Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for June 2021

    Anarcho-Capitalism Refuted

    June 23, 2021 by Will Morrisey

    Murray N. Rothbard: The Ethics of Liberty. New York: New York University Press, 2002 [1980].

     

    No mere libertarian, the late Murray N. Rothbard stands as the most intelligent defender of anarcho-capitalism—as sharply distinguished from anarcho-communalism, the supposed end-time of several forms of socialism. The anarchism of anarcho-capitalism rests on individual liberty; the anarchism of anarcho-communalism rests on radical equality.

    “All of my work has revolved around the central question of human liberty,” Rothbard writes. Here he aims to justify “a totally stateless and therefore purely free (or anarchistic) market economy.” For this, “value-free analysis or economics or utilitarianism” won’t suffice. It is a task for “political philosophy” not political economy. The task begins with the individual, with the figure of Robinson Crusoe, alone on an island, seeking his own good. Unlike an economic analysis, which would analyze Crusoe’s “conditions and actions” in order to find the basics of material survival and comfort, Rothbard considers the celebrated islander to establish the “concepts” of “natural-rights morality.” “The Crusoe model enables one to analyze the actions of man vis-à-vis the external world around him, before the complications of interpersonal relations are considered.” On this foundation, he will seek to understand those complications, which include property and law.

    Natural rights inhere in natural law. Rothbard concurs with “the Thomistic tradition” insofar as it teaches that “natural law is ethical as well as physical law; and the instrument by which man apprehends such law is his reason—not faith, or intuition, or grace, revelation, or anything else.” With Thomas, Rothbard affirms that man has a nature: “if apples and stones and roses each have their specific natures, is man the only entity, the only being, that cannot have one? And if man does have a nature, why cannot it too be open to rational observation and reflection?” Ethics stems from this rationally discernible human nature. “The natural-law ethic states that goodness or badness can be determined by what fulfills or thwarts what is best for man’s nature”—a principle defended by Thomas and before him, Aristotle.

    David Hume famously objected to deriving right from nature. Nature is, Hume allowed, but how am I to deduce rationally an ‘ought’ from that ‘is’? If I cannot, then either nature as a whole nor any part of it, including human nature, provides a rational standard for ethics. What we call ‘right’ is only a ruling passion or set of passions. Morality is therefore ‘subjective’ not ‘objective.’ But Hume in fact saw that human well-being and happiness requires society, Rothbard counters. Moreover, social order cannot exist unless human beings know what it is and under what conditions it can effect their safety and happiness. In society, conditions must include security for persons and property, that is, for what is called ‘justice.’ Justice is therefore rationally discernible and necessarily governs the passions, which tell us nothing about what is concerning safety and happiness. Hume himself admits this when he writes that “nature provides a remedy in the judgment and understanding for what is irregular and incommodious in the affections.”

    Discoverable by reason, natural law is universal among human beings because they have a nature. Natural law “holds the existing status quo, which might grossly violate natural law, up to the unsparing and unyielding light of reason.” The legal principles of a society derive either from “traditional custom,” nor from the will of the rulers, nor from rational recognition of the natural law. These distinctions may be found in Plato and Aristotle. Lord Acton corrected them, seeing “the deep flaw” in “their conception of natural law political philosophy,” namely, their identification of “politics and morals,” which led them “to place the supreme social moral agent in the State,” that is, as ruling apparatus of any political community. Plato and Aristotle also failed to distinguish morality not only from politics but from religion, which was intertwined with the ancient ‘state.’ “Acton added that the Stoics developed the correct, non-state principles of natural law political philosophy, which were then revived in the modern period by Grotius and his followers.” 

    “The great failing of natural-law theory—from Plato and Aristotle to the Thomists and down to Leo Strauss and his followers in the present day—is to have been profoundly statist rather than individualist.” Aristotle was right to call man a social animal, of being whose “nature is best fitted for social cooperation.” He was wrong to posit “a virtual identification of ‘society’ and ‘the State,’ and thence to the State as the major locus of virtuous action.” It took John Locke to correct this error by “transform[ing] classical natural law into a theory grounded on methodological individualism,” on “the individual as the unity of action, as the entity who thinks, feels, chooses, and acts.” From this Locke derives the idea of property as inherent first of all in one’s own person, a person who then mixes his labor with external, natural objects in order to establish private property. As James Madison wrote, man has a right in his property and a property in his rights. Although Locke’s pioneering version of correct natural-rights theory “was riddled with contradictions and inconsistencies,” these were removed by later thinkers, especially Herbert Spencer and Lysander Spooner. This firm distinction between individual and society, between “personal ethics” and “political philosophy,” between “a man’s right and the morality or immorality of his exercise of that right, narrows the scope of political philosophy proper to “the proper or improper exercise of physical violence in human relations,” inasmuch as “it is a man’s right to do whatever he wishes with his person.” 

    Rothbard errs in claiming that Aristotle described man simply as a social animal. On the contrary, he described him as a political animal. That man is a political animal, he argued, may be seen in the fact that human beings originate in families, small or ‘extended,’ and that families exercise three forms of rule within themselves. There is the command-and-obey form of rule seen in the relations between parents and children, exercised for the good of the children; the command-and-obey form of rule seen in the relations of freemen and slaves, exercised for the good of the freemen; and there is the reciprocal rule of husband and wife, which he defines as political rule strictly speaking—rule involving discussion and therefore open to practical reasoning. The fact that Rothbard gets Aristotle wrong is an exegetical point, trivial with respect to ethics, but the important point is that Aristotle is right. The elements of what Rothbard calls “the state” already exist in the family, and the family is indispensable to human survival and flourishing, the ends of Rothbardian ethics as well as the ethics of Aristotle and of Thomas. Human beings are naturally political beings, not merely social and certainly not ‘individualist’ in Rothbard’s sense.

    This error, whether deliberate/rhetorical or inadvertent, vitiates Rothbard’s anarcho-capitalism on its foundation. One sees this as he turns to “a Crusoe social philosophy.” On the island, Crusoe enjoys “the primordial fact of his own consciousness and his own body,” along with “the natural world around him.” Lacking an animal’s “innate instinctual knowledge impelling him into the proper paths for the satisfaction of his needs and desires,” he understands that he must learn to find those paths. Because his island isn’t Eden, he needs to work, to ‘mix his labor’ with “the nature given resources and transform them into useful objects, shapes, and places most useful to him—so that he can satisfy his wants.” Clearly, no human being has ever lived this way, except for those removed by choice, by force, or by accident from family, tribe, or political community. Even Adam in Eden was quickly supplied with Eve because God judged that it was not good for the man to be alone. Alternatively, if one prefers the evolutionists’ account, the first biologically human being must have lived in a family, and quite likely a tribe, of proto-humans, where ruling and being ruled prevailed. Crusoe’s circumstance is in fact radically unnatural. In Aristotle’s more realistic account, families and extended families—already exercising political and other forms of rule— deal with scarcity by allying with other families, by extending political and other forms of rule to others.

    On Crusoe’s island, man “must produce before he can consume, and so that he may consume.” In a family, this is true only of adults and older children; infants and toddlers do very little to mix their labor rationally with the world around them. Indeed, the only ‘labor’ an infant performs is sucking, and that is instinctual, animal-like, indistinguishable from the behavior of any other young mammal. However, as Rothbard and Aristotle both acknowledge, human nature quickly develops its innate capacity to reason and therefore to labor in the Rothbard-Lockean sense. 

    Reason teaches “the way things work in the world, i.e., the natures of the various specific entities and classes of entities that the man finds in existence; in short, he learns the natural laws of the way things behave in the world.” At the same time, “he learns about his own nature, about the sort of events and actions that will make him happy or unhappy”—his natural ends or purposes. His mind can then ‘mix’ with external matter, using mental and physical energy to reshape matter “into ways to sustain and advance his wants and his life”; that is, he learns means by which he can achieve his ends.

    “The individual man, in introspecting the fact of his own consciousness, also discovers the primordial natural fact of his freedom: his freedom to choose, his freedom to use or not use his reason about any given subject. In short, the natural fact of his ‘free will.'” Further, by experiencing his mind’s natural “command over his body and its actions” he discovers “his natural ownership over his self.” This means that he can also distinguish between his natural freedom and his natural powers. “Man is free to adopt values and to choose his actions; but this does not at all mean that he may violate natural laws with impunity,” to do things beyond his natural capacities. He can’t fly, although he may learn to reshape external objects in ways that will enable him to be flown and to control the direction of the flight.

    Here Rothbard departs from Aristotle and the classics generally, entering into the realm of Rousseauian thought. Notice that he takes freedom to be unalienable; the only natural limits to free action are power, which is not a moral category, and the prohibition of impinging on anyone else’s unalienable freedom. Aristotle would reply that human beings are not at all entitled to choose their own “values”—language absent from his philosophy. There are moral limits on human choices themselves, and those limits are imposed by the nature of the human soul, which, like the human body, can have good or bad characteristics, make good or bad choices respecting its well-being. Rothbard tacitly denies the human soul, tellingly referring to ownership over the “self.” That is, contra Rothbard, even a human being isolated on an island has moral obligations with respect to the ends he chooses, and not only physical limitations, quite apart from whether there are any other people around, and even quite apart from whether God is watching him.

    Before elaborating on the effect of social relations on the protection of unalienable rights, Rothbard addresses economic relations. Production is necessary to man’s “prosperity and survival, but so also is exchange.” When the man Friday comes onto the scene, Crusoe might enter into a relation whereby he supplies fish and Friday supplies wheat. “This great gain for both men is made possible by two primordial facts of nature—natural laws—on which all of economic theory is based: (a) the great variety of skills and interests among individual persons; and (b) the variety of natural resources in geographic land areas.” Different individuals, working on different kinds of land (or, for that matter, the sea), will enable exchanges to multiply far beyond the capacities of any individual or small set of individuals. Although most immediately these persons are exchanging material goods, more precisely they are exchanging “not the commodities themselves, but the rights to ownership of them,” having already acquired those rights by ‘mixing’ their labor with the elements of nature to produce them. This also goes for the person who hires others to work for him. “The capitalist, far from somehow depriving the laborer of his rightful ownership of the product, makes possible a payment to the laborer considerable in advance of the sale of the product,” and indeed “saves the laborer from the risk that the product might not be sold at a profit, or that he might even suffer losses.” Labor service is itself a commodity; the powers of my body and mind, which are my property, are purchased by my employer. As long as I consent to this sale, including its terms and conditions, I am not his slave. “A person’s labor service is alienable, but his will is not.” “A man can naturally expend his labor currently for someone else’s benefit, but he cannot transfer himself, even if he wished, into another man’s capital good. For he cannot rid himself of his own will, which may change in future years and repudiate the current arrangement.” 

    This contrasts with Aristotle’s understanding of natural slavery (a point Crusoe’s inventor, Daniel Defoe, did not overlook when he introduced Friday to Crusoe). Aristotle sees that some human beings exercise their wills badly. Their nature lacks the capacity for rational action, either through some innate incapacity or an inveterate vice or set of vices. They do not make choices in Rothbard’s sense; they are ruled by their passions or by their instincts. They ought to be enslaved—nowadays, typically, in jails (in New Hampshire, for example, they are employed making license plates with the legend, “Live Free or Die,” which may be considered an attempt at moral instruction on the road to rehabilitation). 

    Rothbard thus bases social life on economic relations; economic relations maximize freedom, largely ignoring the question of whether what I freely choose is good. “The free market is necessarily embedded in a larger free society,” which includes property rights. “the regime of pure liberty…may be described as a society where no ownership titles are ‘distributed,’ where, in short, no man’s property in his person or in tangibles is molested violated, or interfered with by anyone else.” “This means that absolute freedom, in the social sense, can be enjoyed, not only by an isolated Crusoe but by every man in any society, not matter how complex or advanced”—in “a milieu of civilization, harmony, sociability, and enormously greater productivity through exchanges of property with his fellow men.” Rousseau rightly claims that men are born free, and Rothbard adds they “need never be in chains.” This sounds utopian, and it is, as will be seen soon enough.

    “The society of absolute self-ownership for all rests on the primordial fact of natural self-ownership by every man, and on the fact that each man may only live and prosper as he exercises his natural freedom of choice, adopts values, learns how to achieve the, etc.” Any diminution of this freedom “violates his nature,” as the “aggressor interposes violence to thwart the natural course of a man’s freely adopted ideas and values, and…thwart[s] his actions based upon such values.” By valorizing freedom over other dimensions of human nature, Rothbard overlooks that a chosen “value” might be bad—as in Milton’s Satan’s classic formulation, “Evil be thou my good.” There is enough truth in what Rothbard says—to develop virtues, one must exercise and habituate the human soul, strengthening it to freely choose good things—to give it considerable surface plausibility. That is the the only kind of plausibility it has.

    Regarding the cultivation of the outer world, Rothbard takes Locke’s view. I rightly own only so much land as I can mix my labor with. A Columbus could not claim ownership of a continent, even if it had been unoccupied. Neither he nor any other man can create matter; “what he does is to take nature-given matter and transform it by means of his ideas and labor energy.” “There are only two paths for man to acquire property and wealth: production or coercive expropriation.” The way of production is the way of economics; the way of coercion is political and indeed “parasitical.” Once again, Rothbard narrows ‘politics’ to considerations of power and one-way or ‘command’ rule. Aristotle knows better, acknowledging that ruling itself is as much a part of human nature as choice or freedom, and that what in the family he calls ‘marital’ rule, ruling and being ruled reciprocally, very much involves prudential reasoning. So does the parent-child relationship. Rothbard’s formulation enables him to wave politics away as pure evil. To Rothbard, all “political” rule is coercive, all coercion slavery. He reduces the three forms of ruling seen in the household as Aristotle describes it to one, and the worst one at that.

    This gross simplification (mis)informs Rothbard’s conception of criminal law. “A criminal is anyone who initiates violence against another man and his property: anyone who uses the coercive ‘political means’ for the acquisition of goods and services,” a point which he considers as “the very heart of the entire problem of liberty, property, and violence in society.” Any property that has been acquired by means of coercion has been stolen; all property is private, including government property or territory ruled by a sovereign, since “there is no entity called ‘government'” but “only people forming themselves into groups called ‘governments’ and acting in a ‘governmental’ manner.” Any ‘government’ that uses coercion is criminal. ‘Political liberty’ must then be a contradiction in terms. This leads Rothbard to his well-known claim (radicalizing Bastiat) that all taxation is theft. All of this depends upon his false assumption that politics, including some forms of coercion, is unnatural to human beings, an assumption that flows from his mistaken claim a human individual in exercising rational choice can select whatever ‘values’ he wants.

    Such mistakes don’t prevent Rothbard from seeing some things clearly and indeed astutely. For example, when the United States government defeated the Confederacy and ended slavery, Reconstruction or regime change in the former slave states failed because while “the bodies of the oppressed were freed…the property which they had worked and eminently deserved to own, remained in the hands of their former oppressors. With the economic power thus remaining in their hands, the former lords soon found themselves virtual masters once more of what were now free tenants or farm laborers.” Just so: the slaveowners had initiated unjust violence against the slaves; the United States government had employed, but not initiated, violent coercion on the slaveowners’ regime, but their just war to a substantial extent gone to waste because they failed to ‘win the peace’ by respecting the property rights of the slaves, rights exercised when they mixed their labor on the cotton and tobacco fields of the South. Rothbard wisely rejects pacifism, arguing that “defensive violence” may be used, although only “against an actual or directly threatened invasion of a person’s property,” including his life; such a threat may include intimidation (the threat of physical violence) and fraud, which is a form of theft. 

    What coercion may not attempt, in Rothbard’s view, is “mak[ing] people moral by use of legal violence”—as, for example, sumptuary laws. And violence must be (as it is in both just war theory and in most theories of justice generally) proportional to the crime. A storekeeper has no right “to kill a lad as punishment for snatching a piece of his bubble gum.” Rather, “the criminal, or the invader, loses his own right to the extent that he has deprived another man of his.” An eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth, but not a life for an eye or a tooth. You are indeed entitled to ‘take the law into your own hands,’ but the law you wield must be the rational, natural law, not unbridled vengeance. In a “purely free-market society,” one ordinarily need not do so, however, but rather in effect hire others—police, judges—to exact justice on his behalf. Because one isn’t allowed, according to Rothbard, to make people moral coercively, the notion of criminal rehabilitation is off the table. Jails aren’t ‘penitentiaries.’ They may be the sites where some criminals repent, but their repentance and reformation is neither here nor there; only justly proportionate punishment matters. It is of course significant that Rothbard justifies third-party law enforcement and judging as “convenient.” The notion that third-parties acting as police and judges, ‘hired’ not by individuals but by—you may pardon the expression, although Rothbard wouldn’t—political societies might serve to prevent highly prejudicial defense of natural rights.

    Rothbard gets around to the family only midway through the book, admitting that children pose a “difficult case” for his theory. Beginning with “the prenatal child,” he asserts an absolute right to abortion. “Every woman has the absolute right to her own body,” absolute “dominion” over it “and everything within it,” so long as her body isn’t deployed in a way to injure anyone else. But Rothbard includes the fetus (suddenly no longer a “prenatal child”) among those things. This ignores the fundamental distinction between something in a woman’s body because it is part of her body—the organs—or in it because it will soon be integrated into her body—food, drink—and a ‘fetus’ or prenatal child, which is neither one of her organs nor her last meal. “Should the mother decide that she does not want the fetus there any longer, then the fetus becomes a parasitic ‘invader of her person, and the mother has the perfect right to expel this invader from her domain. Abortion should be looked upon, not as ‘murder’ of a living person, but as the expulsion of an unwanted invader from the mother’s body.”

    But why? Only if one’s freely-chosen wants or desires are morally authoritative, dispositive. Rothbard claims that even if the fetus is a human being, no human beings have “the right to to be coercive parasites within the body of an unwilling human host.” Such an argument violates Rothbard’s own principle of proportionality. The parasitism of a human being, or of any being, within a human body would only be capitally punishable if its parasitism demonstrably threatened the life of its host. The parasitism of a prenatal human ordinarily does no such thing.

    Families generally come into Rothbard’s view as property. The mother has “trustee-ownership of her children, an ownership limited only by the illegality of aggressing against their persons and by their absolute right to run away or to leave home at any time.” Parents may “sell their trustee-rights in children to anyone who wished to buy them at any mutually agreed price.” This makes sense—if one ignores the good of the child and the natural rule of parents over children for the good of the children. It exemplifies (to say the least) the narrowly economistic, anarcho-capitalist illusions upon which Rothbard grounds his theory.

    Beyond family life, Rothbardian societies would have no public streets, only privately-owned ones, whose owners could exclude anyone they didn’t want from using them. There can be no libel laws, inasmuch as my knowledge of your shameful conduct is my property, and so may be disseminated by me without restriction. Further, I can blackmail you, if you don’t want me to ‘go public’ with that knowledge, as “both parties benefit from the exchange.”  Similarly, there’s nothing wrong with bribery, except when the service you purchase is one that I have previously contracted with my employer to perform only on the terms my employer and I have agreed upon in our contract of employment. 

    This leads Rothbard to a consideration of political life itself, which he predictably stages as “the State versus Liberty.” Although “the State” does perform “many important and necessary functions, that does not mean that only the State can perform them. It may be that the State can be abolished and other institutions or practices can do them as well or better.” As it stands, the State enjoys a “crucial monopoly,” namely, “control of the use of violence,” including “the all-important power to extract its revenue by coercion.” All other transfers of income are voluntary, by sale or by gift; the state taxes, and “taxation is theft, purely and simply, even though it is theft on a grand and colossal scale which no acknowledged criminals could hope to match.” If the State attempted to operate on the basis of sales and gifts, it would never receive “anything comparable to the current vast revenues” it now exacts.

    Rothbard denies the relevance of political regimes in this matter. Taxation is theft regardless of whether a country is ruled by one, few, or many. Democracies are nothing more than majority tyrannies. “The fact that a majority might support or condone an act of theft does not diminish the criminal essence of the act or its grave injustice,” any more than Jews murdered by their fellow Germans, most of whom had come to support the Nazis, went to the gas chambers voluntarily. Taxation under republican regimes, governed by representative, is even less a matter of consent than under straight majority rule. In fact, voting doesn’t even usually establish majority rule, since voter turnout rarely amounts to a majority of the adult population. If coercion is itself unjust, then political rule of any kind is unjust.

    Here is where Rothbard departs from libertarians, or at least from most libertarians, who understand government as a form of contract. Such libertarians “hold the contract itself to be an absolute, and therefore maintain that any voluntary contract whatever must be legally enforceable in the free society.” But a contract “should only be enforceable when the failure to fulfill it is an implicit theft of property,” that is, “where title to property has already been transferred.” A mere promise to transfer my title of ownership to any alienable form of property that belongs to me is unenforceable by law, although it is usually the moral thing to do. “It is not and cannot be the function of law (i.e., legal violence) in a libertarian system to enforce morality.”

    Further, no one can transfer an unalienable right at all—very much including the natural right of liberty. Therefore, all social contract theories are illegitimate. “Setting aside the historical problem of whether such a social contract ever took place, it should be evident that the social contract, whether it be the Hobbesian surrender of all one’s rights, the Lockean surrender of the right of self-defense, or any other, was a mere promise of future behavior (future will) and in no way surrendered title to alienable property. Certainly no past promise can bind later generations, let alone the actual maker of the promise.” As for unalienable property rights, such as liberty, they are by definition non-transferrable. 

    Here Rothbard misreads Locke. No one who joins a social-contract civil society gives away the right to self-defense. If I am attacked, my attacker puts himself outside of the social contract; I don’t need to call 911. I am entitled to fight back. As for liberty, Locke explicitly argues that he who would deprive me of my liberty could, if he wished, take away my life also. I am therefore entitled to fight assaults on my liberty on the same grounds as I may fight assaults on my life. This is precisely the argument that Rothbard, following Lysander Spooner, aims at all governments. Taxation implies a command enforceable by violence—your money or your life, or more likely your liberty or your life. The same goes for conscription. I should (and in principle do) retain the right to fight back against any act that threatens my life by denying my liberty, including acts by governments. The difference between Rothbard and Locke consists in Locke’s argument for what might be described as primary and secondary levels of consent. In Locke, my explicit or implicit consent to live within a given civil society entails a primary obligation to abide by the terms of its social contract. If I disagree with a given command issued by the government, I am free to resist or to leave. If I resist in ways that conform to the legal terms of the contract, I should not be punished. If I resist in ways that do not so conform, then I have placed myself in a state of war with the society. That works the other way around, too. A government might act in such a way that puts itself at war with its citizens (if it is a republic) or its subjects (if it is ruled by one or a few). That was the argument of the American colonists in declaring their independence from the British regime.

    Rothbard claims that the only reason that governments get away with their criminal activities is through control over education and communications. They control their subjects’ bodies because they control their minds. The State grants money, power and prestige to “intellectuals” who otherwise would find an exceedingly small market for their services. “Thus, the State is a coercive criminal organization that subsists by a regularized large-scale system of taxation-theft, and which gets away with it by engineering the support of the majority (not, again, of everyone) through securing an alliance with a group of opinion-molding intellectuals whom it rewards with a share in its power and pelf.” And the State backs up both its physical coercion and its mind control by asserting sovereignty over territory as well as bodies and minds. Ultimately, only “the force of habit” enables “State rule”—a certain supine acquiescence fortified with fear and propaganda.

    If his is true, what practical options does Rothbard condone? If I really believe that taxation (and/or conscription) is unjust in principle, I could leave the civil society and find myself a spot where the tax cops can’t find me. I could, as Rothbard says, vote for candidates who intend to “reduce or get rid of State power.” I could lie to the State, which Rothbard regards as “morally legitimate.” Or I could refuse to pay taxes or to report for military duty, becoming a conscientious objector. Or, I could engage in violent rebellion, taking care to observe the Rothbardian principle of proportionality. What I cannot do is to receive the benefits of civil society and expect to pay nothing for them.

    Rothbard also faults libertarians for supposing limited government and laissez faire to be possible. This is a “Utopia,” he claims. “Surely the bloody record of States throughout history should have demonstrated that any power, once granted or acquired, will be used and therefore abused. Power corrupts….” For some reason, Rothbard overlooks whether his anarcho-capitalist notion might be at least as utopian. Anticipating this criticism, he cites the example of “non-state institutions,” such as tribal custom, common-law judges and courts, mercantile courts, and admiralty law enforced by shippers. In Ireland before Cromwell, there was no State, only institutions upholding “customary rules were not haphazard or arbitrary, but consciously rooted in natural law, discoverable by man’s reason.” Grant all that and the difficulty remains: What happens when Cromwell arrives? 

     

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    The Names of Jesus

    June 16, 2021 by Will Morrisey

    Alistair Beggs and Sinclair B. Ferguson: Name Above All Names. Wheaton: Crossways, 2013.

     

    This is a devotional tract, not a scholarly tome, one animated by the desire “to think long and lovingly about the Lord Jesus.” It is, however, far from lacking in scholarship, as the authors criticize Christian churches today for preferring “action” or good works to “meditation.” The authors invite Christians to rebalance pious works with thoughtful faith, urging them to begin by considering the several names by which Jesus is called in the Bible, “begin[ning] in Genesis and end[ing] in Revelation.”  The Apostle Paul tells his fellow Christians at Philippi “to live is Christ.” Who is the Christ in whom Christians seek to live? His names provide the best means of approach to His regime.

    The first name of, the first title for, Jesus is “the Seed of Woman.” Beginning, then, in the Book of Genesis: God tells the Serpent that He will put enmity between the Serpent and the woman, between the Serpent’s “seed” or offspring and hers. In arguing with the Serpent, Eve “assessed the significance” of the Tree of Knowledge of Good and Evil “through her eyes rather than through her ears”; that is, “instead of listening to what God said about it, she thought about it only in terms of what she could see on it,” and concluded that its fruit looked good. “She had not grasped the divine principle: believers ‘see’ with their ears, not with their eyes, by listening to God’s Word” and obeying it. God punishes both Serpent and Woman, allowing the Serpent to crush the heel of the woman’s seed and ordaining that the seed of the Woman will crush the head of the Serpent. The seed of the Woman will turn out to be Jesus, harrower of the Serpent’s regime and eventual destroyer of it. The Bible “is a library of books that traces an ages-long cosmic conflict between the two ‘seeds.'” One might add that the conflict may be ‘cosmic’ insofar as it takes place in the cosmos created by God but it is political insofar as it addresses the question, ‘Who rules?’

    The final book of the Bible reveals the end of this conflict. “John sees a great red dragon that devours humanity. This is the ‘ancient serpent, who is called the devil and Satan, the deceiver of the whole world.'” But the dragon is itself defeated and Christ comes to rule a new Heaven and a new Earth—a new cosmos under a renewed divine regime. Prior to this, readers see similar conflicts, such as that between Cain and Abel, wherein “jealousy and murder result as the seed of the Serpent (Cain) seeks to destroy the seed of the woman (Abel),” or in the conflict of what the authors carelessly call “the Jews” and Jesus, leading to His crucifixion. (This is a dangerous formulation and an inaccurate one, inasmuch as it was rather the rabbis of Jerusalem who called for Jesus’ death on the basis of alleged blasphemy, not Jews generally—some of whom were the first followers of Jesus, Himself born of a Jewish woman.) 

    The authors show the link between the Genesis story and the life of Jesus by calling attention to the fact that Jesus never addresses his mother as ‘Mother.’ At the wedding in Cana he calls her “Woman,” and near the end of His life “he says to her, “Woman, behold, your son!” “Eve” means “Woman”; Jesus is identifying her as a ‘type’ of Eve, Himself as the seed Who will crush the head of the Serpent. “Jesus, the last Adam, had to conquer in the context of the chaos the first Adam’s sin had brought into the world,” including the “onslaught of demonic activity in the Nazareth synagogue” and a series of temptations offered by Satan himself. “The reason there is so much demon possession in the time period recorded by the Gospels is not—as is sometimes assumed—that demon possession was commonplace then,” that it was a feature of a particular ‘historical epoch.’ “In fact it was not. Rather, the land then was demon-invaded because the Savior was marching to the victory promised in Genesis 3:15,” and “all hell was let loose in order to withstand him.” This new Adam differed from the old Adam in one crucial respect: “Where Adam conceded victory to Satan, Jesus resisted him. Total obedience to his Father marked the whole course of his life.” Adam disobeyed when it would have been easy to obey; Jesus obeyed an infinitely harder command, the command to go to the Cross.

    More, “when the second Man was brought to the Calvary tree, he faced a reversed mirror image of the first man’s temptation: “an accursed tree” with “repulsive fruit.” “Jesus had NOT to want to eat the fruit of the tree with his whole being, and yet be willing to eat.” In so willing and doing, He “unmasked Satan’s lie” to Eve, that the fruit of the Tree of Knowledge of Good and Evil was harmless, even good. Satan had insinuated that God did not want the good for His creatures, that He wanted to deny them a good thing, despising not loving His creatures. On the contrary, God so loved His world and especially the human beings He made and gave life to in that world that he “sent his only Son to die on the cross in our place and for our sins.” “It is the cross alone that ultimately proves the love of God to us—not the providential circumstances of our lives.” Human beings are not clever rats in a maze seeking a reward at the end; they do seek rewards, not only on earth but in Heaven, but they receive the highest rewards through obedient love for and gratitude to God, rewards they cannot obtain through their own natural capacities.

    All of this was God’s response to the regime change or revolution Satan and his rhetoric effected. “God wanted Adam to exercise his dominion by expanding the garden,” to “‘garden’ the whole earth, for the glory of the heavenly Father.” In failing, Adam, “created to make the dust fruitful…himself became part of the dust.” Upon His resurrection, Mary Magdalene sees him but doesn’t recognize him, “supposing him to be the gardener.” She mistook his identity but not his purpose. “He is the second man, the last Adam, who is now beginning to restore the garden,” re-founding God’s just regime on earth. “In the closing scenes of the Book of Revelation, John saw the new earth coming down from heaven. What did it look like? A garden in which the tree of life stands.”

    As the author of the Book of Revelation, John stands as the Bible’s final prophet. He is not the Bible’s preeminent prophet, however. “Prophet” is another of Jesus’ names or titles, numbering among the three modes in which Jesus is “anointed” or granted full authority by God the Father (the other modes are priest and king). The necessity of anointing Jesus as prophet consists, first, in the fact that “our fallen condition requires us to have Jesus as our prophet,” given the intellectual and spiritual confusion resulting from sin. “Man’s heart and mind are now skewed in the wrong direction,” leading to the ignorance rebuked in the famous phrase, “The fool says in his heart, there is no God.” Absent revelation from ‘outside’ himself, man “turn[s] in upon himself,” producing idols out of his own imagination to worship, or by worshipping nature in the form of pantheism.  “This is why we need a prophet who is able to dethrone our ignorance.” To dispel some of man’s “internal darkness,” man receives enlightenment in the form of revelation by God’s chosen prophets, among whom Jesus is preeminent; that is, “it is only by God’s grace that [man] discovers eventually that there is no intellectual road to God,” by which the authors mean a natural road. Proofs of God’s existence demonstrate probabilities; they are not apodictic. For truthful certainty, only the intervention of the Holy Spirit will produce the needed noēsis.

    The necessity of anointing Jesus as prophet also entails the need to recognize Him as such. “Jesus is not only the revealer,” as other prophets are; “he is the revelation.” None of the other prophets claimed to be the culmination of all previous prophets. All claimed to show the way, the truth, and the light but none claimed to be the way, the truth, and the light. This being so, how shall Jesus’ office both as prophet and prophecy be realized? The authors cite John Calvin: “He received anointing,” Calvin writes, “not only for himself that he might carry out the office of teaching, but for his whole body that the power of the Spirit might be present in the continued preaching of the gospel.” God’s “body” is now His Church or assembly of the faithful. “There is a vast difference between simply conveying information to people, which can be cold and ineffectual, and true preaching and witness”—a “personal, passionate plea” as the Christian scholar John Murray termed it. The passion of Christian speech has nothing to do with libido dominandi or any other human desire; it is rather compassion or agapic love, “genuine empathy.” 

    The letter to the Hebrews explains Jesus’ office as “the Great High Priest.” Christian Hebrews had been disinherited and excommunicated. “No longer did they catch sight of the high priest—the only man who, once a year, on the Day of Atonement, was allowed to enter the sacred room [in the Temple] to seek God’s forgiveness for the people.” Nor could they receive the priest’s blessing, when he emerged from the inner sanctum to assure them of God’s forgiveness. The letter to the Hebrews argues that Christian Hebrews still have a High Priest, greater than any other because He has delivered Christians both from their bondage to Satan and from the wrath of God. Like a priest, He offered an acceptable sacrifice to God, but in this case the sacrifice was Himself, and forgiveness is comprehensive, as “for believers death is no longer the wages of sin but has become the entrance into everlasting life.” Only now, now that “we are delivered from that great fear—the fear of death and judgment—will other fears become trivial.” God’s just anger with His human creatures makes death a thing to be feared because it is the prelude to God’s just punishment for human sin. “By nature”—that is, by human nature as corrupted by sin—we “are under his wrath” and “deserve to be.” Only with Jesus’ self-sacrifice—whereby “the Lord Jesus, as our high priest, went into the holy place, the very presence of the holy God, and there experienced the awful unleashing of divine judgment”—can human beings be spared the just wrath of the Father. Jesus’ agony on the Cross wasn’t only physically torturous but spiritually so. Only “when the resurrected Jesus revealed himself to his disciples” could he address them with the word Shalom, proclaiming, “Now at last you may have peace with God.” 

    This freed Jesus for the unfinished portion of His priestly work, living in spirit among His people, His assembly, continuing to minister to them as their priest. “You don’t come to believe in Jesus Christ until you have heard him. Until then he is simply a character in a book.” As a Christian, you listen to the Word of God in the sense not only of understanding it but of heeding it. With his Word, Jesus “begins a dialogue with the soul” of the faithful. In doing so, he educates His people in the root meaning of the word, leading His people closer to God the Father.

    Jesus’ third and final office is King of kings, Lord of lords. The Kingdom of God “is a central theme in his message.” God’s regime is a monarchy—a good monarchy or kingship, not a bad monarchy or tyranny, to put it in Aristotle’s terms. While a tyrant rules his subjects for his own ‘good,’ at least as he (mis)conceives it, a king rules his subjects for the sake of their own good, rightly understood. Like all regimes, the Kingdom of God has not only a personal, ruling element but a way of life—what the authors, appropriating contemporary lingo, call a “lifestyle.” To learn about their Ruler and the way of life He prescribes for his consenting subjects, a Christian should begin with wonder, asking himself what he can learn from the portion of the Word he is reading. Only then will he open his mind to the Spirit of God, conveyed by God’s Word, deepening his consent to Jesus’ legitimate, just, kingly rule.

    Some of the kings who ruled the Israelites were true kings. Some were tyrants. “But none of the kings fulfill[ed] their expectations; none of them [was] able to bring real salvation.” Hence the Israelites’ yearning for a Messiah. When Jesus entered Jerusalem, “the jurisdictions of Annas and Caiphas the Jewish high priests, and of the Jewish ruling council, and of Pontius Pilate the governor who represented all the might of the Roman Empire,” Jesus did not deny the accusation that He claimed to be King of the Jews. Working in tandem, the high priests and the governor supposed that they had disproved this claim, bringing his ministry to “an ignominious end.” They failed to understand that ignominy in their eyes might be triumph in the eyes of God. His kingship did not put an end to their rule in Jerusalem; it overthrew the far greater tyranny of Satan, Prince of the World, which the Father had allowed as an instrument of punishment for all human sinners—that is, all human beings. In the words of the letter to the Colossians, Jesus “is the image of the invisible God, the firstborn of all creation. For by him all things were created, in heaven and on earth,” including all rulers and their dominions. Moreover, “he is before all things, and in him all things hold together.” “The universe was made by Him, is providentially sustained by Him and is utterly dependent on Him.” This is what such writers as Dante mean to say when they describe agapic love as the bond of the universe. It is why Enlightenment philosophes took Newton’s elucidation of the force of gravity to refute Scripture, although Newton, a firm Christian, thought no such thing. 

    To say, then, that Jesus is Lord isn’t to make “a statement about my attitude to Jesus; it is a statement about who Jesus is.” The Apostle Paul calls him the Kurios, which is the Greek equivalent of the Hebrew Tetragrammaton, YHVH. And “since Jesus is Lord and God, King and Savior, this impacts all of life,” leaving human beings with “no right to develop convictions or practice a lifestyle contrary to my King’s words,” inventing “new views of marriage” or “reengineer[ing] human sexuality.” Human beings are entitled to rule nature, but only on the terms set down by the ruling Creator of nature. 

    Such offices as prophet, priest, and king bring out Jesus’ authority over human beings and indeed all of creation. But God is also a Son, indeed “the Son of Man,” and even a suffering Servant. Jesus rules but also serves. How is this possible?

    The authors begin their explanation of the title, Son of Man, with the Book of Daniel, where the prophet says “there came one like a son of man: and he came to the Ancient of Days and was presented before him,” then given the one kingdom that shall not be destroyed. In the Gospels, the phrase “Son of Man” is used “fifty or so” times, and only by Jesus.

    There are three elements in Daniel’s prophecy. First, there is “a prophecy of the coming reign of God” following a final war between the Kingdom of God and “the powers of darkness.” “The kingdom of God will overwhelm all other kingdoms” and “endure forevermore.” Second, Daniel prophesies “the coming judgment of evil.” Third, “given this background in Daniel 7, there is more to Jesus’ use of the title ‘Son of Man’ than a simple stress on his humanity in distinction from his deity.” The authors observe that this title appears most often in the Book of Ezekial, “in the context of God personally addressing the prophet.” His sonship reflects his subordination. But he isn’t just any subordinate; “he is a faithful man, a real man,” as distinguished from any man called a “son of destruction.” To destroy typically implies insubordination, contradiction of the maker’s design. With respect to Jesus, “the Son can do nothing of his own accord, but only what he sees the Father doing.” To be a Son of Man, then, “means to be made in God’s image and to fulfill the divine destiny that would lead to a world ordered and completed as God’s garden, extending to the ends of the earth.”

    Jesus refers to Himself as the Son of Man in three ways: as the founder of the Kingdom of God; as a sufferer; and as reconqueror of the earth, reestablishing His Kingdom. As founder, He undergoes baptism, indicating that he joins in “fellowship with sinners” in order to redeem them as subjects of the Kingdom; as founder, He undergoes Satan’s temptation to rule the world without suffering crucifixion, becoming the first man to reject one of Satan’s offers, in contrast to Adam; as founder, He proclaimed His Kingdom, calling His people to repentance prior to their entry into that regime; as founder, He showed his ruling power by performing miracles, signs of “the final regeneration and resurrection of the cosmos; and finally, as founder, He teaches His people the way of life that they will undertake as subjects of his regime. As He takes these founding actions, He consistently shows interest in the consent of His people to His rule, his reputation among them, asking Peter, “What are people saying about the Son of Man?”

    To become the Founder by the Father’s authority, the Son of Man must suffer as if He were a sinner. As the prophet Isaiah says of the Messiah, before he is exalted he must endure torture, his face “marred beyond human semblance” (Isaiah 52:14). As Jesus “is covered in our sin, God no longer sees his own reflection in his Son.” To “repair” human sin, the authors write, Jesus “needs to experience this terrible sense of disintegration—to be treated as sin, to bear the curse, to become ‘a worm, and not a man’ in order to bring about a new integration and a new humanity.” Jesus was innocent of the charge of blasphemy brought against Him by the Sanhedrin, innocent of the charge of treason brought against Him by the Romans. “What is the underlying meaning of all this? It is very simple. The crimes are not his.” Human beings are the ones who “have blasphemed against God by making ourselves the center of our world and the lord of our own life. We have committed treason against God’s rightful authority by refusing his will.” Jesus took the punishment for us.

    As the Son of Man, Jesus will reconquer the earth and bring His founding to completion. Having proclaimed the new regime, having suffered for the sake of His subjects, Jesus “has been exalted at the right hand of God and has asked his Father to fulfill his promise.” As Son of man, Jesus “will take the kingdom he has purchased.” “Incarnate in our humanity, he is our representative, mediator, substitute, savior, and king. He leads us to God’s throne in worship.”

    Despite the Gospel emphasis on the humanity, and especially the bodily form of Jesus, it “contains no physical description of Jesus.” The portrait of Him at Gethsemane instead reveals His inner life, “the depths of his humanity in a way we otherwise would never see.” He “expresses himself in ‘loud cries and tears,'”; or, as Thomas More famously remarked, in the whole account of his life He wept several times but never laughed even once, at any time. The description of Jesus as the Man of Sorrows not of laughter points to His task of what theologians (including the authors) call his “substitutionary atonement.” Without understanding that, we will make “the New Testament’s teaching of Christ” “entirely incomprehensible,” at best “a tragedy of misguided heroism.”

    “Somehow in the vastness of the economy of God in eternity, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit entered into a covenant” whereby “the Father would plan salvation, the Son would come to procure it, and the Spirit would be sent to supply it.” Merely to descend from Heaven and live on earth with spiritually deformed human beings was a substantial sacrifice. But knowing what He had come to do, “Jesus [was] almost beside himself with horror.” At the Cross, “the symbolism of his water baptism at Jordan into his people’s sins [would be] fulfilled in the reality of his baptism in blood at Calvary.” If He had not asked the Father to spare Him this torture, “he would have been less than truly human.” Who has not experienced punishment meted out when he has done nothing to deserve it? Jesus, innocent not only of the crimes of which He was accused but of all sin, must taste “the Father’s wrath falling on his holy soul.” Human parents tell children whom they have punished mistakenly, ‘That’s for all the times you disobeyed and got away with it.’ As Son of Man and of God, Jesus never disobeyed at all, and His Father knows it. Nevertheless, both Son and Father go ahead, for the sake of all their other children.

    The authors emphasize this character of Jesus as the sorrowing Son of Man because the Church or assembly inclines to waver “between diminishing the divinity of Jesus and diminishing his humanity.” Since the Enlightenment, “liberalism has diminished Christ’s divinity, and orthodoxy, partly in reaction, has run the risk of diminishing his humanity.” Speaking to the orthodox, they urge that “in our insistence that Jesus is Lord, that he is the divine king—which we unreservedly affirm—we must never fall into the error of having a less than human, or more than human, Christ.” On the contrary, “he is a real man in this real garden among real friends who fail him just when he is facing this real onslaught.” He is about to sacrifice himself for the sake of human beings, but in doing so He is utterly deserted by men; the only one to minister to him is an angel “commissioned from heaven”—a being for whose sake He is not suffering. “It was partly in the light of this intense passion of the Savior that Martin Luther developed his deep concern about the state of the church in his day. It had become materially strong and was awash with its own sense of power, glory, and triumphalism. It had what Luther called a theologia gloriae—a theology of glory, its own glory. What it needed was a theologia crucis—a theology of the cross.” The feel-good Church of today, in the West, amounts to a democratized and lax version of the monarchic theologia gloriae Luther deplored. “Our smiles of superficial triumph repel rather than attract those who are wrestlers” with human troubles. Yes, Christians triumph, “but the prize is waiting on the other side of suffering.” “We all want a Jesus who does all the suffering, don’t we?”

    This is why Jesus’ final title is the Lamb of God. In the Book of Revelation, John sees that the Lion of Judah “conquered by becoming the Lamb of God, who takes away the sins of the world.” The fierce, wrathful God triumphs by making himself into a gentle, self-sacrificing God, shedding His own blood not the blood of others—becoming a ‘Lamb King’ not a ‘Lion King.’ Whereas Jacob had prophesied that “a lion-like figure” would “come through the line of his son Judah” and reign over Israel, the Book of Exodus records a deliverance that “came through the sacrificed Passover Lamb.” The Lamb of God has seven horns and seven eyes: “The horns speak of power and majesty; the eyes remind us that Christ has sent his Holy Spirit into the World, with all of his omniscience, perfect understanding, and wonderful discernment. And the fact that there are seven horns, eyes, and spirits simply expresses numerically the idea of fullness and perfection.” The symbolic numerology continues in Revelation 10, where readers learn that 144,000 will be saved. “There are 144,000 because that is the square of twelve”—twelve symbolizes the twelve tribes of Israel—multiplied by the cube of ten. “It is a kind of ‘perfect number’ of enormous proportions,” signifying that God’s subjects in His Kingdom encompass what John calls “a great multitude that no one could number.” As with all regimes, God’s Kingdom has a purpose: “They shall hunger no more, neither thirst anymore,” and “God will wipe away every tear from their eyes.”  

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Bible Notes

    Shakespearean Philosophy?

    June 9, 2021 by Will Morrisey

    K.J. Spalding: The Philosophy of Shakespeare. Oxford: George Ronald, 1953.

     

    “Shakespeare’s plays seem, at first sight, to reveal a mind remarkable for its imagination than for its logic.” In Spalding’s time, academic philosophy in the Anglophone world had become dominated by logicians, most of them logical positivists. By that standard, Shakespeare hardly qualifies as a philosopher. “Shakespeare may seem at first sight to have few of the characteristics of the philosopher. Yet poets and artists may be philosophers—philosophers at times more sensitive to the truth of things than those who endeavor to express it by reason and argument.” Plato, Lucretius, Dante, Nietzsche: though rare, such philosophers yield nothing in eminence to their more prosaic counterparts. Looking only at Plato, is dialogue not a sort of play? (Plato found a rival in Aristophanes, who recognized a competitor when he saw one.) And are dialogues not arguments? If so, they lend themselves to philosophy at least as readily as a treatise.

    In some respects, Spalding has in mind the idea of the ‘natural philosopher,’ particularly the physician, who seeks not only to diagnose but to cure the patient before him. By his time, what had been called natural philosophy had been in large measure divorced from philosophy, having been reclassified as ‘science’ or knowledge, distinct from ‘philosophy’ or love of wisdom. Logical positivism was in some respects a response to this narrowing of the meaning of philosophy; in that sense, it registered not only a shift in the self-understanding of philosophers but a regime change in the universities in which most philosophers were employed. That is, academic philosophers were practicing politics, some of them without knowing it.

    In Spalding’s, and Shakespeare’s, more capacious understanding of philosophy, the natural philosopher or, more precisely, the political philosopher who inquires into nature, may act as a kind of physician, both diagnostician and even, in rare circumstances, caregiver to patients, although more usually this task will be attempted by a ruler. The patient might be a person or a polity: “Presenting in different plays different maladies of men and of the State, [Shakespeare] likewise presents in them some physician with the task of alleviating or healing them.” This suggests that Shakespeare might partake not only of natural but of political philosophy in the Platonic-Socratic line. “Like the scientist confronted by the Chance of Nature, Shakespeare’s…rational spirit” attempts “rather to resolve his perplexities than to remain their victim.” Spalding treats the plays as a sort of philosophic ascent whereby Shakespeare “came to himself” as a philosopher.

    As in Plato’s Symposium and elsewhere, the ascent originates in a sort of erotic longing. “Love looks and longs for beauty’s immortality.” For Socrates as for Shakespeare, the ladder of ascent goes beyond the natural philosophy of the early philosophers, through the human element of opinion, subjected to logical scrutiny, toward the ideas, beyond material physis. And if “the beauty of a thing of Nature touched the heart of Shakespeare”—as it does in his early poem, Venus and Adonis—”the beauty of a human mind touched it more deeply,” setting him on the trajectory that culminated in The Tempest, in the figure of Prospero. “Mind knows itself and all things; bodies know neither themselves nor other things.” As recorded in Sonnet 69, Shakespeare became intent on “seeing farther than the eye hath shown.”

    In that ascent, however, it is easy to leave the realm of human opinion behind. “Like Nature, man presents a riddle to the mind. Reason looks for the perfection of either, but experience discovers imperfections in both. In this quarrel reason wins the final word,” for “as the scientist looks for a rational order in the seeming disorder of the natural world, so the moral philosopher looks for one in the seemingly disordered and chaotic life of man.” Yet while the some of the interlocutors in Plato’s Republic seek justice and find it ‘in the abstract,’ bringing actual poleis into line with the ‘ideal’ politeia, the ‘city in speech,’ this proves unlikely or impossible. Taking Plato’s point, Aristotle recalls reformers to sobriety, proposing remedies to political problems seen in the light of practical, not theoretical, reasoning. Spalding maintains that his tension between the ‘ideal’ and the ‘real’ gives Shakespearean drama its drama. And for Shakespeare there is an added difficulty. “An Aristotle has the privilege of writing what he thinks. But Shakespeare had need to consider at once his partners, his actors and the pleasure of the public”; he “might find it impracticable to utter truths plain to himself but strange to the multitude, and not less strange, perhaps, to a Kempe or a Burbage.” Spalding has rediscovered the necessity of exoteric writing.

    He begins, therefore, with the plays that consider the question of “social man” and the immediate difficulties of his own country, with its clashes of opinion, its factions.  In his dramas on Henry VI and Richard III, Shakespeare “seems to be studying the social nature of man as revealed in the political chronicles of Halle and Holinshed,” who show “a people that had been for generations in irrational conflict with itself.” From Margaret in 1 Henry VI to the tyrant Richard, rulers love themselves more than their people and seek to bend the law to their wills. The Taming of the Shrew turns a tyrannical woman into a butt of comedy in a battle of the sexes, that primal natural duality, while The Two Gentlemen of Verona sets two friends, one a model of inconstancy, Proteus, against a model of fidelity, Valentine, subjecting the changeling to firm, comic correction. “For a moment Shakespeare seems to smile at a world restored to its reason, and to the peace and beauty natural to it.”

    For a more lasting solution, Shakespeare must turn to politics, particularly to statesmanship. Spalding cites lines from The Taming of the Shrew: 

    Only, good master, while we do admire

    This virtue, and this moral discipline,

    Let’s be no stoics nor no stocks, I pray; 

    Or so devote to Aristotle’s checks

    As Ovid be an outcast quite abjured.”  [I.i.25-28]  ?????

    Spalding remarks, “Ovid united with Aristotle might be a medicine of a kind to keep men close to the world; while Aristotle united with Ovid might possibly keep men virtuous in it.” More, “a man of this temper might presently become a Statesman and, like Aristotle’s ‘Phronimos,’ find in his care for man the natural purpose of his existence.” At a minimum, erotic love is nature’s guarantee of the perpetuation of the human species; in politics, it guarantees the perpetuation of the polity; in the life of the mind, it guarantees the perpetuation of philosophy. Eros is not a noticeable theme among logical positivists; Spalding would recall academic philosophy to self-understanding, or possibly to a new understanding.

    The need to mate Ovidian love with Aristotelian virtue forms the theme of the comic drama of Love’s Labour’s Lost.  There, “Shakespeare seems to be studying with a good deal of humor the laborings of minds capable of giving birth in their time to the politic being he is looking for,” as the king of Navarre sets himself “at war with his own affections” and those of his courtiers by proposing to turn his Court into “a little Academe”—a Platonic school or ‘republic’—consisting of men who will cloister themselves away from worldly desires for three years in an effort to make themselves, if not Philosopher-Kings, at least Scholar-Kings. The arrival of four ladies from the French Court puts a comic stop to their fantasy, and the ensuing drama issues in a reconception of love, now understood not as a fatal temptation to be countered by an austere life devoted to the liberal arts or by the frivolous eroticism for which the French Court was (in)famous, but for an Aristotelian ‘mean’ or center in the practice of love itself. Called back to the responsibilities of Court life after the death of her father, the King, the princess imposes a lighter sentence on the suitors than the Navarrian king had ordained: one year of mourning followed by marriages if the Navarrians behave themselves in the meantime. “By leaving the world these gallants of Navarre were thus to return to it men sobered, constant, of service” both to Navarre and to France. 

    A Midsummer Night’s Dream does not immediately call statesmanship to mind. But Spalding rightly argues that it should. Once again, Shakespeare presents the problem of misplaced loving among rulers—not only among humans by day but among the fairy regime which rules the countryside at night. Fairy King Oberon cures his queen, Titania, of her jealousy with an herbal remedy; among the young aristocrats, the loves of the two young couples are deranged by the same potion, misapplied by Oberon’s mischievous servant, Puck, whose work eventually gets undone by his master. Families being the foundation of polities, in both the human and the fairy regimes right order is restored, showing that it is not only the intensity of eros that can cause disaster but its direction. Moderation, hitting ‘the mean,’ is indispensable, but so the right choice of one’s beloved.

    But “to ‘cleanse the foul body of the infected world,’ dreams must give way to sterner Reality, and a Man take the place of the King of the Fairies as the physician of human disorders.” In Richard II, “England, ‘bound in with the triumphant sea’…has become “‘a drooping country’ with a ‘broken wing.'” A less rationalist version of the Navarrian king, Richard wastes his time in a world of imagination, “charming to poets and ladies” but useless in a statesman. “Divine as Heaven’s gift of a crown may be, it cannot weigh with a man’s own [practical] wisdom in the rule of a people; and a wise man without that gift is of more service to a State than a fool with it.” Such a man is Henry Bolingbroke, “an uncrowned physician of more promise than Richard,” a man ready to act “like the good gardener” who will “laboriously lop ‘superfluous’ branches ‘that bearing boughs may live'”—first of all by disposing of Richard. It remained for his son, Henry V, to exemplify “the reason-serving ‘phronimos’ of Aristotle, “Free from gross passion or of mirth or anger, / Constant in spirit, not swerving with the blood….” Julius Caesar is Henry’s counterpart in ancient Rome, “a man whose practical wisdom had by its sole might combined and sustained the far-flung fabric of a universal empire,” “possess[ing] the distinctive character of Plato’s ‘Philosopher-King’ and of the rational ‘Monarchos’ of Aristotle.” At the same time, his supposed divinity (he was “worshipped by the many”) was pure fantasy, as the assassins’ knives proved. “Sore for his high flight above them, [the conspirators’] eager envy sought to bring the eagle laughably to the ground,” and as they sought so did they find.

    The limitations of human effort, the ungodlike character of men, appears most clearly in Twelfth Night. Here, Shakespeare “seems to be more seriously concerned with a mysterious world ruled neither by man’s wisdom nor Heaven’s Providence, but rather by untutorable Time and Fate and Fortune. The men and women that now appear on his stage are alike inclined to disallow the efficacy of the human will in the affairs of the world.” This time, there is no “resolute ‘physician’ of men,” no wise statesman to save the day, or the regime. “The best Statesmen may be in the sick world of humanity as the best of physicians in an uncontrollable pestilence of nature; and the wise man may look rather to retire from the world, like Jacques, than, like Caesar, to meddle uselessly with it.” Here Hamlet begins, with a prince who cannot decide what to do. Yet Hamlet proves himself “a rare being in the world,” as “men of ‘practical wisdom’ are more often to be found in it than ‘Kings of infinite space'”—self-divinizing, imperial rulers of Rome. 

    Women too can prove themselves to be wise rulers, as seen in All’s Well That Ends Well. In that comedy, an impoverished physician’s daughter first cures a desperately ill king of his physical affliction, then cures the man the king selects for her husband of his folly in rejecting her. She does this not with a love potion devised by her late father but by means of her own smarts, tricking her wayward husband into bed with her and thereby making him see in her a worthy wife—a realization that confirms the king’s authority by vindicating his command. For Shakespeare, the real aristocracy is what Aristotle said it was: the rule of the best, not the rule of the snobs. “Such a will as Helena’s might be conceived to remedy, not alone the ills of lovers, but the wider-spreading evils of a human society, and in Measure for Measure Shakespeare accords to the Statesman the untrammeled powers of will of a Helena.” The statesman in question, the Duke of Vienna, finds himself about to be overwhelmed with the “envy, folly, and mistaken” of the people. Instead of “the swift decision of a Caesar,” Duke Vincentio practices patience, exiling himself from his corrupt city for fourteen years, allowing the corruption to “boil and bubble till it o’errun the stew.” Only then did he intervene to reform Vienna. That this can in fact be done was demonstrated by Charles de Gaulle, who retired from politics in the late 1940s, watched as the Fourth Republic foundered to the point of capsizing, then reappeared in Paris to found the Fifth Republic.

    Patience conspicuously numbers among the Christian virtues, not so much among ‘the ancients,’ although moderation is its foundation. In Christianity itself, the foundation of patience is agape, “man’s forgiving love for man.” If practiced, this would indeed cleanse the foul body of the infected world. The problem is that it isn’t. “In the course of his reflections,” Shakespeare “discovered physicians of differing capacities: some able, who have helped lame men to their feet; others incompetent, who have aggravated rather than allayed their troubles.” Dovelike innocence, love, and patience must be supplemented with serpentine prudence, or all is lost but good intentions, with which the road to Hell is proverbially paved. “Human beings rarely raise themselves by their sole efforts; or become ‘devils to themselves’ without the help of other men.” “Like Socratic ‘midwives,’ such agents may bring to birth in a man beauties as unknown to himself as to his neighbors; or, like evil nurses, deforming passions subversive of the human reason natural and proper to him.” There are Vincentios among us; there are also Iagos. Spalding finds the tragedy of King Lear in his lack of self-knowledge, which issues in rage when his beloved youngest daughter tells him the truth about her love for her, without flattery. In his dying despair before her corpse, “Life showed death’s shining secrets at the last in visions unrevealed to eyes less martyred”—the flicker of life he alone claims to see in her. Insight into a life after death or pitiable illusion? Shakespeare does not tell us, perhaps because he does not know any more than we do.

    Spalding chooses to read it as insight, if not exactly as Christian insight. “Men find themselves, it seems, rather in an immortal world than in the world of mankind; and learn to smile at last only as their hearts break.” “The human world, for reason’s rational foresight, must look a natural Paradise”—as Miranda sees, when she sees men other than her father for the first time. “But unreason, displanting it, may seem at times rather to have made a wild of it.” This notwithstanding, and despite the fact that the “the best of earthly Statesmen may fail of his purposes,” the “purposes of Heaven, and of the ‘mortal officers'” cited in Pericles Prince of Tyre as inspired by the “will” of Heaven, “are not finally to be thwarted.” “The fingers of the powers above do tune / The harmony of this peace.” (Cymbeline V.v.466). Shakespeare has “presented a world which, freed from human tragedy, must find, through Heaven’s directing power, the ultimate felicity Heaven destines for it.” 

    “Yet the reason of the philosopher is not easily satisfied; and the best of answers may provoke at times the worst of questions. Content with his new world, Shakespeare could still continue to question it,” wondering “why its Providence had admitted an evil to cure” in the first place. Here The Tempest‘s Prospero, not Lear or any of the tragic heroes, has the last of Shakespeare’s many words. “It is for man’s ultimate benefit that Heaven has admitted evil into the world. In making ‘uneasy’ man’s attainment of his rational nature evil is destined to reinforce and invigorate it.” Or rather Spalding’s Shakespeare gives himself his last words on the matter in Sonnet 119: 

             O benefit of ill! Now I find true

    That better is by evil still made better;

    And ruin’d love, when it is built anew,

    Grows fairer than at first, more strong, far greater.

          So I return rebuked to my content,

          And gain by ill thrice more than I have spent.

    By “Heaven” does Spalding mean “God”? He leaves that, too, open, following Shakespeare.

    Since Spalding published his study, numerous writers have followed him in scrutinizing Shakespeare philosophically, although they have never dominated academic Shakespeare studies any more than Spalding did in his day. Allan Bloom, Harry V. Jaffa, Paul Cantor, Michael Platt, have all concurred with Seth Benardete’s conviction that Shakespeare could have written philosophic dialogues along the lines of Plato. And that he did, in his own way.

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • 1
    • 2
    • Next Page »