Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for March 2022

    Political ‘Identitarianism’

    March 30, 2022 by Will Morrisey

    Amy Gutmann: Identity in Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003.

     

    ‘Identity politics’ has its partisans. Citizens in democratic republics often organize around “ethnicity, race, nationality, culture, religion, gender, sexual orientation, class, disability, age, ideology, and other social markers,” forming “identity groups” intended to exert political influence on such regimes. Gutmann wants to understand what this means for democracy—whether such organizations are good or bad when it comes to securing “democratic justice.”

    Identity groups arise whenever a regime respects individuals’ “freedom of association”; indeed, “a society that prevents identity groups from forming is a tyranny.” Many modern tyrannies have attempted to eradicate identity groups altogether, earning the pejorative title, ‘totalitarian.’ Gutmann defines democracy as a regime animated by three principles: civic equality, liberty, and opportunity. Civic equality means “the obligation of democracies to treat all individuals as equal agents in democratic politics and support the conditions that are necessary for their equal treatment as citizens.” Equal freedom means “the obligation of a democratic government to respect the liberty of all individuals to live their own lives as they see fit consistent with the equal liberty of others.” Basic opportunity means “the capacity of individuals to live a decent life with a fair chance to choose among their preferred ways of life.” In terms of democratic justice, then, identity groups “are not the ultimate source of value in any democracy committed to equal regard for individuals,” but neither are they necessarily a source of evil. “Equal regard for individuals—not identity groups—is fundamental to democratic justice.” Identity groups that regard themselves as the ultimate source of value might easily “subordinate the civil equality and equal freedom of persons (inside or outside the group) to their cause” by, among other things, denying individuals the right “to live their lives as they see fit.” 

    Nonetheless, identity groups may have value in democracies. If the moral principles esteemed by the group comport with individual freedom, the group will strengthen members’ commitment to that. Also, “numbers count in democratic politics,” so individual members of identity groups will exercise more influence within the regime than they could if they acted alone. In organizing themselves this way, citizens can better secure their civic equality, their freedoms, and their opportunities. Finally, “even when identity groups do not combat injustice, as long as they do not inflict it, they can be valued and valuable for the mutually supportive relationships that they provide their members.”

    Identity groups may be organized or unorganized, inside or outside government institutions, based on a chosen (e.g., an ideology) or unchosen (race) characteristic. Identity groups are not the same as interest groups. An interest group “organizes around a shared instrumental interest”; its members may not ‘identify with’ one another for any other reason. The interests they pursue precede the formation of the group; members aggregate to secure something they want. Identity group politics centers on “a sense of who people are.” Though distinct, interests and identity usually find themselves in “close connection.” “Democratic politics is bound up with both how people identify themselves and what they therefore want”; group identities and interests often reinforce one another, as seen in the civil rights movement of the 1960s. 

    Although the civil rights movement sought reforms consistent with democratic justice, their enemies in the Ku Klux Klan, equally an identity group, did not. As the example shows, identity groups may or may not “impede democratic justice.” “When mutual identification entails putting considerations of group identity above considerations of justice…identity group politics is morally suspect.” This has often been the case—so much so, that critics of identity politics charge that it endangers democracy itself by discouraging compromise, encouraging sectarianism, and making too much of characteristics not chosen but imposed by accidents of birth. On the other side, partisans of multicultural politics often present themselves as “preoccupied with supporting particularistic identities and interests,” ignoring or denying “egalitarian principles” central to democracy. 

    Gutmann tellingly cites James Madison on faction. Madison defines a faction as any group that opposes the public good—an interest group or, for that matter, identity group which practices and preaches injustice. In the tenth Federalist, Madison famously insists that since factions are to liberty what fire is to air, it is futile to destroy liberty in an attempt to stamp out injustice. For Gutmann, who defines identity groups not as necessarily factitious but as neither good nor bad as such, “identity politics is an important manifestation” of the liberty Madison defends. And the regime of democratic republicanism deserves defense. It is not a neutral political instrument but a way of “institutionaliz[ing] in politics a more ethical treatment of individuals than the alternatives to democracy, which range from benevolent to malevolent autocracies and oligarchies.” Therefore, “identity groups need to be assessed by the same standards that one would apply to any groups that make political claims and exert political influence in democracies.”

    In her case, these standards inhere not in natural rights of individuals but in civic equality. “There is no ethically neutral place to evaluate the contribution of identity groups to democratic societies, nor would a neutral place be desirable if it were available.” Rather, the regime of democracy “can and ideally should be a deliberative democracy, offering opportunities for its citizens to deliberate about the content of democratic justice and to defend their best understanding of justice at any given time.” This, she seems to believe, makes it unnecessary to conceive of rights as natural, although they might not be historical in the ‘ontological,’ Hegelian and Marxist sense of a rationally ascertainable and predictable course of events that determines the best understanding of justice at any given time. That is, she emphasizes the deliberative or prudential dimension of reasoning, not its theoretical or (putatively) scientific dimension. She may not consider nature as anything but ethically neutral, and thus an unfit source of moral principles.

    Far from being a historical determinist, Gutmann considers a “just democracy” a regime that “respects the ethical agency of individuals”; “since individuals are the ultimate source of ethical value, respect for their ethical agency is a basic good.” Such agency has two components: “the capacity to live one’s own life as one sees fit consistent with respecting equal freedom for others,” and “the capacity to contribute to the justice of one’s society and one’s world.” Political ethics in a democratic regime consists of “a public commitment to treating individuals as ethical agents,” neither as “atomistic individuals” with no social or political obligations to one another nor as cells in a larger organism, with no capacity to deliberate and to choose. Civic equality, equal freedom, and basic opportunities serve as “preconditions of a fair democratic process” but also stand as “valuable in their own right as expressions of the freedom and equality of individual persons as ethical agents.” 

    For this reason, Gutmann cautions against thinking that all identities are group identities in a morally or politically relevant sense. My personality surely ranks as part of my identity, but I don’t organize a group based upon it. “Wise or foolish, careful or careless, neat or sloppy, serious or light-hearted,” I am unlikely to reach out to my fellows to organize politically on such bases. On one occasion, a frustrated assistant of President Charles de Gaulle slammed down the receiver of a telephone, shouting, “Death to all fools!” De Gaulle happened to be walking by and intoned, “Ah, Monsieur, what a vast project you propose.” Surely too vast even for the Gaullist politics of grandeur.

    Gutmann devotes one chapter to each of what she considers the four main identity groups: cultural, associational, ascriptive, and religious. A cultural identity group “represents a way of life that is (close to) ‘encompassing’ or ‘comprehensive'”; in Aristotelian terms, it is a regime with the sovereignty subtracted. As such, one’s culture forms a part of ‘who a person is.’ When any person engages in democratic politics, he therefore brings his culture with him, often making claims on his fellow citizens on behalf of that culture. And the group he belongs to which organizes itself around the shared culture will give those claims more political heft. Since “democratic politics typically depends on some dominant culture that includes a common language (or languages), school curricula, occupations, ceremonies and holidays, and even architectural styles, that are not culturally neutral,” a minority culture will pursue ways to defend itself, especially if the dominant culture “is alien and therefore alienating to them.” Members will demand “equal freedom and respect” from members of the dominant culture. Yet no large, modern democratic regime can fully accommodate all claims of all the minority cultures within its territory, since democracies need citizens who can speak with one another in order “to act coherently” and to maintain political union. This begs the question, “What kind of political claims on behalf of cultural identity groups are justified in democracies, and why?”

    Gutmann agrees with cultural identitarians when they assert that cultures provide “publicly important goods” to a democratic regime. “Every person needs a context of choice”; a culture or way of life provides such a context, although it also narrows it by defining the range of choices consistent with that way. The question for democrats then becomes, how narrow is that range of choice? And does a given culture “offer equal freedom to its members”? That is, “the state and the dominant public culture that it supports, both indirectly and directly, cannot be culturally neutral.” What claims made by organized cultural minorities can it accept and what claims must it reject?

    As a democrat and a feminist, Gutmann respects many of the claims made by the Pueblo tribe in defense of its cultural practices. But one of those practices denies civic equality to women. A United States District Court sided with the Pueblo tribal council against Pueblo women who brought a lawsuit against the council under the U. S. Voting Rights Act and the equal protection clause of the United States Constitution. The Court ruled that “to abrogate tribal decisions, particularly in the delicate area of membership, for whatever ‘good’ reasons, is to destroy cultural identity under the guise of saving it.” Gutmann judges this “a particularly suspect argument in the context of a case brought by women to claim their civic equality as Pueblo.” The Court granted absolute sovereignty to a cultural group which denies a fundamental principle of the democratic regime which should exercise sovereignty over it in the name of that principle. “Respect for culture cannot mean deference to whatever the established authorities of that culture deem right,” although there may be prudential reasons for leaving well enough alone if “trying to resist injustice would likely be futile or counterproductive.” In the not-so-distant past, some Amerindians engaged in slavery, cannibalism, and torture; had these practices persisted into the late twentieth century, the minds of our august justices might have seen what they were arguing more clearly and, one hopes, argued differently.

    “Legitimate political sovereignty needs to rest somewhere.” That being so, “what degree of sovereignty should any group be granted, and by what standards may its sovereignty be limited…out of respect for individual rights?” Gutmann answers that sovereignty seldom is, and never should be, absolute. “A cultural perspective goes awry at the start if it rests on the premise that a single culture encompasses the identity of the individuals who are its members,” as if cultures were “homogeneous wholes.” As a matter of fact, some members of every culture will “imagine beyond it” even as they use the “resources” of that culture to do so. Just as a minority culture may rightly oppose a democratic majority that makes “oppressive claims” upon it, so a democratic majority may rightly oppose a minority culture that oppresses its members, recognizing them as “fellow persons who can reciprocally recognize the basic freedom and civic equality of all persons, regardless of their gender, ethnicity, and nationality.”

    “If there is a right to culture, on democratic grounds, it must be an individual right to shape one’s own identity, partly through cultural affiliations.” There is no “fundamental moral standing to a group qua group” because “once we treat a cultural group as having fundamental moral standing, we are logically led to subordinate the claims of individuals to the morally fundamental group.” Indeed, “the right to oppose cultural practices that violate basic rights is as fundamental any right within a democracy.” If Gutmann were a natural-rights liberal, this distinction would be easy to make, but because she is not, she needs to base her liberalism what might be termed cross-culturalism.  

    Against Judith Butler, who accuses human rights advocates as “unjustifiably privileging a particular culture—the culture of human rights—over all others,” denying that any “external standards by which to judge any culture” exist, except “the standards of another culture,” Gutmann replies that “critics of oppressive cultural practices need not claim to stand above other cultures.” Rather, in upholding human rights, democrats in fact “stand inside cultures,” but they “stand inside many cultures.” There are democrats in ‘the West’ but there are also democrats in ‘the East,’ democrats in the United States, China, Russia, Iran, Brazil, Germany, Zaire, and partisans of autocracy and of oligarchy in all those places, as well. This is because the “rights culture” isn’t really a culture at all. It has no common language or literature, no common visual art or music, no distinguishable way of dressing, celebrating, or mourning. “Human rights doctrine is multicultural,” and “so is its rejection,” whether by Chinese or Russian today, Japanese or German yesterday. 

    “Democratic standards are shared by particular cultures that can defend human rights in their own way.” There likely will be occasions when these differing ways seem to contradict one another in ways that also contradict those standards. In these instances, “democratic deliberation across cultures about the content of human rights is one way of furthering our understanding.” 

    Gutmann next moves to the claims of “associational” identity groups, the kind Tocqueville esteemed as checks on majority tyranny. Membership in these is entirely voluntary. It is good for a number of reasons, among them being that they promote a political way of life, that is, a life animated by “reciprocity,” including “mutual aid.” Care must be taken to ensure that such groups do not violate “the conditions of equal freedom of association” by excluding those who wish to join them “out of prejudice.”

    Gutmann affirms Tocqueville’s claim that voluntary associations have value in democratic regimes. They do indeed support liberty—specifically, the liberty of persons to “identify themselves as they themselves see fit rather than as government—or any other powerful agent in society—determines for them.”  They “are an antidote to atomistic individualism that is completely consistent with a free society.”

    Even groups which “reject democratic values” may be tolerated in a democracy so long as they do not inflict injustice on other persons or groups. You are free to join the International Monarchist Society (if there is one), so long as you don’t oppress anyone who is either a member or a non-member of it. A criterion for judging whether an association has overstepped this limit is whether or not a member can “exit it and still live a decent life.” Leaving the United Auto Workers imposes more hardship than leaving the American Fern Society.

    Gutmann seeks a mean between the extreme of removing the freedom of association altogether by “forcing all associations to include anyone who wants to join” and the extreme of “permit[ting] all voluntary associations to exclude would-be members on any grounds.” The UAW should be entitled to discipline any member who takes bribes from an auto manufacturer in order to induce him to take a weaker position when bargaining over a contract; it should not be entitled to exclude someone from membership on the basis of race, class, gender or any other characteristic irrelevant to the democratically legitimate purposes of the organization. “Democratically legitimate purposes” are those which do not obstruct “civic equality.” 

    Gutmann considers two Supreme Court cases centered on policies of voluntary groups. In Roberts v. United States Jaycees (1984), the plaintiff challenged the Jaycees’ denial of membership to women on the grounds of nondiscrimination. An association of businessmen, the Jaycees provide what she describes as a “public good,” namely “professional contacts.” Businesswomen were being denied the opportunity to ‘network’ on equal terms with businessmen. It is of course questionable whether the opportunity to do business deals in a social setting is a public good at all. It looks rather like a private good, a setting for one-on-one transactions. Be that as it may, Gutman sets down three “features of discriminatory exclusion [that] create a strong case for public intervention”: that “the exclusion must be discriminatory based on false or statistical stereotyping”—in this case, that women somehow have no interest or ability to engage in commerce; that “the discriminatory exclusion occurs in a public realm and is connected to the distribution of a public good”; and that “the voluntary association is not primarily defined by its dedication to an expressive purpose,” by which she means the expression of opinions, the restriction of which would violate the First Amendment. On the most dubious point, Gutmann claims that, according to “their own stated purposes,” the Jaycees aimed at providing and promoting the skills of “solicitation and management” as public goods, presumably meaning that they were serving the public good by those aims. If so, would it have made a difference if the Jaycees had simply claimed to promote the business interests of their members, with no rhetoric about serving the public good at all? In other words, as Gutmann rightly asks, “How broadly should we construe the realm of public goods and services?”

    In Boy Scouts of America v. Dale (2000), the plaintiff objected to the Boy Scouts’ exclusion of openly homosexual boys and men from their organization. The Court upheld the Boy Scouts’ right to do so, but Gutmann argues that while homosexual behavior might be a criterion for exclusion, homosexual identity should not be. Until (for example) a homosexual man does something “that justifies denying [him his] equal freedom or civic equality,” such as committing sodomy with underage boys, he should not be barred from membership. She acknowledges a complication. “What makes the Boy Scouts case both difficult and troubling is that free identity expression is centrally at stake on both sides,” necessitating some rational “ranking” of “the competing values of free expressive association”—the Boy Scouts uphold the principle of being “morally straight”—and “freedom from discrimination.” Gutmann’s preferred solution here is to permit the Boy Scouts to continue their policy but to deny them any government support, as for example the use of public-school buildings for their meetings. Generally, “the more freedom that expressive associations have to discriminate, the less state support they should receive beyond the support of legal toleration.” She does not consider the possibility that lawsuits of this sort are intended to advance the claim that homosexuality and homosexual activity are morally straight, that the plaintiffs intend precisely to override “free expressive association,” just as she stands ready to override it in the case of the Jaycees.  

    She concludes her discussion on voluntary associations by citing “an underappreciated fact.” Between 1960 and 1990, membership in such associations declined. At the same time, Americans were “becoming more tolerant by all available measures,” in their opinions and in their actions. She doesn’t seem much to mind the trade-off, although it may evidence the increased bureaucratization of American life, threatening the liberty she esteems. See Tocqueville on the perils of democratic despotism.

    Things get more interesting when Gutmann turns to considering “ascriptive” identity. “What distinguishes ascriptive identity groups is that they organize around characteristics that are largely beyond people’s ability to choose, such as race, gender, physical handicap, ethnicity, sexual orientation, age, and nationality.” Every one of those categories is natural or has roots in nature. One can make choices in relation to them, but only to the extent of deciding whether to join or leave an organization centered on them in some way. One can base that choice on whether or not a particular organization is “justice-friendly.”

    Ascriptive identity groups closely resemble interest groups because ascriptive identity and material interests intermingle in “dynamic interaction.” After all, “people’s interests and understanding of their interests are as identity-driven as their identities are interest-driven”; “ascriptive identities inform peoples interests.” “Even in the extreme case of someone who adopts an ascriptive identity that he had never before seriously considered as his group identity in order to make a living”—at the risk of unkindness, one may think of Barack Obama—the “identity plays a causally important and independent role in shaping how the living is pursued.”

    Given the intimate bond between ascriptive identity and self-interest, ascriptive identity groups can still be justice-friendly if they “encourage subordinated individuals to organize and stand up for themselves,” admit members of other ascriptive groups into their organization, and form coalitions with other groups in pursuit of “the general cause of democratic justice.” During the civil rights movement of the 1950s and 1960s, that is of course exactly what the NAACP and other organizations did, with substantial effect. More, “there is no good reason why obligations to fight injustice should be placed first and foremost at the feet of members of disadvantaged groups.” Other justice-friendly groups should seek to join them.

    By contrast, when ascriptive groups are “least successful, they create new (or deeper) divisions among the disadvantaged and convey the dangerous impression that people need only band together on the basis of their ascriptive identities and not on the basis of their common humanity or a commitment to fighting injustice whoever its victims happen to be.” The virulent response of the recent Black Lives Matter operatives to the slogan “All Lives Matter” may be taken as a case in point, and an unsurprising one, given BLM’s origins in neo-Marxism.

    Just or unjust, to what extent do ascriptive identity organizations really represent the groups they claim to represent? For example, how many American women endorse the policies propounded by the National Organization of Women? Obviously, no such organization can represent the opinions of all those mentioned in its grand title. Therefore, it should “recognize a burden of representation to those individuals who are associated involuntarily with the group” by scrupulous “avoidance of injustice.” The temptation to treat members of out-groups roughly should be resisted; the temptation to deal roughly with members of their own group who do not fully concur with the organization’s principles and policies should be resisted even more. Closely related to this danger is the tendency to urge group members to “take pride” in their identity. “What sense does it make to take pride in an involuntary identity?” None whatsoever: If justice requires that I not be blamed for an identity I didn’t choose, then I cannot claim credit for it, either. Rather, “the appropriate object of pride is not the ascriptive identity in itself but rather the identity’s manifestation of dignified, self-respecting personhood, the personhood of someone who has overcome social obstacles because of an ascriptive identity.”

    Given the fact that injustice “is a moral blight on democracy, and therefore on everyone’s life within it”— one “especially great on the lives of people who materially benefit from injustice but do nothing to combat it”— there is a more comprehensive form of identification than those favored by particularistic identitarians. Individuals are in fact “bound up with living in a more just society,” and should recognize “that contributing without undue sacrifice to making society more just will improve their own lives.” Without acknowledging it, quite possibly without knowing it, Gutmann here makes exactly the same kind of argument George Washington liked to make: Your interests and the interests of your country very often cohere with your moral duties. As she puts it, “our interests are bound up with our identification with other people, and our identification with other people makes us want to contribute to making our society more just.”

    However her relations with America’s first president may stand, Gutmann leaves no doubt that she knows the Golden Rule: “We can perceive it to be in our own interest to contribute to fighting injustice insofar as we identify with other people, and therefore with a society that treats other people justly, as we wish to be treated ourselves.” This takes her to the interesting point I alluded to: “Humanity itself is an ascriptive identity, identification with which can serve the cause of justice.” Human beings form a natural species, to which all capable of reading her book belong. Since “democratic justice cannot leave anyone out of its reach,” it requires “identification with humanity and a commitment to justice.” Very well then. Humanity is natural. Justice is right. Put them together, and they spell out ‘natural right.’ For all her ‘deontological,’ Rawlsian gesturing, an attempt to drive out nature with a pitchfork, Gutmann finds herself brought to witness nature’s return.

    Following reason, she devotes the final main chapter to revelation. Natural-right political philosophy solves the religio-political problem by permitting any religious practice that doesn’t violate natural rights. A congregation of pious Aztecs are welcome, provided that they refrain from sacrificing virgin girls to the Sun God, a ceremony violative of the natural right to life. In terms of U. S. constitutional law, this has meant free exercise of religion combined with separation of church and state, which Gutmann calls “two-way protection” of human rights. 

    Her primary interest is in defining and protecting the right to conscience. This is because no more personal, no more individual aspect of religion exists. Further, conscience exists in the souls of religious and non-religious persons alike, forming a commonality (based, again, on human nature) between citizens who otherwise might find little in common. Further still, my conscience likely differs from yours, which means that if we are to live together as fellow citizens, we need to address that fact. Gutmann resolves this latter difficulty by appealing to politics as Aristotle defines it, as “reciprocity.” As an observer of democracy in the Greece of his time, Aristotle didn’t much associate reciprocity, ruling and being ruled, with that regime because in his experience the many who were poor inclined to seek unjust rule over the few who were rich. Gutmann’s modern-liberal understanding of democracy enables her to think of it more along the lines of what Aristotle calls a mixed regime, which does indeed engage in political or reciprocal rule.

    “Rather than deny the truth of revelation for political purposes, democrats” of Gutmann’s persuasion “argue that revelation by itself cannot justify a coercive law because it cannot reasonably expect the public assent of citizens who have not experienced it and do not share the religious faith of those who take its dictates on faith.” What democrats can do is to acknowledge those religious truths which “can be defended by publicly accessible arguments,” suitable for democratic deliberation. “Then it is the argumentative force of a revelation, judged in nonrevelatory terms, that is doing the justificatory work for democratic purposes, not the revelation itself.” This is essentially where natural right puts the matter.

    Given the fact that natural right no longer finds wide acceptance of modern liberal democracies, and especially not in universities, Gutmann appeals once again to Rawls, who “recommends the democratic ideal” because it lacks a “necessary foundation in any comprehensive philosophy” but instead overlaps “with all reasonable philosophies, where reasonable philosophies include religious ones.” Because it appeals to reason, this “ideal”—which Rawls arrives at with ‘deontological’ legerdemain—rules out fanaticism religious and secular, ‘Islamist’ and Leninist alike. “Reasonable moral faith” can be held by “religious or secular persons, so long as they are democrats”—a clever reworking of Kant’s famous sentence in his Perpetual Peace, “the problem of setting up a state can be solved even by a nation of devils, so long as they possess understanding.” True, faith “goes beyond reason, but reasonable faith is compatible with what the best methods of reasoning can deliver at any time.” And it is compatible with reciprocity, which “does not require agreement among citizens or arguments on the same secular or religious terms.”

    Why Rawls, instead of Aristotle ‘all the way down,’ as the saying goes? It seems that Gutmann inclines to the Humean claim that you can’t derive the moral ‘ought’ from the natural ‘is.’ “A purely empiricist position would yield no commitment to democratic justice or to treating people as civic equals, since evidence and log alone are morally inconclusive”; “empiricism is amoral” and empiricism is the way of modern natural science. Whether empiricism suffices to understand human beings insofar as they are natural beings is a question Hume takes to have been settled.

    In practical terms, Guttmann (following Rawls) doesn’t care so much whether a democracy respects “ethical personhood” as seen in conscience because conscience is taken to originate in God or nature or reason or “human individuality itself,” so long as the regime understands that such respect is indispensable to its existence. “Conscience and democracy share a fundamental premise: persons are ethical subjects.” 

    That being so, how shall democracies deal with the fact that ethical subjects often conscientiously disagree with one another? How can democracy justly resolve the rational contradictions that arise from the free exercise of conscience? Guttman answers that whereas “respect for conscience is a moral good because it reflects respect for the ethical identity of persons, a respect that democratic governments cannot consistently reject,” such respect “cannot be an absolute value for democratic governments because it can conflict with other basic democratic principles such as equal liberty.” The fact that one conscience may call for war and another call for peace proves that “conscience is ethically fallible.” And so is “democratic decision-making,” which generates laws and policies individuals may conscientiously endorse or oppose. Once again, there needs to be politics, reciprocity, deliberation—mutual testing of arguments and counterarguments in the public square.

    “The great challenge to democratic governments is to decide when conscientious objection should be accommodated, even though the law in question is legitimate.” One answer to the challenge would be to say ‘Never.’ Such an accommodation would smooth the slippery slope toward anarchy. The opposite answer would be ‘Always,’ or at least whenever the objector doesn’t reject “a basic democratic principle” such as civic equality or equal freedom.

    The first answer would track a strict separation of ‘church’ and ‘state.’ As Locke recommended, a conscientious objector should be free to defy the law so long as he accepts the punishment established for that defiance. Gutmann considers this too harsh. “A stable democratic state can and should exempt conscientious citizens from some legitimate law and in so doing resect their conscientious objection,” and therefore their ‘personhood,’ “without harming other innocent people.” If strict separationists worry that some will fake conscientiousness in order to evade the law—a common enough occurrence during the Vietnam War—then the regime can establish boards of review requiring of the objector some plausible proof of his conscientiousness, such as “past actions and affiliations” indicating “that they hold a set of conscientious beliefs that can qualify them for the status of conscientious objector.” While “not a foolproof test”—the review board is attempting to ascertain the inner character of another human being”—it is fair enough for government work. 

    The second answer, maximizing “accommodation of conscience” by the regime, would fail to “reciprocally protect other citizens of the state from the harms that can come from conscience.” Why should my conscientious objection to a war, or to war generally, result in your conscription? Those who would maximize a government’s accommodation of conscience “are reluctant to recognize is that a democratic government”—even a democratic government—cannot do that “without undermining the legitimate purposes of democratic government”—its need to defend the country against foreign attack or civil disorder, its need to collect revenues, and the like. They “do not expect conscientious citizens to support democracy supports them, by abiding by laws that are legitimate and democratically elected.” 

    To avoid the tyranny of democracy over individuals, or the tyranny of individuals over democracy, one needs not a Berlin Wall of separation of church and state, or not wall of separation at all, but “a permeable wall of separation” whereby conscience and democracy limit one another. Gutmann’s democracy will “accommodate conscientious dissenters when doing so does not discriminate against other conscientious dissenters or undermine the legitimate purpose of the law,” thereby publicly acknowledging “the centrality of ethical commitments to the identity of persons, and the contribution that those commitments can make to democracy.” Such “reciprocity is the lifeblood of democratic justice.”

    In conclusion, Gutmann remarks, “without ethical precepts to guide group identity, members of groups are blind and can just as easily tyrannize over others as aid them. When guided by ethical precepts, individuals can enlist group identity as a justifiable means for organizing in democratic politics.” Her emphasis on the classical understanding of regimes and of politics as ruling and being ruled in turn raises her treatment of ‘identity politics’ well above most of the other available accounts written in the past couple of decades.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Education for Democracy

    March 23, 2022 by Will Morrisey

    Amy Gutmann: Democratic Education. Second Edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994. With 1999 epilogue.

     

    Before her elevation to the presidency of Princeton University, Amy Gutmann established a reputation as a theorist of democracy, not exactly a political philosopher—one who offers an account of the variety of political regimes—but as a defender and explicator of one type of regime. As such, she argued that modern democracies should be understood theoretically and reformed practically along quasi-Aristotelian lines. Aristotle defines politics as a form of reciprocity, as ruling and being ruled in turn. He defines democracy as majority rule, a bad regime in which the many who are poor rule without restraint over the few who are rich. To prevent this, and equally to prevent the opposite one-way, self-interested rule of the few who are rich over the many who are poor, Aristotle famously advocates a ‘mixed regime,’ one whose ruling institutions require the many and the few to negotiate with one another in order to get laws enacted. The American Constitution, with its separation of powers, and its checks and balances, isn’t quite the same thing, it operates on the same principle of reciprocal ruling and being ruled.

    While the American Founders established a regime of democratic and commercial republicanism upon the moral basis of natural right, Gutmann rejected this orientation, and indeed any ‘foundationalist’ understanding of the American regime, as too easily disputable, given the vastly increased and variegated population of the latter-day United States. Americans no longer share a moral consensus upon which to found their regime, she argued. Therefore, the best way to proceed is through a regime of “deliberative democracy,” “reciprocity among free and equal individuals” whereby “citizens and their representatives offer one another morally defensible reasons for mutually binding laws in an ongoing process of mutual justification.” Unlike Aristotle and the Founders, Gutmann didn’t propose institutional barriers to tyranny. What will save the deliberative-democratic regime from majority tyranny is precisely its deliberativeness. Citizens need to argue things out before the bar of reason.

    Hence the need for education, indeed for political education, and hence Democratic Education. Education typically aims at strengthening students’ capacity for reasoning. Political education could do that, or it could descend to the level of propaganda in the pejorative sense of the word, instilling irrational sentiments favored by the rulers. How can the rulers themselves—in a democracy, the majority—themselves be brought willingly to the bar of reason? That is where “deliberative democracy” comes in. 

    “The central question in political education” is “How should citizens be educated, and by whom?” That is “Who should have authority to shape the education of future citizens?” The “art of governing” and the “art of education” either reinforce one another or contradict one another. Gutmann is especially concerned with the political movement toward more parental control of education, as such control, taken too far, might undermine not only democracy but political life itself by allowing the political community to fall back into its constituent parts, the families that compose the nation. Such “civic minimalism” might not inculcate the habits of deliberation needed for citizenship, as education “sets the stage for democratic politics.” Because it does, democratic regimes need a theory of education consonant with the regime, lest their educational policies become impossible to assess. But that regime poses the risk of tyrannical majority rule if it eschews reasoning. Under a regime of “deliberative democracy,” citizens will, as it were, continue their education, learning about a variety of educational policies as they debate them with one another. “We can publicly debate educational problems in a way much more likely to increase our understanding of education and each other than if we were to leave the management of schools, as Kant suggests, ‘to depend entirely upon the judgment of the most enlightened experts'”—that is, upon a sort of aristocracy.

    More radically, Gutmann charges that any “foundationalist” account a political regime, whether divine right, natural right, ‘utility,’ or ‘history,’ is “profoundly apolitical” because they all depend upon some pre-political insight into the character of human nature and of politics. The fact that Aristotle, the author of the definition of the definition of politics she uses, propounds a moral and political philosophy founded upon natural right, and that the American Founders, who made rather a point of government by consent of the governed, did the same, doesn’t faze her, since she argues that no one can get consent to any such foundation under modern conditions. “Only in a society in which all other citizens agreed with me would my moral ideal simply translate into a political ideal.” This being the case, only citizens’ deliberations are left to settle “what the moral boundaries of authority are.” In so doing, democracy must be “liberal” democracy in the sense that no rational way of thinking, “however unpopular,” and no minority, however despised by the majority, may be excluded from the deliberative process. A “democratic society must be constrained not to legislate policies that render democracy repressive or discriminatory.” Within those limitations, education rightly understood “include[s] every social influence that makes us who we are.” 

    Against the American Founders, but also against all “foundationalists,” including Marxists, “deliberative democracy” enjoys “an important advantage”: with it, “one can arrive at a democratic theory of education without first defending a conception of human nature upon which theories of education are typically constructed.” Such attempts, Gutmann claims, depend upon a “fallacy,” the fallacy “of relying on deductions from axioms of human nature,” when “most of the politically significant features of human character are products of our education.” “If education is what gives us our distinctive character”—that is, if education is what makes us human—then “we cannot determine the purposes of education by invoking an a priori theory of human nature.” That is, education derives from the political regime under which we live; the political regime under which we live typically determines how we are educated and, by so doing, critically inflects our sense of what human nature is. Our “self-evident” truths are self-evident only to those so educated. 

    This will not do. If, as Gutmann herself admits, “education may aim to perfect human nature by developing its potentialities, to deflect it into serving socially useful purposes, or to defeat it by repressing those inclinations that are socially destructive,” this begs the question of whether some regimes do this better than others and, if so, which regimes those are. That is the question of political philosophy, and it suggests the need to ascend from the realm of opinion. Gutmann hopes that the process of democratic debate will supply, if not an ascent, as sort of progress via the process of rational sorting-out of coherent from incoherent opinions. Her commitment to reason implies an unspoken “foundationalism”: that human beings are rational and political animals. Her political commitment to democracy implies that ‘the many’ can vindicate that claim, if they can be educated to deliberate together.

    Toward that end, she outlines three forms of the modern state—not regimes, an issue she treats as settled, but states, that is, political communities understood in terms of their size and their degree of centralization. The first she calls “the family state,” by which she means a state in which political authority is tightly centralized, as it is in a small family. The family state “claims exclusive educational authority as a means of establishing a harmony…between individual and social good based on knowledge,” as seen in the ‘regime in speech’ designed by Socrates and his interlocutors in Plato’s Republic. Socrates justifies this authority that “all states that claim less than absolute authority over the education of children will…degenerate out of internal disharmony” because there will always be a ‘disconnect’ between the good as conceived by individuals for themselves and the good of the political community as a whole.

    Gutmann sees that Socrates’ idea of justice cannot be transferred into practice, although she stops short of acknowledging that Plato and his Socrates know that as well as she does. She also sees that the education in this purely ‘theoretical’ regime extends only to the guardian class, not to the philosophers or to the artisans, and therefore lacks comprehensiveness. She rightly observes that “part of Platonic wisdom is not to assume away the problems of founding a family state, but to recognize that the process of creating a social agreement on the good comes at a very high price, and to wonder whether the price is worth paying.” Predictably, she objects to what she calls Plato’s failure to recognize that “our good is relative to our education and the choices we are capable of making for ourselves, our children, and our communities.” That is, poor Plato doesn’t see that our moral principles are ‘socially constructed.’ There is no room in her doctrine for the philosophic ascent from the cave, at least insofar as we contemplate moral opinions. 

    “As long as we differ not just in our opinions but in our moral convictions about the good life”—she doesn’t clearly define the distinction between “opinions” and “convictions”—the “state’s educational role cannot be defined as realizing the good life, objectively defined, for each of its citizens.” That would depend upon how capacious an objectively defined good life for each citizen might be; for example, even in Plato’s city in speech, there are three distinct classes of people, each of which pursues a good or goods relative to their own capacities. In the American republic, at no time has the good life been identified as anything narrower than living secure in one’s unalienable rights and respecting those rights in others. Nor did the Americans’ natural-rights orientation stop Publius from expecting, as Gutmann does, that politics in a representative government tends to “refine and enlarge the public views.” All of that, on supposedly unattainable ‘foundationalist’ grounds.

    For the sake of the argument, however, we can surely stipulate that a modern state should not be as tightly organized as an ancient polis, and that attempts to do so have resulted in tyranny, sometimes called ‘totalitarianism’ in an attempt to convey exactly this point. One rival to this is what Gutmann calls not the “family state” but “the state of families.” This means placing education in the hands of parents instead of the state, and among its distinguished defenders are Thomas Aquinas and John Locke. Gutmann denies that parents can “be counted upon to equip their children with the intellectual skills necessary for rational deliberation,” although it seems that that would depend upon the parents in question—their own character, the amount of time they have available to devote to teaching. It is more likely that some would, some wouldn’t. More tellingly, she observes that children are members of both their families and their political communities, and that there is moral and civic value in bringing them into a wider range of associations and of opinions than a household can furnish. “Children are not more the property of their parents than they are the property of the state,” which gives the political community a moral interest in their education. She judges the “assumption” that parents “have a natural right” to exclusive authority over their children as “unfounded”; nor does the state have such authority. [1]

    Gutmann calls the third form of the modern state “the state of individuals” or liberalism. Liberalism mixes and attempts to balance the first two forms while aiming at a morally neutral education for children. John Stuart Mill, for example, proposed public education for “the poorer classes of children” and public exams for those privately educated, with fines imposed on parents whose children fail. The exams themselves would be “confined to facts and positive science exclusively,” leaving moral education to the parents and private schoolmasters. Gutmann quite sensibly finds this approach implausible, since “even the most liberal states are bound to subvert the neutrality principle: they will try, quite understandably, to teach children to appreciate the basic (but disputed) values and the dominant (but controversial) cultural prejudices that hold their society together.” The policy of establishing a class of professional educators, persons “unconstrained by parental or political authority,” in practice would only slant their lessons toward their own ‘values,’ likely including ‘professionalism.’ Liberals who argue that “neither parents nor the state may shape the character of children on the grounds that they can distinguish between better and worse moral character, yet they may shape children’s character for the sake of cultural coherence, or in order to maximize their future freedom of choice” merely achieve logical incoherence, inasmuch as “cultural coherence” and “freedom of choice” themselves require fostering a certain sort of character in children.

    Very well then. “We disagree over the relative value of freedom and virtue, the nature of the good life, and the elements of moral character.” Yet we also intend to sustain “the practices and authorities to which we, acting collectively as a society, have consciously agreed”—that is, we have given our consent to living in a regime together. That regime is a democratic republic. It will therefore be both necessary and proper to cultivate in children “the kind of character conducive to democratic sovereignty.” Children should be educated with a view to sustaining that regime. Gutmann has already defined a particular kind of democracy that she advocates, namely, “deliberative democracy.” Education in her democracy must cultivate deliberation, reasoned discourse among citizens. Deliberative democracy will establish shared authority over education among parents, citizens generally, and professional educators—really a sort of ‘mixed regime,’ to stay with Aristotelian categories. 

    This will be an education in “civic virtue,” consisting of moral freedom and of “participation in the good of [students’] family and the politics of their society”—animated by the natural love of one’s own—yet also with the capacity for “critical deliberation” about the good. The authority of citizens (of the regime and of the state) will therefore have two principal limitations, limitations founded, respectively, upon the characteristic democratic principles of freedom and equality. These are non-repression (no use of education “to stifle rational deliberation of competing conceptions of the good life and the good society”) and non-discrimination (“all educable children must be educated”). Such a “democratic education is not neutral among conceptions of the good life, nor does its defense depend on a claim to neutrality,” supporting as it does “choice among those ways of life that are compatible with [the] conscious social reproduction” of the regime of democracy itself, democracy’s continuation over the generations.

    On the level of “primary education,” by which Gutmann means elementary and high school education, she rejects the admonition of Noah Webster, based upon the natural-rights republican principles of the American Founding, that schools should reject teachers of “low-bred, drunken, immoral character.” “Citizens of a republic,” she intones, “must be free to disagree over what constitutes low-bred and immoral character,” although evidently not drunkenness or its ill effects on students taught by drunks, and on drunken students. She goes so far as to claim that “Webster’s prescription would require the establishment of an educational dictatorship.” It is rather more likely that it would require the establishment of democratically elected school boards charged with deliberating on the moral standards in question; if that is democratic despotism, we may need more of it. “How many, if any, thoroughly moral men and women have lived in even the best republics?” she asks, rhetorically. Well, “thoroughly” is an imposing word. We are all sinners in the hands of an angry God, are we not? But vulgarity, drunkenness, and immorality are not so difficult to ascertain. What Gutmann wants to avoid are standards of vulgarity and immorality that exist outside her favored regime of deliberative democracy. At the early grades of primary schooling, “precept and reasoning” won’t ‘take’ on students; education “must be by discipline and example,” as Webster was saying, but the discipline and example will derive from her regime, not from regimes like the City of God or the City in Speech, from divine or natural law. 

    “Quite apart from its political function, children will eventually need the capacity for rational deliberation to make hard choices in situations where habits and authorities do not supply clear or consistent guidance.” Such an education will teach children “to behave in accordance with authority”—the commands issued, and the examples set by parents and teachers—and, as they mature, “to think critically about authority.” This education will also “learn how to live a good life in the nonmoral sense by teaching them knowledge and appreciation” of such matters as literature, science, history, and sports—Mill’s supposedly ‘neutral’ topics. “Fortunately, the same education that helps children live a non-morally good life often aids in the development of good moral character”; the study of science and mathematics teaches logic; the study of literature teaches “interpretative skills”; literature and history teach “the understanding of differing ways of life”; and physical education can teach sportsmanship. All of these capacities contribute directly or indirectly to the practice of deliberation in democracy. 

    Gutmann wisely opposes the then-fashionable ‘values clarification’ approach to teaching morality. “The problem with values clarification is not that it is value-laden, but that is laden with the wrong values,” teaching “every moral opinion as equally worthy.” This encourages children in the false subjectivism that ‘I have my opinion and you have yours and who’s to say who’s right?’—a claim hardly conducive either to deliberation or to democracy, one that fails to “take the demands of democratic justice seriously,” one “too indiscriminate for even the most ardent democrat to embrace.” [2] Such “moral autonomy” cannot perpetuate any regime, even a democracy. A democracy will need to teach what Tocqueville calls the art of association, what Gutmann calls “the morality of association,” that is, “the willingness and ability to contribute and to claim one’s fair share in cooperative associations.” The democratic virtues can be taught, by bringing children of several religious and ethnic backgrounds “together from an early age in the same classrooms,” by “bringing all educable children up to a high minimum standard of learning,” by teaching American history “as lessons in the practice (sometimes successful, sometimes not) of political virtue, lessons that require students to develop and to exercise intellectually disciplined judgment.” Educators don’t know how to teach “the whole of virtue”—not all virtue can be taught in a classroom setting—but they can foster the virtues needed for citizens in a democracy. And, since democratic citizens have for the most part already consented to the regime of democracy, they can agree upon the principles needed for shared citizenship in that regime much more readily than they can agree upon religious or philosophic moral principles. The way in which such citizens will arrive at consensus on specific policies, the way of deliberative democracy, itself “has educational value” for parents and educators alike.

    Parents, citizens, educators: “Which democratic community should determine what school policies” Who along with democratic communities should share control over what happens in public schools?” And should students themselves have any say in “shaping their own schooling”? Although Gutmann doesn’t treat ruling institutions formally, she does bring them in implicitly by considering relations among families, school boards, and professional teachers and school administrators. How shall this mixed-regime ‘democracy’ be mixed, with respect to rule over education?

    To answer these questions, Gutmann imagines a school district as if it were a polis or a New England town. Such a political community will seek to perpetuate “shared beliefs and practices particular to this city-state” (such as speaking English and celebrating Thanksgiving) along with opinions and practices “essential to any democratic society.” The distinctive beliefs and practices can be maintained effectively by citizen-democratic rule over the schools. But Gutmann doubts that the second, universal set of practices, “which follow from the principles of non-repression and nondiscrimination and constrain democracy in its own name,” are likely to be upheld adequately by elected officials. That is, she doesn’t want elected school boards “to control what is taught within the classroom,” preferring to leave that to “the educational authority of teachers.” Teachers, she says, must not be forced “to profess doctrines inimical to their intellectual standards.” Indeed not, but why can they not be removed from their positions by democratically elected school boards in consultation with parents and administrators they hire? And if the answer is ‘tenure,’ then why should teachers told to teach doctrines inimical to their intellectual standards, quite likely including their ideological standards, not move to some more welcoming school district, or go into some other business altogether?

    To this, Gutmann replies that in a large modern nation-state, citizens beyond the local community should have their own rightful and (always within limits) authoritative say in what is taught. Congress, for example, should be able to enact legislation upholding general educational standards those elected representatives deem needed to sustain the American regime. True, “federal and state control must not be all-encompassing, otherwise local democratic control over schools is rendered meaningless”; such extreme educational centralization would ignore “the more particular collective preference of face-to-face communities,” which large modern states cannot be. Gutmann endorses not only a democratic regime but a federal state. “At all levels of government, citizens have a legitimate interest in teaching children a civic culture; democratic politics is the proper means for shaping that culture; and primary schools are the proper institutions for teaching it.” Simple majoritarianism in democratic regimes of the sort Aristotle deplores in the Politics brings “political repression.” Federalism contributes to the refinement and enlargement of the public views in education as in other aspects of democratic life. [3]

    But this avoids the question. What about the teachers? They are not democratically elected representatives of anyone. They constitute a sort of aristocracy within the democracy, a group that makes Gutmannian democracy an actual ‘mixed regime.’ She suggests “a division of labor between popular authority and expertise: democratic governments perpetuating a common culture, teachers cultivating the capacity for critical reflection on that culture,” shedding “critical light on a democratically created culture,” “uphold[ing] the principle of non-repression by cultivating the capacity for democratic deliberation.” It isn’t clear how this would be enforced, however: how teacher-ruled critical reflection or deliberation in the classroom would remain democratic. Why would teachers not seek to subvert democracy as Gutmann defines that regime? Why would they not seek to reinforce and extend their own authority by exerting influence upon the souls of their students? “Teachers must be sufficiently connected to their communities to understand the commitments that their students bring to school, and sufficiently detached to cultivate among their students the critical distance necessary to reconsider commitments in the face of conflicting ones.” Nice work, if you can find many people willing to do it.

    As for student “participation” in school governance, Gutmann has little more than a cursory reference to the practices of John Dewey’s Laboratory School at the University of Chicago, a school Dewey ran for seven years at the turn of the last century. Even “the youngest students were given the daily responsibility of collectively distributing and carrying out important tasks,” although I for one would worry more about what the older students might get themselves up to do. This “embryonic democratic society” elicited “a commitment to learning and cultivated the prototypically democratic virtues among its students,” but “not because it treated them as the political or intellectual equals of its teachers,” one is relieved to learn. After all, “were students ready for citizenship, compulsory schooling—along with many other educational practices that deny students the same rights as citizens—would be unjustifiable.”

    To give readers a better notion of what she means by limiting democratic authority with professional expertise, Gutmann looks at three policies that generate controversy in and around schools. They are books, civics, and sex.

    On books, democratic majorities “may be acting within the range of legitimate discretion” in banning certain books from school libraries and school curricula; children are not yet fully citizens, and the right to free speech, extended to reading materials, does not extend to them as fully as it does to adults. As for the right of librarians and teachers to select books, Gutmann recommends “restructuring the process of textbook selection” by opening it to “citizen participation”; such participation, involving deliberation, would “open citizens to the merits of unpopular points of view.” “Restructuring the process rather than constraining its outcomes is likely to have the additional unintended advantage of furthering the education of adults, while they further the education of children”—adults that will include teachers, librarians, and administrators as well as ‘ordinary citizens.’

    On civics, including the civics of the City of God seen in the controversy of teaching creationism as an alternative to evolutionism in public schools, Gutmann is more restrictive. In answer to the question, “Is it within the legitimate authority of a democratic community to insist that biology teachers give the theory of divine creation balanced treatment with the theory of evolution in their classrooms,” she answers with a firm ‘no.’ Biology is biology, not Bible study; as a science, biology has “standards of evidence and verification” that do not include Scriptural interpretation. Creationism “is believable only on the basis of a sectarian religious faith”; teaching it “is as out of place in a biology classroom as is teaching the Lord’s Prayer.” Science is secular, and to pretend otherwise is to violate the principle of non-repression, to inhibit scientific teaching and inquiry. 

    This does not mean that schools must “sacrifice a common moral education,” since moral principles do not necessarily depend upon divine revelation to win conviction. “Public schools can avoid even indirect repression and still foster what one might call a democratic civil religion: a set of secular beliefs, habits, and ways of thinking that support democratic deliberation and are compatible with a wide variety of religious commitments.” Here, she can endorse Noah Webster’s stance: that “every child in America should be acquainted with his own country,” taught to “lisp the praise of liberty and of those illustrious heroes and statesmen who have wrought a revolution in her favor.” She still does not accept Webster’s natural-rights foundation for such knowledge and esteem, but she has no complaints about a reasoned patriotism, a love of one’s own open to criticism of one’s own with a view to improving it. The standard for improvement, however, for her remains citizen deliberation—dialectical reasoning among citizens, not ‘a priori’ principles held to be self-evident. She continues to champion the democratic regime instead of defending any one ‘ontological’ justification for that regime.

    As for “sex education,” she denies schools the authority to impose it, as it “would be unwise…to lead parents to flee the public schools.” Rather, schools should offer parents the option of exempting their students from taking “such courses and rely upon the informal teachings of friends to educate those adolescents who are not themselves committed to their parents’ point of view.” After all, “one of the few things most of us have learned from experience is that adolescents learn more about sex form their friends than from their parents or teachers.”  

    What if conservative or, for that matter, any dissenting parents move to withdraw their students from public schools, anyway? And what if they choose to place them in schools for morally bad reasons? For example, some Christian fundamentalists (Gutmann unfortunately fails to say “some” or “a minority of”) claim that their schools should include no black students because, according to their absurd reading of Scripture, such racial discrimination is divinely ordained. Since “Christian fundamentalists are not just members of a church” but “citizens of our society,” a society that opposes racial discrimination in schools and elsewhere, and since “to exclude anyone from an education on racial grounds constitutes an injustice by our common standards,” state legislatures may require schools operated by such persons to integrate. However, “because the requirements of racial nondiscrimination and religious non-repression conflict in this case,” legislatures are not morally required to do so, by the standards of deliberative democracy. The problem with Gutmann’s argument is that non-white students are not being excluded from “an education” by private, religious schools, however bogus their rationale for doing so may be. They are being excluded from an education at a particular set of schools; a legislature might very well cut off public funding or other direct public support of such schools, but unless a school violates the natural or legal rights of persons actually ‘in’ the school—students, staff—it is hard to see any warrant to require them to integrate, at least on the grounds of “deliberative democracy.” 

    More generally, “If its main purpose is to develop democratic character, how should primary schooling be distributed?” Put another way, in terms of democracy, what is “equal educational opportunity”? Such matters as school funding and busing students to schools outside their neighborhoods for purposes of racial integration arise under framework. One answer has been “maximization”—devoting “as many resources to primary schooling as necessary, and distribut[ing] those resources, along with children themselves, in such a way as to maximize the life chances of all its future citizens.” Given the human tendency to define ‘I need’ as ‘I want,’ under this policy “the state could spend an endless amount on education to increase the life chances of children.” “Yet its resources are limited,” and it ‘needs’ to spend money on other things, as well.

    A policy of “equalization” would require the state “to distribute educational resources so that the life chances of the least advantaged child are raised as far as possible toward those of the most advantaged.” Gutmann judges this feasible, if the inequalities ameliorated are limited to those which “deprive children of educational attainment adequate to participate in the political processes.” Otherwise, (for example) a school that spent extra money on a science program would be required to spend an equal amount of extra money on programs in all other parts of its curriculum, thereby running into the “maximization” dilemma.

    “Meritocracy” is a third policy some schools implement—programs for ‘gifted and talented’ students, for example. This amounts to the reverse of “equalization,” and presents the mirror-image problem. Now, it isn’t that school districts will be financially overburdened with an array of ‘special’ programs but that “children with relatively few natural abilities and little inclination to learn” will receive the least resources and attention. Gutmann considers meritocratic policies acceptable only if schools allocate resources “above the threshold level.”

    How to determine the “threshold level”? She offers two principles to guide educators. The “democratic authorization principle” grants to democratic institutions such as state legislatures “determine the priority of education relative to other social goods,” thus avoiding the dilemma of “maximization.” The “democratic threshold principle,” already stated, specifies “that inequalities in the distribution of educational goods can be justified if, but only if, they do not deprive any child of the ability to participate effectively in the democratic process.” Democratic institutions “still retain the discretionary authority to decide how much more education to provide above the threshold established by the second principle.”

    In terms of financing the democratic threshold principle commits Gutmann to a substantial centralization of authority, inasmuch as local school districts do not enjoy equal available revenues. “More spending entails more taxing, and the tax base of local governments depends heavily on the location of businesses and affluent household, who can relocate—and often threaten to relocate—if school taxes become significantly higher than in other districts.” She judges that “the more practical—and democratically defensible—alternative is to make educational funding the primary responsibilities of states or the federal government.” Given the relative affluence of some U.S. states over others, this really means that the federal government would become the primary funders of schools, unless the Constitution were amended to permit the federal government to require richer states to send a portion of their tax revenues to poorer states. Given the obvious fact that funding always comes ‘with strings attached,’ and given the equally obvious fact that Congressional laws usually leave the details, in which the Devil lurks, to the federal bureaucracy, what centralization of school funding in the name of democracy would really mean is equalization under oligarchy. Gutmann sees this (how could she not?), conceding that “education may be best controlled and distributed locally.” Her compromise between democratic politics and egalitarian distribution of revenue by oligarchs is to limit federal funding and its oversight to “helping disadvantaged children reach the threshold.” 

    With respect to racial integration, she begins by remarking that “the perpetuation of any form of prejudice is a serious problem in a democracy because it blocks the development of mutual respect among citizens, but more serious still is the perpetuation of prejudice against an already disadvantaged minority,” such as American blacks. At the same time, she concedes that many desegregation policies, such as busing, do little to assuage racial prejudice. As a result, democratic institutions are likely to resist those policies, leaving their implementation to judges who, “by virtue of their greater insulation from popular pressure, are in a better practical position than legislators to enact desegregation.” The fact that this in effect makes judges legislators doesn’t seem to concern her; she likes separation of powers so long as one separated power can take over the constitutional function of another, as needed. 

    In summary: “the content of education should be reoriented toward teaching students the skills of democratic deliberation”; financing elementary and high schools should be centralized within the states; financing the education for the education of disadvantaged, including handicapped, children should be federalized. With that, she turns to considering higher education.

    By the time a student reaches college or university, he should have learned “basic democratic virtues, such as toleration, truth-telling, and a predisposition to nonviolence” (it isn’t clear if she means pacifism or simply a disinclination to settle disputes with one’s fists or, nowadays, other weapons). “If adolescents have not developed these character traits by the time they reach college, is probably too late for professors to inculcate them,” she prudently observes. The university’s “primary democratic purpose” is the purpose Tocqueville proposed for aristocracies: “protection against the threat of democratic tyranny.” Universities can do this by serving as “sanctuaries of non-repression” wherein scholars’ academic freedom remains secure and the ‘academies’ themselves enjoy substantial freedom “against state regulation of educational policies.” Whereas the German universities, otherwise the models for many post-Civil War American universities, “were generally self-governing bodies of scholars who made administrative decisions either collegially or through democratically elected administrators, American universities (with few exceptions) are administrated by lay governing boards and administrators chosen by those boards.” In the American setting, academic freedom has meant freedom of professors from administrative authority. This has “made it easy for faculty to overlook their stake in defending their universities against state regulation, to overlook “freedom of the academy.” If, and only if, “taken together,” will these two kinds of freedom “help prevent a subtle but invidious form of majority tyranny”—regulation by state legislatures—without “substituting a less subtle and worse form of tyranny—that of the minority,” the school administrators—in its place.

    As a matter of fact, by granting degrees needed to qualify for certain kinds of work, universities “serve as gatekeepers to many of the most valuable social offices, particularly in the professions.” That is, universities set the standards for other ‘aristocratic’ classes within the democratic regime. By what standards should universities proceed in this role? Gutmann questions the utility of utilitarian standards. “As long as they must look for measurable and commensurable values, universities that try to maximize the social value added of their students must take their signals from the job market.” There are indeed agencies that gather and publicize statistics on the earning power of each American college and university over a lifetime. But “if employers are racist or anti-Semitic, so will universities be in the guise of maximizing social utility.” At the same time, she wants to avoid the opposite view, whereby the university aspires to “the ideal of a community united solely by the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake,” which “may have made more sense where it first flourished,” in the slaveholding Athenian polis, where hard physical labor was imposed upon everyone but free men. This would exclude most citizens in America’s business-is-business commercial republic from universities; so many of us work for a living, even if we are not slaves.

    As before, Gutmann’s deliberative democracy hearkens to the example of Aristotle’s mixed regime. “Is there, then, an ideal university community by democratic standards? Yes and no. To the extent that there is an ideal community, it is one whose members are dedicated to free scholarly inquiry and who share authority in a complex pattern that draws on the particular interests and competencies of administrators, faculty, students, and trustees.” Her term for this mixed regime is “principled pluralism,” which is clever of her.

    How shall access to this mixed regime serving an aristocratic function within the deliberative democracy be distributed? What are the relevant standards for the admission of its temporary class of citizens, the students? Academic ability is the most obvious criterion, but the university should also seek “people who will use their knowledge to serve society well,” and that requires such moral virtues as “honestly, reliability, leadership, and a capacity to work well with others.” Character is harder to measure than test scores, but far from impossible, as she nicely puts it, “to discern.” That’s why admissions committees conduct interviews. Nonacademic qualifications for prospective students are licit, so long as they are “publicly defensible” by the standards of deliberative democracy, “related to the purposes to which the university is publicly dedicated,” and “related to associational purposes that are themselves consistent with the academic purposes that define a university as such”—that capacity to work well with others. 

    When addressing the question of admissions standards in recent decades, the issue of racial quotas and of “affirmative action” inevitably appear. Universities have long favored what amounts to affirmative action, if not quotas, on behalf of alumni children, athletes, and other non-academic categories. Why not affirmative action on behalf of racial minorities, too, especially if they have been excluded in the past, or if they still face obstacles to academic achievement in primary schools, obstacles such as poverty, ‘systemic racism,’ and so forth? Over time, she assures her readers, “as our society becomes more egalitarian and the experience of being black becomes less relevant to the educational and social purposes of universities, the case that members of admissions committees make for preferring black applicants over more academically qualified white applicants will become weaker.” She wants to keep all such policies within the universities operating under the principle of “freedom of the academy” from federal and state legislative command. Legislatures might demand that universities undertake to contribute to “reparations” for past slavery and present racism, but “universities are not the appropriate, or the most effective, agents of reparations.” She does rather like racial quotas in medical schools, since the less qualified M.D.s tend to go into the less lucrative, but more needed, field of general practice, and the medical schools have oversupplied American society with specialists. For this reason, while med schools should “avoid admitting black applicants whose academic qualifications” don’t make it likely that they will “do satisfactory work,” they “would still be free to prefer black applicants who are academically qualified over white applicants who are academically more qualified.”

    In her 1999 Epilogue, Gutmann addresses multiculturalism, patriotism, and cosmopolitanism. Multiculturalism calls for toleration but more, “public recognition of cultural differences.” “To teach United States history largely without reference to the experiences of Native Americans, African Americans, Latino Americans, and Asian Americans…constitutes an intellectual failure to recognize the contributions of many different cultures—and the contributions of individuals who identify with those cultures—to United States history.” While doubtless true, to leave it at that would be to commit the intellectual failure of supposing that United States history, crucially inflected by the character of the regime founded in 1776, has been primarily the work of white men—for better and for worse, but mostly for better, as will be seen if one follows the Gutmann’s own recommendation to study other regimes and states in other countries. And indeed, Gutmann herself insists that “a multicultural history should not imply—let alone claim—that competing cultural beliefs and practices are equally valuable.” Being committed to deliberative democracy, she is no cultural relativist. “The actual practice of a relatively peaceful democratic politics, with all its flaws…tends to be more conducive to cultivating mutual respect than does the actual practice of world politics.”

    To this she adds some entirely sensible cautionary paragraphs about any multiculturalism that attempts cosmopolitanism. Schooling lasts for a couple of decades, at most. That is “too short a timeframe in which to teach everything.” And to focus on “domestic history and politics” enables us to become citizens who pursue “justice, not only within but also beyond [our] country’s borders.” A moderate “republican patriotism”—the love of our country but also the love of its decent regime—can dampen the fires of nationalism.

    It is in Gutmann’s ‘politics of recognition’ that the difficulties inherent in her eschewal of natural right show themselves. Deliberative democratic education takes nourishment from “a commitment to equal respect for persons,” for their “equal dignity and civic equality.” But a commitment is an act of will, not of reason. What makes human beings respectable? What gives them their dignity? If not nature or God, or both, what? When she writes that even “republican patriotism does not full respect the basic liberty of persons,” what is this if not a tacit admission that she needs something like a theory of natural right that endows persons with a moral claim to such a “basic liberty”?

    In her “deliberative democracy,” Gutmann has constituted a sort of egalitarian Burkeanism, a Burkeanism of the ‘Left.’ As such, it surely towers above the current educational fevers, which are egalitarian without being either deliberative or democratic. Whether it can suffice to lower those fevers remains to be tested.

     

    Notes

    1. Accordingly, Gutmann dislikes the ‘voucher’ system, whereby parents dissatisfied with the local public schools are permitted to use tax monies to pay for private education. She prefers to improve public schools. That would be a very good thing, although it is also a long-range thing, and parents cannot be expected to wait for public schools to improve during the decade-and-a-half it takes to bring a child through primary schooling. The competition might even spur bad schools to become better.
    2. See Paul Eidelberg and Will Morrisey: Our Culture ‘Left’ or ‘Right.’ Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 1992.
    3. A variation of federalism might even be applied within schools themselves in order to counter bureaucratic sclerosis in the larger public schools. Gutmann endorses a policy outlined by Ernest Boyer, who would “organize large schools into several smaller ‘schools-within-a-school,'” a structure which would bring administrators closer to the teachers and students they minister to. This, she hopes, would “prevent educational bureaucracies from destroying professional autonomy while creating the potential for more local participation in the making of school policy.”

     

     

     

     

     

     

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Liberal Multiculturalism, II: Kymlicka’s Restatement

    March 16, 2022 by Will Morrisey

    Will Kymlicka: Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1995.

     

    By “minorities,” Kymlicka means, primarily, national minorities, that is groups “whose homeland has been incorporated into the boundaries of a larger state, through conquest, colonization, or federation.” Such incorporation has often been solemnized by treaty. With 600 “living language groups” spread out over the then-existing 184 independent states, and with increased tension between many of those minority groups and the states that ruled them, Kymlicka contends that “finding morally defensible and politically viable answers to these issues is the greatest challenge facing democracies today,” seeing that “since the end of the Cold War” (a few years prior to his writing), “ethno-cultural conflicts have become the most common source of political violence in the world, and they show no sign of abating.” This was also true in the earlier part of the twentieth century, when the treaties governing minority populations proved “inadequate.” On the one hand, “a minority was only ensured protection from discrimination and oppression if there was a ‘kin state’ nearby which took an interest in it”; Jews in Europe were out of luck. But even “where such kin states did exist, they often used treaty provisions as grounds for invading or intervening in weaker countries,” as Nazi Germany did in Poland and Czechoslovakia.

    After the Second World War, “it was clear that a different approach to minority rights was needed,” and liberals turned to “human rights” as their new formula, causing the newly formed United Nations to replace the League of Nations’ references to ethnic and national minority rights with its Universal Declaration of Human Rights. After all, they reasoned, the agony of religious warfare in Europe ended when regimes began to acknowledge the existence of natural rights of life, liberty, and property, protecting them by separating churches and states and guaranteeing individuals’ right to religious freedom. In the revised liberal view, “ethnic identity, like religion, is something which people should be free to express in their private life, but which is not the concern of the state.” 

    The problem was that human rights, whether conceived as natural or ‘historical,’ do not tell us much about “some of the most important and controversial questions relating to cultural minorities,” including the languages used in public institutions, education funding, representation in public offices, federalism, voting rights, and entitlement to natural resources. “The problem is not that traditional human rights doctrines give us the wrong answer to these questions. It is rather that they often give us no answer at all.”

    “A liberal theory of minority rights…must explain how minority rights coexist with human rights, and how minority rights are limited by principles of individual liberty, democracy, and social justice.” Kymlicka had already taken up this challenge in his previous book, but this one is much better written because less ‘academic.’ He spends a lot less time contending rival liberal theorists, which has the effect of clearing things of jargon.

    Although there are many forms of “cultural pluralism,” the main ones are national minorities—once self-governing, still territorially concentrated cultures incorporated (voluntarily or involuntarily) into a larger state—and ethnic groups—often immigrants (voluntary or involuntary, as in the case of American slavery), territorially dispersed, who seek not self-government as a people but self-government within the political institutions of the state. Kymlicka calls states with national minorities “multination states,” states with ethnic minorities “polyethnic states.” Some states are both multinational and polyethnic—for example, the United States. A “culture” is a defining element of a “nation” or “people,” along with a distinct language and a shared history. Indeed, as Kymlicka announces, he will use the terms “culture,” “nation,” and “people” as synonymous, defined as “an intergenerational community, more or less institutionally complete, occupying a given territory or homeland, sharing a distinct language and history.” In the United States, such incorporated nations as the several Amerindian groups, Puerto Ricans, Hawaiians, Chamorros, and the original Chicanos (those incorporated after the Mexican War of 1846-48) often acquired “a special political status”—reservations for the Indians, commonwealth status for Puerto Rico, protectorate status for Guam—and/or special economic status—e.g., land use rights for native Hawaiians, some Indian tribes, and Chamorros—and/or linguistic status—equal status in schools, courts, and other governmental entities, as for Hawaiians and Chamorros. To grant such special rights has made little difference in the country as a whole, since “most of these groups are relatively small and geographically isolated,” a “fraction of the overall American population.” 

    Multination states need not be disunited; such citizens may “view themselves for some purposes as a single people,” as in Switzerland. Kymlicka thus distinguishes between patriotism, “the feeling of allegiance to a state,” from “national identity, the sense of membership in a national group.” He goes so far as to claim that national groups “feel allegiance to the larger state only because the larger state recognizes and respects their distinct national existence.” On the contrary, it is quite likely that the larger state also provides a free trade zone for all groups and provides much stronger military defense than any single group could muster alone. These benefits in turn reinforce the patriotism that derives from a shared history. That is, the history of a national minority ‘taken in itself’ often overlaps with the history of a national minority living within a multinational state, as for example the Navajo and Lakota code talkers, who secured U. S. army messages against German codebreakers in two world wars.

    The immigration that produces polyethnic states has been addressed quite differently at different times. In the United States, Canada, and Australia, for example, “prior to the 1960s, immigrants were expected to shed their distinctive heritage and assimilate entirely to existing cultural norms.” This was “seen as essential for political stability, and was further rationalized through ethnocentric denigration of other cultures”—the last point being Kymlicka’s rather solemn riff on G. K. Chesterton’s observation that wherever you go in the world, foreigners are seen as funny. Political stability, indeed: citizens in all three countries understood that many immigrants came from countries where republican regimes had never existed, that immigrants often brought anti-republican ideologies and habits of mind and heart with them, a point Kymlicka doesn’t trouble himself to emphasize. At any rate, “beginning in the 1970s, under pressure from immigrant groups”—who quickly learned to ‘work’ the republican regimes even as they did not entirely respect them—each of the “Anglo” countries “rejected the assimilationist model, and adopted” what Kymlicka is pleased to call “a more tolerant and pluralistic policy which allows and indeed encourages immigrants to maintain various aspects of their ethnic heritage.” Many of these policies were politically trivial—respecting the immigrants’ “food, dress”—and some not always so—religion. “In rejecting assimilation,” such immigrant groups did not usually attempt “to set up a parallel society, as is typically demanded by national minorities,” although this has been done in the past—quite notably by English-speaking colonists in North America and elsewhere, Spanish colonists in Puerto Rico, French colonists in Quebec. “It is an essential feature of colonization, as distinct from individual emigration, that it aims to create an institutionally complete society.” 

    Kymlicka aims at “mak[ing] a more tolerant and inclusive democracy” regarding the national minorities—civic nations as distinguished from ethnic nations—as the argument for equal inclusion of ethnic groups has been made by many other advocates of liberal democracy. This must raise the issue of regime—specifically, of what a “democracy” is and what justifies it. 

    Liberal-democratic republics typically offer three types of group-differentiated rights. First, they attempt to secure protection of the civil and political rights of individuals. Kymlicka rejects as “profoundly mistaken” the claims of “various critics of liberalism,” ‘Left’ and ‘Right,’ who argue “that the liberal focus on individual rights reflects an atomistic, materialistic, instrumental, or conflictual view of human relationships.” In fact, “individual rights can be and typically are used to sustain a wide range of social relationships,” as Tocqueville saw when he described Americans as master of the art of association. Second, such regimes also offer several kinds of group-specific rights, various forms of self-government without full sovereignty. These include federalism, which leads to well-known difficulties in balancing “centralization and decentralization,” and reservations, which may include higher levels of self-government than seen in states (in the U.S.) or provinces (in Canada). Indian reservations today “are becoming, in effect, a third order of government, with a collection of powers that is carved out of both federal and state-provincial jurisdictions.” Regarding federalism, the United States and Canada differ, as Americans made “a deliberate decision” not “to use federalism to accommodate the self-government rights of national minorities,” whereas Canada established Quebec as just such an accommodation. While the American approach “has tended to make national minorities in the United States more vulnerable,” lacking as they do “the same constitutional protection as states’ rights,” it also provides “greater flexibility in redefining those powers so as to suit the needs and interests of each minority” within a given state.

    The second form of group-differentiated rights in liberal-democratic republics are polyethnic rights: self-expression of cultural norms and customs, educational accommodations, public funding for ethnic associations, museums, and festivals, and exemptions from certain laws. These aren’t truly group rights, however, as they aim at “help[ing] ethnic groups and religious minorities express their cultural particularity and pride without it hampering their success in the economic and political institutions of the dominant society.” They are often intended to break down social prejudices against such minorities, again enhancing full civic and political participation for them as equal citizens in practice, not only ‘in theory.’ 

    “Special representation rights” are the third form of group-differentiated rights. These are much more controversial than the others. Such rights would entitle minorities to reserved seats in state-provincial and/or national legislatures. Kymlicka considers them “a form of political ‘affirmative action,'” whereby republics would remedy “some systemic disadvantage in the political process which makes it impossible for the group’s views and interests to be effectively represented,” sometimes to the point of considering this “a corollary of self-government.” In this second, stronger rationale, representation would be offered not as a temporary, remedial measure (as ‘affirmative action’ was once advertised to be) but as a permanent institutional feature of the regime. As Kymlicka remarks, there is no reason in principle why such representation would not extend to the courts, including the U.S. Supreme Court or (one might add) to the executive, in national and state/provincial bureaucracies. 

    What justifies such arrangements, beyond an intention to appease obstreperous constituents? “A liberal democracy’s most basic commitment is to the freedom and equality of its individual citizens.” If so, “then how can liberals accept the demand for group-differentiated rights by ethnic and national minorities?” Because, although “it is natural to assume that collective rights are rights exercised by collectivities, as opposed to rights exercised by individuals, and that the former conflict with the latter,” such “assumptions do not apply to many forms of group-differentiated citizenship.” 

    Kymlicka begins by distinguishing two kinds of claims made by national and ethnic groups: those made by the group “against its own members,” restricting internal dissent in order to protect the group from instability; and those made “against the larger society” in order to protect the group against decisions made by that society. Internal restrictions, external protections. All groups, qua group, impose restrictions on their members, whether the group in question is a country or a bridge club. “All governments expect and sometimes require a minimal level of civic responsibility and participation from their citizens.”

    Some groups go further, going beyond restrictions needed to uphold freedom and equality and compelling members “to attend a particular church or to follow traditional gender roles”—restricting what Kymlicka calls “basic civil and political liberties,” although he doesn’t pause to explain why traditional gender roles violate basic civil and political liberties. [1] As always, he is particularly concerned with restrictions on the right of group members “to question and revise traditional authorities and practices.” In the United States, for example, Amerindian tribal councils were long exempt from penalties against violating the Bill of Rights, and even after the 1968 Indian Civil Rights Act, a tribal member may not usually appeal an alleged violation to the United States Supreme Court. The tribes have argued that their regimes do respect government by consent but achieve it in ways unlike those stipulated in the American regime. Kymlicka evidently agrees, although he draws the line on Pueblo restrictions on religious liberty, again on the grounds of protecting the right to dissent. 

    Some groups might also deploy external protections in a way that violates freedom and equality, as white South Africans did with apartheid. “However, external protections need not create such injustice” because special representation rights, land claims, or language rights to a minority need not, and often does not, put [the minority group] in a position to dominate other groups.” Indeed, such external protections may “promote fairness between groups.” For this, Kymlicka deems it especially important to protect land rights, as “struggles over land are the single largest cause of ethnic conflict in the world.” Since “history has shown” that the power “to establish reserves where the land is held in common and/or in trust, and cannot be alienated without the consent of the community,” is “the most effective way to protect indigenous communities from” external economic and political power, he endorses such restrictions on individual property rights within minority national communities. 

    Kymlicka thus establishes that individual rights will always be compromised when individuals become members of groups, and that some individual rights must be restricted if the group intends effectively to defend ‘core’ individual rights. My individual right to liberty may be restricted if I threaten your life. So far, this is standard liberalism. The question then becomes, what is the hierarchy of rights? Which should be sacrificed in order to protect the others?

    Kymlicka first turns to the history of liberalism, showing that “for most of the nineteenth century and the first half of the twentieth, the rights of national minorities were continually discussed and debate by the great liberal statesmen and theorists of the age,” although they often disagreed with one another about what those rights should be. Wilhelm von Humboldt and Giuseppe Mazzini, for example, argued that “the promotion of individuality and the development of human personality is intimately tied up with membership in one’s national group, in part because of the role of language and culture in enabling choice.” [2] This form of liberalism opposed imperialism, or at least any form of imperialism that failed “to grant political powers to the constituent nations within” the empire. Some, like Mill, further argued that liberalism itself required nation-states, since without a shared “sense of political allegiance” buttressed by a “common nationality,” people will be reluctant to grant civil and political liberties to their fellow citizens. 

    Kymlicka doesn’t like the sound of that. Mill, he charges, was being “ethnocentric,” if not racist. Others who argued in his way really were racists. “The great nations were seen as civilized, and as the carriers of historical development.” By contrast, the smaller nationalities were considered “primitive and stagnant, and incapable of social or cultural development.” Historicism, then, is fine with Kymlicka as long as it undergirds equality and liberty, bad when it doesn’t. In fact, he observes, “other liberals” such as Lord Acton, “argued the opposite position, that true liberty was only possible in a multination state” because the several nationalities check and balance one another while effectively resisting overbearing centralized power. English liberals in particular “were constantly confronted with the fact that liberal institutions which worked in England did not work in multination states,” as “many English liberal institutions were as much English as liberal,” “only appropriate for a (relatively) ethnically and racially homogeneous society such as England.” The question would then be, how can the liberal principles of equality and liberty be secured in practice in any particular civil society? [3] This leads Kymlicka to call for “truly international mechanisms for protecting national minorities that do not rely on the destabilizing threat of intervention by kin states,” as he was seeing in the 1990s, when “Hungary declared itself the protector of ethnic Hungarians in Slovakia and Romania” and “leaders in Russia and Serbia” made similar pronouncements regarding “ethnic Russians in the Baltics and ethnic Serbs in Bosnia and Croatia.” He also admits that internationalism failed when institutionalized under the League of Nations and does not show why the United Nations would do better. 

    Nor have socialists done any better than liberals. As historicists, they too have endorsed notions of historical evolutionism whereby some nations are deemed ‘progressive,’ others ‘backward.’ But Kymlicka applauds socialism’s more recent iterations “Whereas Marx thought that bigger was better, many socialists (and environmentalists) now think that small is beautiful,” since “certain kinds of community and collective action are only possible in small groups.” However, “this is not necessarily the case,” for “decentralization only meets the needs of national minorities if it increases the capacity of the group for self-government.” A small governmental unit might still leave a minority group in the minority, without defense against those who control the local government.

    Moreover, in practice “socialists have often appealed to cultural identity where this was helpful in gaining or maintaining power.” In the Soviet Union, the Communist Party made such appeals for tactical reasons, “support[ing] nationalist movements in non-Communist countries in the hope of destabilizing Western countries or Western allies in the Third World.” Within the Soviet Union itself, Lenin cheerfully granted language rights to minorities, so long as those languages were used to convey socialist propaganda. For him and for his successor, Josef Stalin, national identity “was simply an empty vessel that could be filled up with Communist content.” 

    Given these theoretical and practical complications, Kymlicka needs to clear a theoretical path toward clarifying the relation between individual rights and national rights. He now moves “to show that minority rights are not only consistent with individual freedom, but can actually promote it.” He will argue that “the liberal value of freedom of choice has certain cultural preconditions, and hence issues of cultural membership must be incorporated into liberal principles.”

    Although the term ‘culture’ “has been used to cover all manner of groups, from teenage gangs to global civilization,” he will use it to mean “societal culture,” that is, “a culture which provides its members with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human activities, including social, educational, religious, recreational, and economic life, encompassing both public and private spheres.” Usually “territorially concentrated and based on a shared language,” but often dwarfed by majority societal cultures around them wielding the resources of the centralized modern state, minority cultures now need institutional embodiment in “schools, media, economy, government, etc.” That is, what Kymlicka calls societal cultures are really what Aristotle calls regimes, which consist of rulers, ruling offices or institutions, ways of life, and purposes the rulers, ruling offices, and ways of life aim at securing. What these regimes lack, however, is full self-government or sovereignty.

    They have been eclipsed by “the process of modernization.” Statesmen typically want “a common culture, including a standardized language, embodied in common economic, political, and educational institutions” fostering patriotism (including citizens’ or subjects’ willingness “to make sacrifices for each other”) and (if those states are republics) “equality of opportunity,” often in commercial markets with no internal trade barriers. Such a regime has in fact prevailed in the United States, which has “integrated an extraordinary number of people from very different backgrounds into a common culture,” with only “a relatively small number of minority cultures.” By the third generation, immigrant families find that “learning the mother tongue” of their grandparents “is not unlike learning a foreign language.” With the spirit of liberalism, modern states, especially those with republican regimes, enable citizens to “choose their own plan of life,” so long as their choices remain within the legal framework. “It is only through having access to a societal culture that people have access to a range of meaningful options” respecting their life plans. 

    But is such individual choice “tied to membership in one’s own culture”? If a person has “a deep bond” with his own culture, should immigrant groups “be given the rights and resources necessary to recreate their own societal cultures”? And “what if a culture is organized so as to preclude individual choice”? Kymlicka claims, dubiously, that to refuse to enable such persistent cultural bonding “treats the loss of one’s culture as similar to the loss of one’s job.” But of course liberal societies put few if any restrictions on changing one’s job because changing one’s job in no way threatens social solidarity and may well enhance social prosperity. While it is undoubtedly true that “people’s self-respect is bound up with the esteem in which their national group is held,” given Kymlicka’s tacit acknowledgment that a societal culture is really a regime, why should the dominant regime not insist on some substantial degree of conformity to its principles and practices? This is especially true of immigrants, who have placed themselves under the authority of the regime voluntarily. It is somewhat less true for refugees, if their presence is temporary—as it often turns out not to be. As for what Kymlicka calls national minorities, the question would be: To what extent will their self-government interfere with the regime of the state? It is true that large modern states are not small city-states, and so can tolerate a greater degree of divergence from the regime, especially if the national minorities are small, with enclaves not located on geostrategic chokepoints. The question remains, what degree? And what kind of principles and practices are tolerable? 

    To these questions, Kymlicka replies that “the aim of liberals should not be to dissolve non-liberal nations, but rather to liberalize them,” an ambition which “may not always be possible,” although sometimes it is: “it is worth remembering that all existing liberal nations had illiberal pasts, and their liberalization required a prolonged period of institutional reform.” And no regime or “societal culture” will likely allow immigrants to colonize it. Kymlicka remarks that “liberals want a societal culture that is rich and diverse, and much of the richness of a culture comes from the way it has appropriated the fruits of other cultures.” This, presumably, on the grounds that “richness” and diversity offer a widened palette of life-plan choices for the citizens. 

    What about the exigencies of justice? Every regime will enforce some idea of justice. To what extent can numerous and diverse cultures co-exist, and even enhance one another, without interfering with that idea. “Protecting one person’s cultural membership has costs for other people and other interests, and we need to determine when these trade-offs are justified.”

    Kymlicka argues against those liberals who say that “a system of universal individual rights already accommodates cultural differences, by allowing each person the freedom to associate with others in the pursuit of shared religious or ethnic practices.” If a given way of life is perceived to be valuable, it “will have no difficulty attracting adherents,” and to give extra political heft to a minority national culture will place an unjust burden on those footing the bill with money or votes. Kymlicka charges that this view “is not only mistaken, but actually incoherent,” since “the state unavoidably promotes certain cultural identities, and thereby disadvantages others.” But so what?

    He answers this question in four ways. The “equality argument” holds that “some groups are unfairly disadvantaged in the cultural market-place, and political recognition and support rectify this disadvantage.” This, on the basis of “the importance of cultural membership.” “External protections” will “ensure that members of the minority have the same opportunity to live and work in their own culture as members of the majority.” Members of the majority regime “cannot reasonably ask people” to sacrifice what remains of their own regimes. To be sure, “this equality-based argument will only endorse special rights for national minorities if there actually is a disadvantage with respect to cultural membership, and if the rights actually serve to rectify the disadvantage.” For example, “one could imagine a point where the amount of land reserved for indigenous peoples would not be necessary to provide reasonable external protections, but rather would simply provide unequal opportunities to them.” To protect the minority nation’s language, Kymlicka advocates government subsidy of education in that language, lest it become extinct; presumably, he would also insist on schooling in the dominant language, without which shared citizenship in the larger regime would be impeded. On the basis of the “equality argument,” a “fair way to recognize languages, draw boundaries, and distribute powers” consists of “ensuring that all national groups have the opportunity to maintain themselves as a distinct culture, if they so choose,” leaving decisions about which particular aspects” of that culture “are worth maintaining and developing” to “the choices of individual members,” whose right to do that will be ensured against the intentions of the minority regime if it denies the right itself.

    Kymlica’s second answer rests on history. “What are the terms under which two or more peoples decided to become partners?” An existing treaty might be unfair in the light of liberalism. For example, “if the members of the national minority never gave the federal government the authority to govern them in certain areas, the federal government is unlikely to accept responsibility for funding minority self-government.” Generally, arguments drawn from the history of intergroup relations will not suffice because circumstances change and treaties may need to be renegotiated accordingly.

    His third answer is the ‘value of cultural diversity’ argument, made earlier. Whereas the equality argument and the argument from history “appeal to the obligations of the majority, this third argument appeals to the interests of the majority,” defending “rights in terms of self-interest not justice.” In addition to the aforementioned appeals to the benefits of cultural richness and diversity, an example of this kind of argument is the claim that “traditional lifestyles provide a model of a sustainable relationship to the environment.” Such arguments may be persuasive, “but it is not clear that any of these values by themselves can justify majority rights” [emphasis added], because “the benefits of diversity to the majority are spread thinly and widely whereas the costs for particular members of the majority are quite high”: “unilingual anglophones residing in Quebec or Puerto Rico are unlikely to get government employment or publicly funded education in English.” Like the historical argument, then, the ‘cultural diversity’ argument will prove good as a supplement to the “equality argument,” but not as the primary argument for national rights or ethnic rights. 

    Finally, there is an argument based on an analogy with states. Liberals recognize that for the time being the world will consist of sovereign states with the right to ‘self-determination’ or self-government, and indeed sovereign self-government, often (as liberal internationalists will insist) within the framework of international law. Kymlicka maintains that “the right of states to determine who has citizenship rests on the same principles which justify group-differentiated citizenship within states and that accepting the former leads logically to the latter.” Even under liberalism, which makes so much of individuals’ rights, “not everyone can become a citizen, even if they are willing to swear allegiance to liberal principles.” While “some critics have argued that liberals cannot justify this restriction, and that the logic of liberalism requires open borders” under conditions other than a threat to the public order, this does not hold if liberalism remains “indifferent to people’s cultural membership and national identity.” As earlier remarked, in England, English rights and liberal rights have often mingled in ways the English would not care to disentangle. While this must be so, it is also true that Kymlicka scants the firm liberal insistence on social contract, sometimes formal but often (as in England and Canada) unwritten but nonetheless elaborated in a set of statutes and court decisions, changeable with changing circumstances.

    Kymlicka quite sensibly writes, “There is no simple formula for deciding exactly what rights should be accorded to which groups.” Given these “unavoidable indeterminacies,” and given “the complexity of the interests, principles and historical circumstances at stake,” these matters “must be resolved politically, by good-faith negotiations and the give and take of democratic politics.” But, of course, this raises another set of questions concerning the institutional structure of democratic politics—issues such as redistricting, guaranteed representation, and proportional representation. While “the middle-class white men who dominate politics in most Western democracies are not demographically representative of the population at large, they are the elected representatives of the population at large,” often enjoying “widespread electoral support from minority and disadvantaged groups.” It isn’t at all certain that “people can only be fully ‘represented’ by someone who shares their gender, class, occupation, ethnicity, language, etc.” Oddly, Kymlicka never mentions ‘ideology’ or political doctrine as a criterion for ‘being represented. Yet what is more bound up with the idea of rights, individual or ‘groupish,’ than political doctrine? He does see that “the argument that members of one group cannot understand the interests of other groups” would “undermine the possibility of group membership as well,” since every group has a range of subgroups. “The principle of mirror representation seems to undermine the very possibility of representation itself”: under its terms, “How can anyone represent anyone else?” It also undermines the principle of democracy, since majorities are achievable but unanimity nearly impossible. Therefore, the only form of group representation he endorses is a temporary form, similar to affirmative action, intended to redress injustices entrenched in the past. He does not say how such a form of representation would not itself likely become entrenched, therefore (eventually) unjust. Generally, then, “the right of self-government is a right against the authority of the federal government, not a right to share in that authority,” as (for example) to guarantee Indians seats in the legislature might simply mean that they would have gained the right to be outvoted, particularly with regard to the issues of federalism, the degree of central government control over their own communities, that they are most anxious to guard.

    To put it another way, if one wants to know what groups should be represented in the national legislature (or in any other branch of government), one would need to know if they experience “systemic disadvantage in the political process” and whether they have a reasonable claim to self-government, based on the ideas of justice sketched earlier. But if you add up the “oppressed groups” in the United States—women, ethnic, national, and sexual minorities, among others—they add up to 80 percent of the population. Why would they not begin to oppress the remaining 20 percent? While group representation “is not inherently illiberal or undemocratic,” it raises “difficult questions.”

    And what if “the demands of some groups exceed what liberalism can accept”? Liberalism may not require one regime, but it cannot tolerate all regimes. Kymlicka has already articulate “two fundamental limitations on minority rights”: requirements by minority cultures “to restrict the basic civil or political liberties” of “their own members”; in terms of what he’s called “external protections,” “liberal justice cannot accept any such rights which enable one group to oppress or exploit other groups,” as in slavery, apartheid, or segregation. “In short, a liberal view requires freedom within the minority group, and equality between the minority and majority groups.” Groups that attempt to push past these limits may do so because to accept them “might imply that the internal structure of their community should be reorganized according to liberal standards of democracy and individual freedom”—it might indeed imply regime change. It isn’t only that such resistance would “limit the freedom of individual members within the group to revise traditional practices,” as Kymlicka points out; it would actually require the group to “revise” those practices. 

    Some might say means that “to find room for minority rights within liberal theory…requires qualifying these rights in such a way that they no longer correspond to the real aims of minority groups.” (I would be among those who say so.) “Is the insistence on respect for individual rights not a new version of the old ethnocentrism, found in Mill and Marx, which sets the (liberal) majority culture”—in the case of Marx, it must be said, a decidedly illiberal minority culture, the culture of communist parties—as “the standard to which minorities must adhere”? Only if liberalism is ethnocentric, one might well reply. While modern liberalism unquestionably originated in Europe, under conditions of modern statism, does that make it ethnocentric in principle, to its core? Not really, as the many non-European liberal regimes attest. 

    What Kymlicka wants to get at is that there are forms of toleration which are not liberal. In the past, they have centered on ‘culture’ in the original sense—on cult, on religion. For example, the longstanding Ottoman Empire permitted Muslims, Christians, and Jews to practice their religions more or less in peace, without requiring them to abstain from severe restrictions on individual liberties within each of those groups. “This system was generally humane, tolerant of group differences, and remarkably stable,” if not liberal, not respecting individual freedom of conscience, allowing intra-group repression of heterodoxy. The Ottoman state amounted to “a federation of theocracies.” Locke, Kant, and Mill would not approve, and Marxian atheists would shrink from it in horror and indignation. 

    “So it is not enough to say that liberals believe in toleration. The question is, what sort of toleration?” If “liberal tolerance protects the right of individuals to dissent from their group, as well as the right of groups not to be persecuted by the state,” then liberalism requires a regime with a state apparatus sufficiently powerful to reach into ethnic and even national minority communities to protect dissenters but sufficiently gentle not to injure religionists who do not persecute their own dissenters. But what if non-liberal minorities “want internal restrictions that take precedence over individual rights”? Should the liberal regimes act to prevent this? That is, “does a third party have the right to impose liberal principles on another society” by coercive measures? If so, to what extent? 

    “Many nineteenth-century liberals, including John Stuart Mill,” went so far as to say that “liberal states were justified in colonizing foreign countries in order to teach them liberal principles.” Although most “contemporary liberals” have “abandoned this doctrine as both imprudent and illegitimate,” depending instead upon such nonviolent methods as “education, persuasion, and financial incentives,” they continue to hold coercion legitimate in dealing national minorities. Kymlicka objects. “Both foreign states and national minorities form distinct political communities, with their own claims to self-government.” To the obvious question—So what?—he can only sputter about aggression, paternalism, colonialism, while worrying that “these attempts often backfire.” Indeed, they often do, but that is no principled objection. He is surely right to say that “liberal institutions can only really work if liberal beliefs have been internalized by the members of the self-governing society, be it an independent country or a national minority,” but that only begs the question of how that might more effectively be accomplished.

    As for Kymlicka, he holds out the hope of negotiations. Given the fact that “members of some minority cultures reject liberalism,” representatives of “the liberal majority will have to sit down with the members of the national minority, and find a way of living together,” carefully identifying what the “views” of the illiberal minority are and seeking some modus vivendi on the basis of any shared opinions that may exist. He hopes that gradually, over time, the illiberal minority will liberalize and, in the meantime, with their right to self-government respected, their liberalization will be ‘from within,’ not imposed. That sort of approach might work with a national minority that posed no serious threat to the liberal regime of the surrounding state. There would surely be times when civil war might quite rightly result, however, and the policy gives little or no help when confronting formidable illiberal regimes ruling foreign states. 

    Will “group-differentiated minority rights” lead to disunity in a country, ruin a liberal regime? Whereas “the impulse underlying representation rights” for minorities “is inclusion, not separation,” such inclusion is on the basis of separation. Although “there is strikingly little evidence that immigrants pose any sort of threat to the unity or stability of a country,” and indeed subsequent generations of immigrants are often ardent patriots, national minorities “pose a more serious challenge to the integrative function of citizenship.” Such minorities may claim “that there is more than one political community” within the larger state, and that the state “cannot be assumed to take precedence over the authority of the constituent national communities.” Kymlicka acknowledges that “it seems unlikely that according self-government rights to a national minority can serve an integrative function.” Such rights instead “give rise to a sort of dual citizenship, and to potential conflicts about which community citizens identify with most deeply”; indeed, “there seems to be no natural stopping point to the demands for increasing self-government.” The dilemma is that “imposing common citizenship on minorities which view themselves as distinct nations or people is likely to increase conflict in a multination state.” Both liberal and Communist states have failed in wielding their substantial powers to change the “national consciousness” of minorities within their empires. “Since claims to self-government are here to stay, we have no choice but to try to accommodate them,” and, he maintains, “self-government arrangements diminish the likelihood of violent conflict,” especially since outright secession only establishes a national state on or within the borders of the larger state, with all the attendant dangers that implies.

    Some liberals, including Rawls, have hoped to establish good relations among such different ‘cultures’ or regimes on the foundation of “a shared conception of justice.” But, as Kymlicka observes, “shared values are not sufficient for social unity.” Sweden and Norway share ‘values,’ but they have no interest whatsoever in uniting into one country. [4] What’s required for political union “seems to be the idea of a shared identity“—a “commonality of history, language, and maybe religion,” and especially “pride in certain historical achievements,” such as the American founding. Since “in many multination states history is a source of resentment and division between national groups, not a source of pride,” this may prove a dead end. Why would American Indians, or indeed most ethnic minorities in America, feel pride in the American founding, an achievement largely of English colonists? 

    There is, then, no “generalized” solution to the problem. “A country founded on ‘deep diversity’ is unlikely to stay together unless people value deep diversity itself, and want to live in a country with diverse forms of cultural and political membership.” And “even this is not always sufficient.” Rather, members of the several national groups “must value…the particular ethnic groups and national cultures with whom they currently share the country.” But on the basis of what? There must be a shared “patriotism” felt for the overall state, but “liberal theory has not yet succeeded in clarifying the nature” of this sentiment. With that admission, Kymlicka ends his book.

    Patriotism is a form of the love of one’s own, a sentiment seen most naturally in the love of parents for their children and the love of everyone for most if not all of their property. Before the Rawlsian liberalism of recent decades, and before the historicist liberalism of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, Americans grounded their regime on natural rights. Being natural, those rights respected love of one’s own without sacralizing it. The regime they founded was intended to secure those rights. They hoped to see the establishment of similar commercial-republican regimes, especially in America’s geopolitical ‘neighborhood,’ the New World. In the more remote areas of the Americas, they were content to promote regime change and to undermine European empires diplomatically, as when President Jefferson sent a copy of the Declaration of Independence to Brazil, carried by a young Brazilian acquaintance of his. In the nearer areas, Americans did not hesitate to conquer the peoples living under rival regimes, most notably those of the Amerindians and (some of) the Mexicans. They also changed, or attempted to change, the regimes of the conquered peoples, with mixed results. When it became clear that the states in the southern section of the country preferred oligarchic regimes based on substantial slave populations to American republicanism, a brutal civil war resulted. What natural rights-based republicanism lent to the ‘American mind’ was clarity not only on the level of reason or theory but on the level of sentiment. In the 1850s, Abraham Lincoln could tell his fellow citizens that he had never felt a political sentiment that did not derive from the Declaration of Independence. Knowing that the Southern oligarchs no longer shared that sentiment, he then could make prudential choices determining what to do about it. As is well known, the defeated Southern oligarchs held out for a century after the war, hamstringing the new regime of natural rights imposed by the Unionist republicans who very imperfectly imposed that regime upon them. But the regime won out, in the end and, in the meantime, Southerners fought loyally in two world wars, on the side of the hated ‘Yankees.’ They did so, knowing and feeling that the regimes they were fighting were worse than the American regime they were living in, and that (somewhat more ‘concretely’) they disliked German submarines sinking American merchant ships, some of whose sailors were Southerners as well as Americans. Shared enemies help, too, and enemies tend to be regime enemies, if your regime is a commercial republic.

     

    Notes

    1. He may not think it necessary to defend his claim because he rejects natural right as the foundation of individual rights, although he might conceivably deny that natural right precludes civil laws against homosexual activity. 
    2. Humboldt and Mazzini, it should be remarked, were historicist—Hegelian or neo-Hegelian—liberals, who eschewed natural-right liberalism. Kymlicka’s own pointed ignoring of natural-right liberalism suggests that he prefers to avoid the complications that liberalism would pose for his own project.
    3. According to Kymlicka, “American liberals” in this period mostly ignored the issue. He evidently doesn’t know about the successful efforts of the Washington Administration to effect regime change among the Five Civilized Tribes of the American southeast, efforts spoiled by whites in Georgia who went ahead and encroached upon Indian land rights, eventually leading to the catastrophic “Trail of Tears.” Efforts to settle the boundaries of Indian territories in part by settling the Indians into agricultural ways of life continued nonetheless, with very mixed success, depending in large measure on whether the lands reserved for the tribes were conducive to agriculture.
    4. Kymlicka leaves unremarked the fact that while the ‘values’ shared by Swedes and Norwegians don’t lead to political unification of the two nations, they do conduce to peace between them. 

    Filed Under: Nations

    • 1
    • 2
    • Next Page »