestic.
    These wars required substantial revenues; revenue extraction provoked popular resistance, which provoked more state-building. The revolution in the name of the people was advanced against the people by the suppression of political clubs and local militia. In the end, this only elevated Napoleon Bonaparte, a new monarch at the head of a still larger state apparatus.

    America designedly fought no major wars after the revolution, until 1812.  No less a military hero than Washington established this wise policy. Both the American and French revolutionaries invoked the imagery of Roman republicanism. But the ‘Roman’ imagery associated with Washington linked him to Cincinnatus, the man called from his farm to serve the republic who, having served, returned to his plow.

    On the economic level, Karl Marx got it somewhat wrong. The French Revolution was not a ‘bourgeois revolution’ in the same sense as the revolutions in England and America. To be sure, the revolution did establish a political economy based on private property rights. However, the revolution also confirmed France as a statist country with a bourgeoisie largely uninvolved in industry or finance. Although the populations of both countries were mostly agrarian, French farmers we peasants revolting against landlord-aristocrats, and then against the extractive French state. Independent and commercially-oriented, American farmers rebelled first against a foreign state, then against American debt-holders, but lacked any moral purchase with which to resists George Washington or Congress, whom they had helped to elect.

    Finally, on the level of religion, it is customary to observe that the close association between the Catholic Church and the French monarchy made anticlericalism and even atheism an all-too-attractive alternative to what might be termed the spiritual side of absolutism. Absolute monarchy made Christianity itself suspect. The reality is more complex. Most of the more ardent atheists were renegade aristocrats, the Marquis de Sade being the most conspicuous example. Among the middle classes, however, most revolutionaries were Christians, whether Catholics or Protestants. A minority were atheists or agnostics. They weren’t much interests in libertinism à la Sade. Many were secular moralists who wanted somehow to retain much of Christian morality without its theological underpinnings. The kind of military discipline required by this not-very-bourgeois middle-class republic required moral discipline.

    The problem arose in 1790, when the National Assembly voted not only to abolish tithes, cutting off Church income, but also to reorganize the Church dioceses and to make clerics salaried state officials. That is, the republic sought to entwine the Church in the state structure more tightly than the monarchy had done. As a result, with respect to education, eventually the regime attempted to replace the parish priest with the local schoolmaster. The philosophe Condorcet calls the teachers instituteurs, which means agents of the founding morality of the republic. The republican schoolteacher would then be an agent of the state operating locally, inculcating the proper secular republican virtues in the young.

    Needless to say, all of this attracted the unfavorable attention of the clergy and their many faithful adherents throughout the country. It fueled passions on all sides, encouraging everyone to think of politics as an irreconcilable spiritual conflict.

    In the United States, where the clergy very often supported the revolution on the basis of a Biblically-oriented version of natural and civil rights, where the established, Anglican Church had much less strength than the Catholic Church of France—hardly any at all in many colonies, which had been founded by religious dissenters—thee was usually no sharp conflict between Enlightenment types, who could afford to remain discreet, and a generally, though not entirely, pious citizenry. The American Founding saw a collaboration between such genuine Christians as John Dickinson, John Jay, and the clergy, and such Deists and secularists as Franklin, Jefferson, and Adams. As for the schools, they remained largely in the hands of religious men for a long time, because religiosity in America simply did not contradict republicanism.

    To answer my question—why republican France saw simultaneous instability and state-building, while republican America saw a civil war delayed long enough so that a resolute president and his fellow Unionists could restore the republic and preserve the national state—I have admired arguments advanced by Friedrich Gentz, who points to the moderation and legitimacy of the American Revolution. I have supplemented Gentz’s analysis in two main ways:

    First: the class differences in American versus the conflict of estates in France. Because estates are imbricated in a statist or proto-statist structure, every major social conflict threatens the regime itself. Class animosities, by contrast, are often directed not at ‘the state’ at all, and often have little or no revolutionary potential. Note well: many of the worst revolutions of the twentieth century, and many of the worst revolutionary outcomes, occurred in countries with traditions of imposing state structures—Russia, Germany, China.

    Second, the socioeconomic bases of the American Revolution were agrarian and commercial; the socioeconomic bases of the French revolution were agrarian and military—military because the state-building monarchic regime preceded the revolution. The Roman-republican militarist imagery of the French revolutionaries reflected and glorified this condition, a legacy of the statism or proto-statism induced by the saliency of Machiavellianism in Europe, crowded with countries formidable to one another. The Americans faced less dangerous enemies on their continent, needing less ‘state’ than Europeans. The state-building aspect of Machiavellianism made less sense here.

    In the eighteenth century, a story well known to students of the ancient world was the clash between the two great republics of Rome and Carthage. Rome was a military republic, a regime of the citizen-soldier. Carthage was a commercial republic. The French attempt to modernize the military republicanism of Rome led to disaster, eventually to Napoleon’s career, which might be described as Caesarism on amphetamines. The attempt to modernize the commercial republicanism of Carthage, seen in America and more gradually in England, led to a surprising result: the commercial republics, unlike the ancient republic, have enjoyed victories in the major wars they’ve fought against regime enemies. The English themselves in the 1780s, then the American Confederates, then the monarchic Germans of the First World War and the German tyranny of the Second, and finally the communist and eastern Europe all lost military/political confrontations with regimes they believed too sot, too money-mad, too unsoldierly to fight.

    The governance of faction is the practical problem of political life. On this, the statist polities appear more formidable than they are. State power, the ability to impose and to intrude, generates opposition precisely targeted against the political order itself. It sharpens factionalism even as it attempts to smother it. By contrast, regimes of liberty diffuse opposition and moderate or at least redirect political passions. Given the massive increase of technological power that modern life encourages, and the accordingly massive increase in the power of the state, the political discoveries of the American revolutionaries will continue to prove indispensable in the twenty-first century, the century in which you will raise families, govern, and engage others in the American regime of self-government.

     

    Filed Under: Nations

    Marx’s Critique of Liberalism

    April 23, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Karl Marx shares the materialist assumptions of the more optimistic forms of pre-Kantian modern liberalism. He lists these in The Holy Family. They are: “the original goodness and equal intellectual endowment of man, the omnipotence of experience, habit and education [i.e., the malleability of human nature], the decisive importance of industry [i.e., the labor theory of value], the justification of enjoyment [i.e., hedonism],” along with empiricism. Hobbes and Locke would demur on the allegation of natural goodness and intellectual equality, although not on egalitarianism generally, but they endorse all the other items. And, as the example of some of the philosophes shows, liberalism comes in a sunny, human-perfectibility form as well as its drizzly, British Isles one. The British liberals, with Marx, also make “enlightened interest” the “principle of all morality”; they demur, however, on the claim of natural human sociality (although another good ‘liberal,’ Thomas Jefferson, would not).

    Marxism shares with modern liberalism the overall pattern of the modern philosophic project, particularly as seen in Bacon. Marx himself acknowledges this. Bacon is “the real ancestor” of “English materialism and all modern experimental science.” His disciple Hobbes makes “power and freedom” identical (The Holy Family; see also Capital III. 7). Enlightenment is part of this pattern, or project. Marx sees himself as carrying forward the Enlightenment task, to “unmask human self-alienation.” As do most of the principal modern philosophers, Marx regards human beings as self-created, creating through their own labor, aimed at the conquest of nature. The struggle with nature, seen in “the labor process,” is “the necessary condition for affecting exchange of matter between men and nature; it is the everlasting, nature-imposed condition of human existence, and therefore is independent of every social phase of that existence, or rather, is common to every such phase” (Capital III. 7).

    Marx shares the egalitarianism of earlier moderns. With respect to the character of human wants, the lures which impel men to strive against outer nature, it “makes no difference” whether wants “spring from the stomach or from fantasy” (Capital I. 7). This equalization of human wants, in such sharp contrast with, for example, Aristotelian hierarchy, is identifical to the arguments seen in Smith and Mandeville (that “honest, clear-headed man” [Capital VII. 25]). The same goes for Marx’s labor theory of value, which is already in Locke: All kinds of labor are equal, a point, Marx claims, that Aristotle ‘fails’ to see.

    Progress, in this view, consists of the progressive appropriation of the matter of outer nature for the purposes of inner nature–to be sure, no less material than outer nature, but organized humanly. The progress from the state of nature to civil society and eventually, after centuries of despotism, to political democracy has the same general direction as Marxist dialectic.

    This said, there is modernity and then there is modernity; modernity comes in a several (often mutually rivaling) varieties. The results of Marxism in practice—by Marxism’s own standards, the crucial test—cannot allow anyone to leave things at comparisons. The contrasts between Marxian and ‘liberal’ regimes have been noticeable, even after Marxian regimes ‘liberalize.’

    While Marx applauds the philosophic work of modern materialism so far, he also criticizes it, along with the political regimes it has spawned. Marx allows that the Enlightenment has unmasked human self-alienation in its “holy forms,” crushing the ‘infamy’ that is religion, but it has actually fostered alienation in its “unholy forms,” possessive individualism and capitalism. (See “Toward the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Law.”)  Locke is the best of all previous materialists, but his materialism centers on the individual, objectivist, remaining at best civil-social. Marxian materialism, centers on “sensuous human activity,” praxis; comprehensively social, it includes politics (Theses on Feurbach). Liberals start with the state of nature, but in real history the individual comes last, and is a social product (Critique of Political Economy, Introduction). The modern, liberal state is merely “an accommodation between the political and the unpolitical state.” Machiavelli had said this, thinking of Christianity; Rousseau had said this, too, thinking of the middle class. Liberals did not say it. Marx complains that freedom, “the feeling of man’s dignity,” “with Christianity vanished into the blue of heaven,” leaving earthly life open to bourgeois egoism. (See “Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of the State.”)

    Like other moderns who are not liberals, Marx wants to ‘de-feminize’ or re-thumotize the world. The Communist Manifesto ends with a conspicuously ‘manly’ or spirited peroration. Unlike the Declaration of Independence’s manly and spirited peroration, the Manifesto predicts victory, relies on no Providence, refuses to moderate its spiritedness. The liberal regimes don’t go far enough, offering only formal, political, epiphenomenal liberation, “the negation of alienation within alienation,” the final order of liberation within the prevailing order of things. In America, the State is free but men are not; the tyrannical relations of employer and employee remain. Modern natural right is egoistic/individualist, yielding a society based upon the inhuman cash nexus. Money is the “alienated essence of man’s labor and life,” a social relation disguised as a thing, a ‘thingification’ of social relations. Money externalizes a social practice, labor, such that the laborer looks at his own work as a thing to be sold, a mere means to get money, rather than an authentic life activity. We get money in order to buy ‘goods’ to consume and time in which to lay about; human means are aimed at animalistic ends. Hobbes’s state of nature reappears within society itself, a war of all against all pitting men alienated from their humanness and from their fellows. Godlike, the bourgeoisie has created a world after its own image, moving like a decidedly unholy world-spirit, ever changing, destroying old life-ways in order to create anew. This is the penultimate, deformed but necessary, ‘dialectical’ move in human history, which is the story of the self-creation of human beings through labor. Self-creation makes man the free and universal being, the only species that remakes/synthesizes all of nature, bending it to his collective, not merely individualistic will. Freedom is power. “The principle of politics is will.”

    Marx’s celebration of sociality over individuality causes him to sound rather like Aristotle, or any modern pope, on the topic of usury (Capital II. 4). Capital is even worse; describing it, Marx invokes Bram Stoker-like images of gothic horror: “Capital is dead labor, that vampire-like, only lives by sucking living labor, and lives the more, the more labor it sucks” (Capital II. 4). And so Marx sharply departs from liberalism not only by proposing a variant form of the labor theory of value but in his application of that theory. With international capital comes an international proletariat as disenchanted and dis-enchanting as the bourgeoisie, but more numerous (90% of the population, according to Marx), more productive, and therefore potentially far more powerful. The universal suffrage wrought by liberalism is not panacea, but it “possessed the incomparably higher” (if quite unintended) “merit of unchaining the class struggle,” of bringing “the real people” (as distinguished from the middle class alone) onstage for the first time (Class Struggles in France). The revolutionary dictatorship of the proletariat, announced first in 1848 (the first shot in a world war of classes) will soon be at hand (Critique of the Gotha Program). Increasingly conscious of its own power and of the ways of power, the international proletariat will expropriate the expropriators of the products of its labor, establish its own brief dictatorship, abolish private property and thereby abolish politics as we have known it—an instrument of class domination.

    Looking at the most liberal of the liberal regimes, that of the United States, Marx insists that merely political emancipation seen there will not do, even for settling the problem of religious conflict. To abolish religion entirely—part of the radical Enlightenment project—and thus to find a final solution to the problem of religious differences, one must also abolish private property, that is, “the right of self-interest” and the division of labor. Only when labor unifies in a far more profound unity than any seen in the federalism of the ‘United’ States, will the State transcend particular religions to become “a universality” (“On the Jewish Question”). The maintenance of the civil society of private individuals seen in liberal religious toleration, which means continued toleration of religion, means men still treat each other as means. Marx instead wants the advent of “species being,” the extension of conscious life that distinguishes the human species from other animal species (Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts) to replace liberal “security” (as per Hobbes and Locke), that “guarantee of egoism” to continued preservation of itself. “The political revolution dissolves civil life into its constituent elements without revolutionizing those elements themselves and subjecting them to criticism” (“On the Jewish Question”). ‘Judaism’ is Marx’s synecdoche for the money society of liberalism, whose devotees worship money as value-giver. But this god is false, “the alienated essence of man’s labor and life.”

    This critique of liberalism, as Marx makes clear in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, is a ‘materialized’ form of Hegelian dialectic, “the dialectic of negativity as the moving and productive principle,” seen in the historical alternation of “alienation and transcendence.” It is Marx’s neo-Hegelianism that accounts for both his similarity to, and his divergence from, modern liberal philosophers. Hegel of course subsumes all previous philosophic doctrines into his own system on the basis of his omnivorous, all-synthesizing dialectical ‘Absolute Spirit,’ the self-mastery of which consummates a vast process of which Bacon’s ‘conquest of nature’ afforded an early glimmering. The Baconian, Hobbesian, Lockean, French-philosophe, and even Kantian elements of Marx (the latter seen in his indignation of the use of human beings as means, not ends), make sense in terms of this Hegelian character of his thought.

    Why then has Marxism in practice resulted in so much tyranny, with the further result that Marxism itself has been largely discredited? Hegel and Marx are among those who have attempted to lift liberalism from its deliberate occupation of the low but solid ground. What makes liberalism so difficult to lift?

    Another anti-liberal philosopher, Nietzsche, famously predicts that national war, not class war, will characterize the future of the world, because the will to power will endure. But Marx says much the same thing about power, if his comments on labor as Baconian conquest are remembered; yet Nietzsche got the form that the will to power would take correct, as Marx did not. Marx rejects Nietzsche’s prediction in advance with the rhetorical question, “Is Achilles possible when powder and shot has been invented?” Marx fails to see that the answer is ‘yes.’

    The thumotic man, the warrior spirit, remains alive in the modern world, both as a physical warrior and as a mind-warrior. Marx himself is one of the latter, explicitly linking philosophy to the project of changing the world, not just understanding it. He fails to see that political men think the same way, and they have armies at their disposal. Marx, Hegel-as-materialist, weakly grasps politics, which he dismisses as epiphenomenal. Modern liberalism gives less scope for politics than the ancients did, splitting it off from civil society and therefore from economic life, but the milder politics that resulted did not dismiss political men as anachronisms, limiting their revulsion to tyrants (whom Aristotle doesn’t classify as genuinely political men at all). Tyrannical souls will rage against the liberal regimes, adopting such thumotic ideologies as Communism and its structural twin, Fascism, but they have been outnumbered and, so far, outgunned by the productive power of the bourgeois order. Marx does not anticipate that his philosophy and the rhetoric he deploys to advance it will attract the kind of men very likely to oppose liberalism too thumotically, too unintelligently.

    The excessively spirited man is unlikely to be sufficiently ‘erotic’ or receptive to study concrete circumstances patiently, without giving way to moral indignation or bending what he knows to polemical purposes. In Marx himself one sees an intense conflict between eros and thumos, a conflict which, in his disciples, saw the unqualified victory of thumos. Marx too-hastily eschews all natural-right philosophy in his angry critiques of a particular kind of natural right, modern liberal natural right. This lack of a moderating standard of conduct led to a series not of supermen but of super-Robespierres, who told the workers they had nothing to lose but their chains. On the contrary, millions lost their lives or were fastened in chains. Instead of recognizing each social class as a potential faction, as the natural-right commercial republicans did, Marxists treated a particular class the way religionists often think of themselves, and as Hegel thought of himself: as the God-bearing (or ‘History’-bearing) class destined to carry humanity to glory. But whereas religionists teach the God-bearing nation that God is the heaviest burden, the strictest lawgiver, the gravest imposer of responsibilities, Marxists ‘realistically’ speak of power, of ‘laws’ inhering in social relations, rather than laws untouched by what human beings think or do. What realism? What law?

    Marx writes, “All mythology subdues, controls, and fashions the forces of nature in the imagination and through imagination; it disappears when real control is established.” To which Publius replies: “In framing a government which is to be administered by men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: you must first enable the government to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself.” To oblige anyone to do anything, you need a standard beyond his own will and you need institutions so arranged as to check him from doing as he will if, in a fit of libido dominandi or even honest moral indignation, he inclines to violate that standard. More thumotic, and less genuinely scientific than it knows, Marxism fails on both counts, in theory and in practice. Liberalism does not, always.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 142
    • 143
    • 144
    • 145
    • 146
    • …
    • 226
    • Next Page »