Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for December 2020

    Livy, Teacher of Statesmen

    December 30, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    Livy: The History of Rome. Books I-V. Valerie M. Warrior translation. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 2006,

     

    In retirement at his home in the village of Colombey-les-Deux-Églises, Charles de Gaulle came upon his grandson studying an oration by Cicero. Seeing which one it was, he reached down and placed his large hand over the page, elevated his gaze to the middle distance, and recited the oration to the astonished boy. After completing its peroration, he looked down and said, “You should read Livy. He is much more grand.” 

    In what does the grandeur of Livy consist? Livy writes political history with political intent. He teaches his readers—most immediately Romans in the decades immediately before and after the birth of Christ—what amount to lessons in statesmanship. Philosophy can teach a student how to think logically; religious writings teach piety and right doctrine concerning divine and human conduct. Teaching statesmanship may seem impossible, an attempt to bring the student to a practical reasoning usually inculcated only by experience, that hardest of teachers. Political history enables its students to learn the lessons of experience with a minimum of injury to themselves. It second-handedness may be less vivid than experience but it is also less painful. When the historian recalls the history of one’s own country he additionally appeals to the love of one’s own, while spurring consideration of the lasting geopolitical interests and traditions that must enter into any serious consideration of Roman policy, moving forward. As Livy puts it in his Preface, “it will be a pleasure to have celebrated, to the best of my ability, the memory of the past achievements of the greatest people on earth,” a people now living in a vast empire, “laboring under its own size”—so much so that in “recent times [the Latin phrasing has the double meaning of “revolutionary times”] the might of a most powerful people has long been destroying itself.” Historical narration of Roman events with accompanying portraits of the Roman politicians who spoke and acted in the course of them will enable him, and his readers, “to turn away from the contemplation of the evils that our age has seen for so many years.” Under the watchful eye of the Emperor Augustus, it would not do to suggest that a reader might glean from his book any means to remedy those evils, but the thought does occur.

    Livy is no ‘scientific historian,’ obsessed with separating fact from fiction. But he does want to get at the truth insofar as he can. “The intent is neither to affirm nor refute the traditions that belong to the period before the foundation of the city or the anticipation of its foundation, for these are embellished with poetic tales rather than based on uncorrupted records of historical events.” The ancients made “the beginning of cities more august by mingling human affairs with the divine,” sanctifying the foundings they recall by “reckon[ing] their founders as gods.” “These and similar things, however they will be regarded and judged, I shall not for my own part regard as of great importance.”

    Five things are more important: the kind of lives men lived; what their moral principles were; by what individuals and with what skills Roman dominion was born and grew; how, as discipline collapsed, there was as it were a disintegration of morals; how Roman morals decline, until the present time in which “we can  endure neither our own vices nor their remedies.” That is, Livy undertakes an account of the several Roman regimes, especially the way of life of each regime and its purpose, its principles, and the rulers. He omits mention only the form or institutional structures by which the Romans ruled, perhaps because these were the phenomena Romans struggled over in exhibiting their habits of heart and mind. The “particularly healthy and productive element of history [is] to behold object lessons of every kind of model as though they were displayed as a conspicuous monument.” From such examples “you should choose for yourself and for your state what to imitate and what to avoid as abominable in its origin or as abominable in its outcome,” inasmuch as “there has never been a state that is greater, or more righteous, or richer in good examples,” one in which “greed and luxury migrated so late into the citizens, nor where there has been such great respect for small means and thrift.” Grand indeed, as the founder of France’s Fifth Republic said.

    Livy’s work extended to 142 books, most now lost. The first five books or “pentad” recount the city’s founding in the eighth century BC to its conquest (soon reversed) by the Gauls in 390 BC. The first two books discuss not only the founding but several important regime changes from kingship to aristocracy to tyranny to its overthrow. The third chapter, the central and pivotal chapter, shows the gradual ‘democratization’ of the regime, how the plebeian class gradually came to control some of the key institutions, with the patricians opposing them at every step; the result, a republic or ‘mixed’ regime, survives military challenges from neighboring city-states and continues to see further democratic encroachments on aristocratic authority.

    Livy begins his story with the more-or-less legendary figures of Aeneas and Antenor, who were spared by the Greeks after the conquest of Troy because “they had always advocated peace and the return of Helen” (I.i.5). Antenor settled in the uppermost gulf of the Adriatic Sea, where the people had lost their king at Troy. As for Aeneas, “fate guided him to initiate greater achievements” (I.i.5). In Livy’s hand, even mythological history has value because he can produce lessons for statesmen out of it. Here, two heroes win very different degrees of fame not through virtue alone, not even through virtù alone, but because fate treated them differently. Statesmen must understand that; respect for circumstances is the first thing they need to learn.

    Aeneas and his men went to Macedonia, then to Sicily and then to Laurentum, fifteen miles south of Rome. There they confronted King Latinus and the aborigines, made peace with the king, who gave his daughter in marriage to Aeneas, who became king. The basis of the polis is the family, which is also the basis of the regime of kings. The newly-strengthened polis fought the Rutulians and their king, Turnus, who allied with Etruscans—the rulers of both people worried by the increased power of Laurentum. “Confronted with such a formidable war and the need to win over the minds of the Aborigines, Aeneas called both peoples Latins so that everyone would not only be under the same law, but also the same name. From that time on, the Aborigines’ dedication and loyalty to King Aeneas was no less than those of the Trojans. Aeneas relied on the spirit of these two peoples, who daily became more united” (II.ii.7). Nomos means both ‘name’ and ‘law’; the new king was a statesman who understood that citizenship and law can unite disparate peoples. King Aeneas died after leading the successful defense of the city against the Rutulian-Etruscan alliance.

    Aeneas’ line ruled the polis well for several generations, founding the polis of Alba Longa, until younger brother, Amulius, exiled his older brother, Numitor, the rightful inheritor of the throne. “Violence was more powerful than the father’s wishes or respect for age,” and Amulius used violence thoroughly, murdering his brother’s male children and, “under the pretext of honoring his brother’s daughter Rhea Silvia, selected her to be a priestess of Vesta,” thereby “condemning her to perpetual virginity” (I.iii.9). There would be no one from Numitor’s line to claim the throne Amulius had usurped.

    But again the fates ruled otherwise. “To the fates, as I suppose, was owed the origin of this great city and the beginning of the mightiest empire that is second only to that of the gods” (I.iv.9). “The Vestal was raped and produced twins,” claiming “that Mars was the father of her doubtful offspring, either because she believed this or because it was more honorable to put the blame on a god” (I.iv.9) “But neither gods nor men protected her or her children from the king’s cruelty” (I.iv.9); he commanded that the infants be throne into the River Tiber. Fate or the gods—”some heaven-sent chance” (I.iv.9)—caused the Tiber to overflow, and the lazy executioners of the tyrant’s command left the children on the edge of the tidewater, where Faustulus, master of the royal flock, found them and took them home to his wife. Livy reports the rival stories that the infants were suckled by a she-wolf before their discovery or, perhaps, only by their adoptive mother, “who was called ‘she-wolf’ among the shepherd community, since she had been a prostitute” (I.iv.10). However that may have been, they became hunters as well as farmers and shepherds. “In this way the achieved strength of body and mind” (I.iv.10). Faustulus suspected that the boys were “of royal birth,” having heard that the Amulius had order the exposure of two mail infants just before he found them. Their exiled grandfather, Numitor, took custody of Remus and, observing the “temperament” of both twins,” which was not at all slavelike,” readily entered into a conspiracy with them, now grown, to overthrow the tyrant. Romulus and Remus led separate forces against Amulius; it was Remus who got to the tyrant first, killing him.

    With Numitor restored as the legitimate king of Alba Longa with the support of Romulus, Remus, and the people (“a unanimous shout of assent” [I.vi.12)), the brothers were “seized by a desire to establish a city in the places where they had been exposed and raised,” gathering a group consisting of Albans, Latins, and the native shepherds, all of whom hoped that their new city would soon grow bigger and better than the poleis they had left behind (I.vi12). “But these thoughts were interrupted by the ancestral evil that had beset Numitor and Amulius—desire for the kingship,” that is, a struggle over control of a monarchic regime (I.vi.12). “From quite a harmless beginning, an abominable conflict arose” (I.vi.12); Livy means to impress his reader with the vulnerability of monarchy to tyranny, a lesson that might well be taken by anyone living under the rule of Augustus and the subsequent monarchs of the Roman Empire, many centuries later. 

    In this case, neither contender for the throne could claim legitimacy on the basis of prior birth. “They decided to ask the protecting gods of the area”—every place has a ‘genius’ or ‘genii,’ local deities—to “declare by augury who should give his name to the new city and who should rule over it after its foundation” (I.vi.12). [1]  When the augury proved ambiguous, Remus was either killed in a brawl between his followers and those of Romulus or when Romulus himself killed his brother when Remus jumped over the wall separating his section of the polis, the Aventine, from Romulus’ section, the Palatine. However it happened, it happened in violence, and “Romulus became the sole ruler and the city, so founded, was given its founder’s name” (I.vii.13). Monarchic regimes originate, then, in one of three ways: alliance or consent (Aeneas) or violence (Romulus). They are perpetuated either by legitimate succession (the kings up until Amulius) or violence (Amulius). Either way, they may be decent kingships or indecent tyrannies and, either way, they may or may not win the consent of the few who are rich and/or the many who are poor.

    Romulus solidified his rule by reassuring the people in two ways. He fortified the Palatine, looking after their physical safety, and he sacrificed to the gods and to Hercules, whose legend was associated with the area—attending to the religious concerns of his new subjects. Livy pauses to explain the significance of Hercules to the founding. It was “the only foreign rite undertaken by Romulus” (Hercules having been a Greek) (I.vii.13); according to the local legend, the hero had killed a cattle thief there—that is, someone who had seized Hercules’ property, as Remus had attempted to do to Romulus. Although Hercules was accused of “blatant murder” by the shepherds, Evander, an exile from the Peloponnese whose “wonderful skill with the alphabet, a novelty among men who were untutored in such arts” was “revered” by the shepherds as a consequence, intervened in his defense (I.vii.14). Citing a prediction handed down by his mother, “who was believed to be divine and was admired as a prophetess,” this Evander proclaimed that Hercules was a son of Jupiter and that an altar would be “dedicated to you” here, an altar to be called “the Greatest Altar” by “the race that was destined one day to be the most powerful on earth” (I.vii.14). Hercules shook hands with his new ally, said “he accepted the omen and would fulfill the prophecy by establishing and dedicated an altar” I.vii14) “A fine cow was taken from the herd, and the first sacrifice was made to Hercules,” punisher of cattle thieves (I.vii.14). By so associating Rome, and himself, with Hercules, “Romulus was already honoring the immortality won by valor, an honor to which his own destiny was leading him” (I.vii.15).

    As his final act of establishing his legitimacy, Romulus “made himself venerable by adopting symbols of office,” including royal dress and a retinue of twelve lictors—symbolism backed by force, and the only way “by law that [the Romans] could become a unified community” (I.viii.15). He undertook a building campaign, “more in expectation of a future population than for the number of men they currently had” (I.viii.16). He also had recourse to the myth of autochthony, “long used by founders of cities, who gather a host of shady, low-born people and put out th story that children had been born to them from the earth” (I.viii.16). Rome became a city of asylum; “the entire rabble from the neighboring peoples fled their for refuge,” men and women “without distinction, slaves and freemen alike eager for a fresh start” (I.viii.16). “This was the first move toward beginning the increase of Rome’s might” (I.viii.16). The founder wisely saw that strength is not enough, “add[ing] deliberation to strength” by appointing one hundred men as senator, called patres or fathers, their descendants called patricians (I.viii.16).

    With deliberation comes stratagem. The next move to enhance the population was the famous-notorious ‘rape’ of the Sabine women. “Already Rome was so strong that she was the equal of any of the neighboring states in war,” but this wouldn’t have lasted if the polis lacked a sufficiency of women to produce an equally populous next generation (I.ix.16). Romulus sent embassies to the neighboring tribes, seeking alliance and intermarriage. The envoys told their hosts that poleis, “like everything else, start from the most humble beginnings” (I.ix.16); the Romans were not to be despised. More, “great wealth and a great name are achieved by those cities that are helped by their own valor and the gods”; “the Romans were men like themselves, and so, as neighbors, they should not be reluctant to mingle their blood and stock with them” (I.ix.16). Neither the appeal to piety nor the appeal to common humanity swayed the neighboring peoples, who “fear[ed] for both themselves and their descendants, the great power that was growing in their midst”; to this geopolitical concern they added contempt for the low origins so many of the Romans, deeming them unworthy to wed their daughters. “The young Romans resented this attitude, and things were undoubtedly beginning to look violent” (I.ix.17). 

    Romulus himself had a smarter course to follow. He “hid his resentment” and instead announced a festival in honor of Neptune, patron of horses, inviting the neighbors to attend (I.ix.17). The grand new buildings he had constructed drew a large crowd, animated by their human curiosity; the rapidity of construction had been possible precisely because the Romans had no real household, no families to care for. These peoples included the Sabines, who brought their wives and children to enjoy the holiday. On signal, “the Roman youths rushed in every direction to seize the unmarried women,” with “some exceptionally beautiful girls” seized by plebeians at the command of the senators, for the senators (I.ix.17). The enraged parents could only call down the wrath of the god in whose honor the festival was ostensibly organized. Romulus stepped in, telling the maidens that their parents were to blame, having arrogantly refused intermarriage with Romans and assuring them that they would have all the rights of marriage, a share in the household properties, citizenship in Rome, “and the dearest possession that the human race has—children” (I.ix.18). “They should calm their anger and give their hearts to those to whom chance [!] had given their bodies. For, he said, often affection has eventually come from a sense of injustice. They would find their husbands kinder because each would try not only to fulfill his obligation, but also to make up for he longing for their parents and homeland. the men spoke sweet words to them trying to excuse their action of the grounds of passionate love a plea that is particularly effective where a woman’s heart is concerned.” (I.ix.18). Some time later, Romulus’ wife, Hersilia, would persuade the king to grant amnesty to the women’s parents and “grant them citizenship,” too, “saying that by this means the state would grow in strength and harmony” (I. xi.20). This policy worked because by then Rome had defeated those neighbors who were outraged at the theft of the women, leaving their parents’ spirit “collapsed as a result of the defeat of the others” (I.xi.20). At this point the Sabines themselves attacked but Romulus again led his soldiers effectively and, as the battle intensified, the Sabine women intervened, “their womanish fear overcome by the terrible situation” in which fathers and husbands were killing each other (I.xiii.22). Like so many Helens of the Troy from whose citizens the Roman founders descended, they cried, “We are the cause of war; we are the cause of wounds and deaths to our husbands and our fathers” (l.xiii.22). Unlike Helen, however, they said something effective to halt the war: “Better that we die than live as widows or orphans, without either of you” (I.xiii.22). Their appeal halted the fighting and led to a treaty merging the two peoples into one, with a shared kingship but with Rome as the capital. Romulus honored the women by naming each of the thirty wards he established in the city after the women.

    Romulus’ monarchic counterpart, Tatius, proved unfortunate. Some of his relatives assaulted a group of visiting Laurentine envoys, “who protested under the law of nations” (I.xiv.23). “More influenced by partiality for his relatives and their pleas,” he died at the hands of a mob that surrounded him in Lavinium (I.xiv.23). “Romulus took this less badly than was proper, whether because of the disloyalty that is inherent in shared rule or because he thought that Tatius’ murder was not unjustified” (I.xiv.23). He renewed the pact between Rome and Lavinium “in order to expiate the insults to the envoys and the murder of the king” (I.xiv.23). He went on to win subsequent battles with two attacking Etruscan poleis, Fidenae and Veii. “The strength that he gave to Rome enabled her to have untroubled peace for the next forty years” (I.xv.25). “More popular with the people than with the senators,” he as “above all…dearest to the hearts of the soldiers,” enjoying the protection of 300 armed bodyguards (I.xv.25).

    These men were not unfailing in their vigilance, however. Presiding over an assembly of the people, Romulus disappeared when a thunderstorm “enveloped him in a cloud so dense that it hid him from the view of the people” (I.xvi.25). The people “readily believed the assertion of the senators who had been standing nearby that he had been snatched up on high by the storm”; “stricken with fear as if they had been orphaned,” they all decided that Romulus should be hailed as a god, son of a god, king, and father of the city of Rome” (I.xvi.25-26). Livy raises an eyebrow: “I suppose that there were some, even then, who privately claimed that the king had been torn into pieces by the hands of the senators” (I.xvi.26). This remained the minority view, although the people still longed for a king and disliked the senate. If they did indeed plot the king’s assassination, the senators navigated around that dilemma, as an outright murder would have sparked a popular uprising. A patrician appeased the people by claiming an epiphany: “Today at dawn, Romulus, the father of this city, city descended from the sky and appeared before me. Overcome with fear and awe, I stood there, beseeching him with prayers that it might be permissible for me to gaze on him. But he said, ‘Depart, and proclaim to the Romans that it is the gods’ will that my Rome be the capital of the world. So let them cultivate the art of war; let them know and teach their descendants that no human strength has the power to resist the arms of Rome.'” Livy comments, “It is astonishing what credence was given to this man’s story, and how the longing for Romulus felt by the people and army was alleviated by belief in his immortality” (I.xvi.26-27). By encouraging the people’s pious superstition, ‘the few’ maneuvered themselves into greater authority over ‘the many’ while never assuaging their distrust. 

    “An ambitious struggle for the kingship engaged the minds of the senators” (I.xvii.27); given the newness of Rome’s general population, no prominent men had yet arisen from it, so there could be no competitors for the position from that quarter. “All wanted to be ruled by a king, for they had not yet experienced the sweetness of liberty” (I.xvii.28). The senators split between the “original Romans” and the Sabines, each wanting a king from their group. Deadlock ensued, and for a time they established a power-sharing arrangement whereby the senators divided into groups of ten, with a representative from each group presiding over the government. This aristocracy or oligarchy caused popular “grumbling,” as it seemed that Romans’ servitude “had multiplied,” with rule by “a hundred masters instead of one” (I.xvii.28). If they could not offer a candidate for the monarchy from amongst themselves, surely they could elect one from among the senators. Alarmed, the senators “won the people’s favor by granting them supreme power on such terms that [the senators] gave away no more of their power than they retained”; the people could elect the king but “their choice would only be valid if it was ratified by the senators” (I.xvii.28). “This so pleased the people that they did not want to give the appearance of being outdone in goodwill, and so they merely resolved that the senate should decide who should be king in Rome” (I.xvii.28). Such popular deference to both monarchic and aristocratic rule would endure for a long time. Livy does not neglect to compare the electoral arrangements of early Rome to those of his own time, when the people are allowed to vote for laws and officials but only after the senators have “ratif[ied] the outcome of an election in advance, before the people can vote” (I.xvii.28).

    Eventually, the Sabine Numa Pompilius attained the kingship, a ” great man” “famed for his justice and his sense of obligation to the gods” (I.xviii.28,29). Numa was learned in divine and human law but his virtues were natural; “I think that Numa’s mind and moral principles derived from his own native disposition (I.xviii.28). His elevation to office duly solemnized by an augur, Numa set about “giv[ing] the new city that had been founded by force of arms a new foundation in justice, law, and proper observances,” seeing that “the warlike spirit of his people must be softened by their giving up of arms” (I.xix.29). At the same time, he also saw that such softening, augmented by the peace treaties he signed, would “cause the spirit that had been held in check by military discipline and fear of the enemy [would] become soft from idleness” (I.xix.30). His remedy was “to instill in them a fear of the gods, on the assumption that it would be most effective with a populace that was unskilled and, for those days, primitive” (I.xix.30). “Since he could not get through to their minds without inventing some miraculous story, he pretended that he had nocturnal meetings with the goddess Egeria,” who instructed him on the establishment of divinely-approved rites (I.xix.30). He also established a calendar, the political benefit of which was that it marked out holy days when no public business could be done, “since it was desirable to have times when nothing could be brought before the people” (I.xix.30). Popular religious piety could thus be deployed to limit popular authority. Anticipating that “in a warlike nation there would be more kings like Romulus than like himself,” he also used piety to tame the Romans, establishing permanent priestly offices, including a pontiff to govern the practice of sacred rites, public and private, guarding against the introduction of the foreign religious practices to which frequent military expeditions would expose patricians and plebeians alike (I.xx.31-32). Perhaps as a guard against rapine, he also “chose virgins for the service of Vesta, a priesthood that originated in Alba and was thus associated with the race of Rome’s founder” (I.xx.31); the Vestal virgins, supported by public expense, would enjoy “revered and inviolable status” (I.xx.31).

    Numa’s constitutional lawgiving worked. “Consideration and attention to these matters turned the thoughts of the entire people away from violence and arms. They had something to occupy their minds, and, since the heavenly powers seemed to have an interest in human affairs, the people’s constant preoccupation with the gods had imbued the hearts of all with such piety that the state was governed by regard for good faith and oaths, rather than by fear of punishment under the law” (I.xxi.32). Rome’s neighbors accordingly “came to feel such a respect for the Romans that they considered it sacrilege to do violence to a nation that had so entirely turned to the worship of the gods” (I.xxi.32). This was another reason why peace endured for decades after Romulus’ death. “Thus two successive kings, each in a different way, promoted the state: the one by war, the other by peace,” as “the state was not only strong but moderated by the arts of both war and peace” (I.xxi.33). 

    Livy finds such dualities a core feature of Rome, eventuating in the longstanding tension between patricians and plebeians within the city, warfare with the peoples outside it. The next king, Tullus Hostilius, would confirm Numa’s expectation of Roman kings generally; “even more ferocious than Romulus,” Tullus thought “the state was enfeebled by inaction” and so “looked around for an excuse to stir up war” (I.xxii.33). He maneuvered ambassadors from the nearby Alban people to declare war on Rome. The Alban dictator, Mettius Fufetius, nonetheless offered some prudent advice. “If truth is to be spoken, rather than a show of words, it is a desire for dominion that is goading two related and neighboring peoples to take up arms” (I.xxiii.35). Without “discussing the rights and wrongs of the matter,” Mettius pointed out that both his people and the Romans were surrounded by the Etruscans, whose “strength on the sea is even greater than on land” (I.xxiii.35). If Alba and Rome go to war, the Etruscans will wait until the two nations exhaust themselves, then step in to conquer both. “Since we not content with the certainty of liberty but are casting dice for slavery or dominion, let us find a way whereby it can be determined which side will rule the other, without great loss of life or bloodshed on either side” (I.xxiii.35). They agreed to a solution involving a double duality: two sets of three brothers, the Horatii and the Curiatti, would meet in a combat of champions to settle the conflict. When the Romans won (the surviving Horatian then killing his sister, who dared to mourn her fiancé, a Curiatian he had killed in the fight), Tullus ordered the Alban dictator to keep his men under arms for a war against the Etruscan city of Veii. The Roman people themselves acquitted Horatius of murder when his father intervened, “implor[ing] them not to make him childless” (I.xxvi.40). “The people could not endure either the father’s tears or the courage of the young man who was steadfast in every peril. They acquitted him in admiration more for his valor than for the justness of his cause” in keeping with their warlike character. (I.xxvi.40).

    Pressured by the Alban people, who were “resentful that the dictator had entrusted the fortune of the state to three soldiers” and evidently did not appreciate his larger geostrategic objective, Mettius betrayed Rome within “the guise of the alliance,” stirring up the peoples of the Roman colony Fidenae and the Veientines to attack the Romans and promising he would join them (I.xxvii.41). In fact he planned to hold his troops back, ready to attack whichever side was losing. After winning the battle, Tullus, who had uncovered Mettius’ treachery, punished Mettius but rewarded the Albans, bringing them into Rome and granting citizenship to the people, their leaders to positions in the senate, “mak[ing] one city and one state” (I.xxviii.43). Out of duality, oneness: Mettius, he said, “as you divided your mind between the Fidenates and the Romans, so now you will give your body to be torn apart,” a lesson for “the human race to hold sacred the bonds that have been violated by you” (I.xxxviii.43). This punishment, Livy remarks, itself “ignor[ed] the laws of humanity”; “in other cases, we can boast that no other nation has decreed more humane punishments” (I.xxviii.43). After the Albans were brought to Rome, their city, Alba Longa, was demolished; for the ancient peoples, such a loss was even more catastrophic than it would be for ‘we moderns,’ as every city, and every household within it, harbored the lar and the penates of the people. Tullus spared the public temples of the gods.

    Rome’s population now doubled, Tullus turned his warlike attentions to the Sabines. Rome won again, but Tullus died, after a thirty-two-year reign, “his famed ferocious spirit broken along with his physical health” during a plague (I.xxxi.46). The Romans too had wearied of war, now “want[ing] to return to the situation under Numa, believing that the only help for their sick bodies was to seek favor and pardon from the gods” (I.xxxi.46). They elected, and the senate ratified, Ancus Marcius, grandson of Numa, as their next king. Although “both the citizens who yearned for peace and the neighboring states were led to hope that Ancus would adopt the character and institutions of his grandfather,” the Latins began a series of raids on what they took to be a weakened rival (I.xxxii.47). “Ancus’ disposition was midway between that of Romulus and that of Numa; he was mindful of both. He was convinced that, in his grandfather’s reign, a people that was both young and ferocious had a greater need of peace; but he also believed that the absence of war without being exposed to injustice would not fall as easily to him as it had to Numa. His strength was being tested and, having been tested, was the object of contempt.” (I.xxxii.47). At the same time, he did not want Roman war-making to ignore the gods. “Since Numa had set up religious practices in time of peace, he wanted to hand on a ceremony for war so that wars might not only be waged, but also declared with some kind of ritual,” whereby Rome would first ask restitution from a foreign state for a perceived injury before a formal declaration of war could be issued (I.xxxii.47).

    The Latin aggressors wanted no peace, however, and got none. Rome conquered them and integrated their population into Rome. This demographic shock led to a regime crisis. “The enormous increase in the population of the city resulting in a blurring of the distinction between right and wrong,” the distinction both Numa and his grandson had striven to establish (I.xxxiii.50). The rule of law was undermined, presumably because the size and heterogeneity of the population weakened moral consensus by introducing new and contradictory ways of life to the city while making the old ways of life harder to enforce, given the sheer numbers of persons to govern—Livy himself does not explain. This moral and legal derangement afforded an opportunity to a dangerous foreign man.

    Tarquinius Priscus was the son of an exile from Corinth who had settled in Tarquinii, an Etruscan town located 56 miles north of Rome. Despised as the son of a foreign exile, despite his wealth and the wealth of his wife, he set out for Rome, where Tanaquil “could see her husband in a position of honor,” given the Romans’ condition as “a new people, where nobility was quickly acquired and based on merit,” not birth, as seen in the lives of the Sabine Tatius and Numa the Curiatti (I.xxxiv.52). According to the story Livy relates, as they approached Rome an eagle “came gently down,” removed the cap from Tarquinius’ head, the “deftly replaced the cap on his head, sent, as it were, by the gods for this purpose” (I.xxxiv.52). “Tanaquil, a woman skilled in interpreting prodigies from the sky, as Etruscans generally are,” “embraced her husband” and “told him to expect a high and exalted position” in Rome, the eagle having “performed the auspice around the highest part of a man,” removing the cap “placed on a mortal’s head, only to put it back with divine approval” (I.xxxiv.52). He did indeed rise quickly in Rome, winning the confidence of King Ancus to such an extent that he was named guardian of the king’s children.

    Upon the king’s death, with the sons conveniently dispatched on a hunting expedition, Tarquin seems to have become “the first to canvass votes for the kingship and make a speech that was designed to win over the hearts of the people,” citing the precedents of foreign kings in Rome, his apprenticeship with King Ancus, his familiarity with Roman laws and rites, and his goodwill toward the people—all “claims that were by no means false” (I.xxxv.52-53). Upon election, he took the precaution of adding a hundred members to the senate, effectively packing it with partisans; he then captured a Latin town and inaugurated the Great Games in honor of Jupiter, thus checking the boxes (as it were) of military prowess and piety. He also increased the number of the cavalry, which proved the decisive factor in a rout of the Sabines, who had launched an unprovoked attack on Roman territory. While Numa had counteracted the threat of peacetime softening of the Roman spirit with a spirit of piety, Tarquin preferred to put the people to work, directing the construction of defensive walls in unfortified parts of the city, draining swamps, and constructing sewers. He also built a temple to Jupiter that he had vowed during the Sabine war, far from neglecting respect for the gods even as he busied Romans with these tasks.

    What of an heir to the throne? King Ancus’ sons had by now attained their majority and were “outraged that they had been driven from their father’s throne by their tutor’s deceit and that Rome was ruled by a stranger who was not of neighboring stock, still less Italian” (I.xl.58). Tarquin and Tanaquil had already designated another successor, a child Livy suspects to have been the child of the wife of the king of Corniculum, a Sabine city; Tanaquil had rescued the woman after the city’s capture, befriended her, and raised her son as “a safeguard to our royal house when it is stricken,” attributing a reported miracle attributed to the child as a glimpse into “the will of the gods” (I.xxxix.57). The disinherited sons of Ancus hired two “ferocious shepherds” to assassinate Tarquin, and they succeeded (I.xl.58). Unintimidated, Tanaquil concealed her husband’s death and elevated her now-adopted son, Servius, to the throne, the partisan senate concurring in this without the consent of the people.

    Servius secured popular support and reinforced senatorial approval of his rule by routing the Veientines and other Etruscans. More important in terms of the regime, he formalized the class distinctions in Rome, first instituting the census, then decreeing that “a man’s duties in war and in peace would be determined, not indiscriminately on an individual basis as before, but in proportion to a man’s wealth” (I.xlv.60); that is, the new Roman class system would consist of political distinctions based upon ‘economic’ distinctions. There were six classes in all, with the poorest exempt from the military service that can serve as a pathway to honor. What is more, “now suffrage was no longer given indiscriminately to all,” with the upper classes voting first; since votes were weighted to favor those classes, voting on laws “almost never…descend[ed] as far as the lowest citizens” before a law was enacted (I.xlv.62). Servius further divided the city into four territorial divisions, their inhabitants called “tribes,” probably a derivative of “tribute” because tributes were collected according to one’s place of residence, not class. “The king had promoted the state by enlarging the city and arranging domestic affairs to meet the needs of both war and peace” (I.xlv.64). “Now undoubtedly king de facto, Servius was formally so declared, having “won over the goodwill of the people by dividing the territory captured from the enemy among all the citizens” (I.lvi.65).

    The senate was another matter. Servius had married his two daughters to the sons of his predecessor, Tarquinius Priscus. “It was the women who began all the trouble” (I.xlvi.66), trouble that resulted in “a crime worthy of a Greek tragedy, in order that hatred of kings might hasten the coming of liberty and the last kingship be one that was obtained by a criminal act” (I.xlvi.65). Lucius Tarquinius was spirited and ambitious, Arruns Tarquinius “a young man of a gentle nature” (I.xlvi.65). The women they married were similarly “very different in their characters” (I.xlvi.65), but the gentle wife was married to the ambitious man, the ambitious wife married to the gentle one. The wife of Arruns “turned completely from him to his brother; he was the one she admired, calling him a man and one of true royal blood. She despised her sister, because, as she said, now that the other woman had a real man as a husband, she had lost the boldness that a woman should have. similarity quickly brought the two together, as usually happens since evil is most drawn to evil.” (I.xlvi.65). They murdered their spouses and married; unable to prove that crimes had been committed, “Servius did not prevent the marriage but hardly gave his approval” (I.xlvi.66). Further goaded by his wife, Lucius denounced his father before the senate, pretending that Servius, a man of low origins, hated nobles and had divided Roman land “among the rabble” (I.xlvii.67). Lucius then threw Servius down the steps of the Senate, where the king was murdered by Lucius’ partisans. To complete the enormity, his wife drove her carriage “over her father’s body” (I.xlviii.68). Thus the regime changed from kingship to tyranny.

    Lucius Tarquinius earned the name “Superbus,” for his arrogance. He forbade the burial of his father-in-law, killed the leading supporters of Servius in the senate, surrounded himself with bodyguards to prevent his own assassination, and ruled with neither popular support nor senate approval. “His rule had to be protected by fear, since he had no hope of the citizens’ affections” (I.xlix.69). (Centuries later, that profound student of ancient Rome, Montesquieu, generalized this point, identifying fear as the principle of despotism.) Tarquinius Superbus went on to murder more senators in order to seize their wealth and to “bring more contempt on the senate” (I.xlix.69). “The first of the monarchs to break with the custom of consulting the senate on all matters, a custom handed down by his predecessors,” he sought support instead from the Latin peoples, “in order that assistance from them might give him greater safety among the citizens at home” (I.xlix.69,70). Thus, like many monarchs and especially tyrants, he appealed to ‘the many’ against ‘the few’—in this instance, a people only recently added to the Roman population, thus less tied to the customs and traditions of the original stock. 

    Some of the Latins regarded the tyrant’s overtures with suspicion. Turnus of Aricia warned that Tarquinius “would press them into servitude” if they followed him, treating you as he has treated his own people, with murder and theft (I.l.70). A “rebel and troublemaker” himself, Turnus soon attracted the tyrant’s unfavorable attention. “He began to plot Turnus’ death, so that he might inspire in the Latins the same fear that he had used to oppress the spirit of the citizens back home” (I.l.71). “He trumped up a false charge and so destroyed an innocent man” (I.li.71). This had the desired effect. Out of fear, the Latins acceded in renewing their association with Rome while relinquishing the right to have their own military commanders.

    “Unjust as the monarch was in peacetime, he was not a bad general in war,” Livy concedes (I.liii.73). He waged a successful campaign against the Volsci, initiating a series of conflicts between the two peoples that would continue for the next 200 years. He also took the city of Gabii with “guile and trickery, a thoroughly un-Roman stratagem,” then had his son, Sextus, execute the city’s leaders, some in public and others secretly (I.liv.75). In a show of piety at Rome, he built the temple of Capitoline Jupiter as “a memorial of his reign and of his family” while deconsecrating several sanctuaries and shrines established by the ill-fated Sabine co-king, Tatius (I.lv.75). Portents were interpreted to predict the future greatness of the Roman empire. As for the Roman people themselves, he imitated King Ancus by putting them to work, this time on the sewer system and the seats for the Circus Maximus.

    Conspiracies to overthrow Tarquinius Superbus’ tyranny began to emerge. His two younger sons hoped to exploit an oracle they had been granted at Delphi to eliminate Sextus from the succession. At the same time, Lucius Junius Brutus, the son of their aunt, Tarquinia, bided his time, playing the fool and concealing “the great spirit that was to free the Roman people” (I.lviii.79). Lucius Tarquinius had initiated a war against the Rutulian city of Ardea; it was a wealthy place, and he needed the money to pay for his vast public works and to pay off the increasingly disgruntled people of Rome. “Seized by an evil desire to debauch” Lucretia, the wife of the son of the Ardean king—her beauty and her chastity equally inflamed him—he blackmailed him into committing adultery with him by threatening to kill her and her slave, then laying them together and thereby ruining her reputation (I.lvii.80). After reporting the crime to her father and grandfather, she committed suicide so that no unchaste woman could ever use her example as a precedent.

    This gave Brutus the opening he needed. Swearing vengeance on the Tarquins and the overthrow of the monarchic regime in Rome, he entered into a conspiracy with Lucretius’ widower, Collatinus, and her aggrieved father and grandfather. They gathered an army and moved against Rome, under Brutus’ command. “There he gave a speech that was quite inconsistent with the spirit and disposition that he had feigned up to that day,” he denounced Lucius for his crime and his arrogance in rule, including his policy of near-enslavement of the people for the purpose of building and cleaning sewers and ditches (I.l.ix.82). The tyrant, still in the camp at Ardea, returned to Rome but found the gates closed; he had been exiled by a vote of the people. For his part, Brutus had made the opposite journey, from Rome to Ardea, where he received the enthusiastic support of the army. 

    “The rule of the kings at Rome, from the foundation of the city to its liberation, lasted 244 years” (I.lx.83). It was replaced by the rule of two consuls, the hero-liberators Lucius Junius Brutus and Lucius Tarquinius Collatinus—yet another duality, this one ending Tarquinius Superbus’ malign rule of one. Livy ends Book I here. He has provided his readers with a guide to monarchic statesmanship, both its advantages and its defects. His Book I thus serves as an ‘ancient’ equivalent of Machiavelli’s The Prince, in term of its theme. It stands in strong contrast to Machiavelli’s treatment of monarchy in two ways; although it shares some of the Florentine’s inclination to recommend the use of piety for purposes of ruling unruly peoples, it never departs from the classical virtues; what Machiavelli would term virtù enters in strictly as subordinate to those virtues. More, Livy never suggests that Fortuna can be mastered by human beings. Fortuna, and behind it Fate, put limits on human action in ways Machiavelli denies they need to do.

    In Livy’s presentation, the monarchic regime presents a problem of ‘one versus two.’ As the story of Romulus and Remus demonstrates, a dual regime may lead to fatal inconveniences. However, no one monarch is usually good enough. A people needs two things, not one for good government; it needs both rule by force and rule by law. Yet no one man is likely to be good at both modes of rule; early Rome itself oscillates between forceful and lawful monarchs—Romulus types and Numa types. The attempt to combine the two in one person can as easily result in a tyrant, who combines the two modes malignly—saying in effect, ‘I am the law’—as it does in a wise and just monarch who uses force in accordance with the law. It was exactly this tyrannical eventuality that ruined the monarchic regime in Rome and led to the installation of ‘republicanism’—initially rule of ‘the few.’

    Hence Livy’s opening sentence of Book II. “The libertas of the Roman people, their achievements in peace and war, government by annually elected magistrates, and the rule of laws that overrides the rule of men will be my theme from now on” (II.i.84). Livy carefully counsels his readers that Brutus “would have acted in the worst interests of the state if, in a premature desire for liberty, he had wrested the kingship of any of the earlier kings” (II.i.84). A people consisting of shepherds and refugees would not yet have been prepared for governing themselves. “Released from fear of a king’s power, they would have been buffeted by the storms of tribunician demagogues, creating quarrels with the senators of a city that was not their own, before pledges of a wife and children and love of the very soil—a characteristic that develops over a long period—had created a sense of community” (II.i.84). Factionalism would have destroyed Rome “before it reached maturity.” before it could “bear the good fruits of liberty” (II.i.85).

    The Romans replaced the one king with two consuls. Crucially, the limited the term of the consulship to one year, rather than reducing the power wielded by the new ‘kingly’ offices. Also, only one consul at a time could hold the fasces, the symbol of the power to flog or execute wrongdoers. Quite sensibly, the liberator Brutus was chosen to hold the fasces at first, and he “prov[ed] as keen a guardian of liberty as he had been its champion” (II.i.85). Brutus brought the Senate back up to strength, enrolling leaders of the equestrian class to replace those murdered by the tyrant. If anything, the liberated Romans “went too far in protecting their freedom,” forcing one consul, Tarquinius Collatinus, to abdicate simply because he was a member of the hated Tarquin family, all of whom were then exiled, their lands either distributed to the plebs or consecrated to Mars (II.ii.86). The senators intended this to persuade the plebs to “dismiss forever any hope of peace with the Tarquins” (II.v.89).

    The first threat to the regime came not from them, however, but from young aristocrats, “sons of families of some importance whose pleasures had been less restricted under the monarchy,” having been the “companions” of the Tarquins and “accustomed to living like princes” (II.iii.87). They preferred “license” under tyranny to liberty under republicanism (II.iii.87). Under tyranny, “there was scope for receiving and doing favors,” as monarchs know “the difference between a friend and an enemy” (II.iii.87). “The law, however, was deaf and inexorable, more helpful and better for the weak than for the powerful; it was inflexible and lacking indulgence, if one exceeded the limit” (II,iii.87). For the young aristocrats, “it was dangerous to rely on innocence alone” (II.iii.87). They plotted to restore the monarchy, and two sons of Brutus himself joined in the conspiracy. But a slave overheard their conversation and reported the matter to the consuls, who “crushed the whole plot without any disturbance” (II.iv.88). The traitors were “stripped, scourged, and beheaded”; although the Romans were grieved by the betrayal of Brutus, Romans generally, and the gods by Brutus’ sons, as was Brutus himself (his “face revealed his natural feelings as a father as the state’s retribution was administered”), the informer was rewarded with money, liberation from slavery, and citizenship in Rome, “to provide in all respects an outstanding deterrent to further crimes” (II.v.89-90). 

    “When news of what had happened was reported to Tarquin, he was enraged with not only disappointment at the collapse of his great hopes” (II.vi.90). Conspiracy having failed, “he realized that he had to prepare openly for war” (II.vi.90). He found allies in the Etruscan cities of Veii and Tarquinii—his people, who had suffered defeats at the hands of Rome. “Two armies from the two states followed Tarquin to restore the monarchy and make war on the Romans” (II.vi.91). In the battle, Brutus and Arruns Tarquinius, a son of the former tyrant, rushed at one another, each then mortally wounded. The victorious consul, Publius Valerius, returned to Rome in triumph, but his “popularity turned to hatred and suspicion,” “so fickle are the minds of the mob,” frightened that he secretly aimed at kingship (II.vii.92). It took his resignation from the consulship and a conciliatory speech to the people to assuage their fears; these actions, along with new laws granting the people the right to appeal the decisions of magistrates and “pronouncing a curse on the life and property of a man who plotted to seize the throne,” brought him back into public favor, and he was granted the title “Publicola,” “the People’s Friend” (II.viii.93). This was among the earliest steps of bringing an aristocratic ‘republic’ closer to a mixed-regime republic.

    Tarquin was dead, but the Tarquins still lived. The fled to the city of Clusium, asking the king, Lars Porsenna, to rally to the standard of monarchy against republicanism. “The end was at hand for monarchy, the finest institution known to gods and man,” they argued (II.ix.95). The panicky Roman senators, still unsure that the people would stand firm in defense of the new regime, freed them from taxes and customs duties while assuring them a ready supply of grain and salt. The people, they saw, might incline to either rule by ‘the few’ or rule by ‘the one,’ and their actions secured popular allegiance to themselves against the monarchists. “This liberality on the part of the senators so maintained the harmony of the state in the harsh times of siege and famine that were to come, that the name of ‘king’ was abhorrent to high and low alike. Nor was there any individual in later years whose demagogic skills made him as popular as the senate was at that time because of its good governance.” (II.ix.95).

    In this war, such ardor led to the famed battlefield prodigy of Horatius Cocles, who faced off against the invaders in defense of the bridge across the Tiber River with only two companions at his side. He held out long enough for the bridge to be destroyed, preventing the monarchist army from overrunning Rome. Another hero, Mucius Scaevola, infiltrated the enemy camp in an attempt to assassinate Lars Porsenna; captured and threatened with death by fire, he thrust his own hand into the fire, saying “Look and see how cheaply the body is regarded by those who look to great glory,” and averring that there were hundreds more young Romans just like him (II.xii.99). The intimidated king offered peace, which was accepted. He later persisted in requesting that the Tarquin monarchy be restored, but the Roman envoys explained that “what the king was seeking was contrary to the liberty of the Roman people” and that “they were united in this vow that the end of liberty in the city would be the end of the city” (II.xv.102). 

    To Livy, then, the maintenance of republicanism requires citizen virtue, virtue based on the superiority of the soul, and particularly the spirited aspect of the soul, thumos, over the body and its appetites. A soft people—and not only the men, as he recounts the stories of courageous women, as well—must unhesitatingly risk and even sacrifice their bodies in defense of political liberty. 

    Next to plot against Rome were the Sabines. Although the war faction among its rulers prevailed, there was a substantial peace faction, including one Artus Claudius, who fled the country with his “large band of clients” (II.xvi.102); admitted to Rome, they were granted citizenship there, and Claudius became known as Appius Claudius. The Sabine threat soon induced the senate to appoint a new office, the dictator, selected from the ex-consuls to meet military emergency with a unified command. This quasi-monarchic office struck fear into the plebs and the Sabines alike. Temporarily stripped of the right to appeal from one consul to the other, the plebs saw no other recourse for themselves but the path of “scrupulous obedience” (II.xviii.105). The Sabines took the precaution of forming an alliance with the Latins, who broke their peace treaty with Rome. The indignant and well-disciplined Romans won the war, and the practice of appointing a dictator as the leader in major wars was affirmed.

    The great republican, Publius Valerius died, and his son also died in battle against Latin forces allied with the Tarquins. Tarquinius Superbus himself died in exile in 495 BC. “The senators were cheered by this news, as were the plebs. But the senators indulged too much in their joy. The nobles began to mistreat the plebs, whose interests up to that time they had most diligently served.” (II.xxi.108). Removal of the regime threat and perhaps the increased commerce made possible in peace (the senate dedicated a temple to Mercury, god of commerce, at this time) as it were elevated care for the body. The citizens of ancient Carthage, a commercial republic, were accustomed to prosperity; the citizens of the military republic, and especially its ruling class, may have been corrupted by it, and were in any event made arrogant when fear of losing their regime to rival monarchists abated. A peace treaty with the Latins reinforced this. Roman duality recurred, this time in the form of class struggle.

    From then on, the Roman republic saw “hatred between the senators and plebeians, especially on the question of those who were ‘bound over’ to their creditors for debt (II.xxiii110)—that is, forced into servitude to their creditor until the debt was paid. “The freedom of plebeians,” the plebeians complained, “was safer in war than in peace, amid enemies rather than amid fellow citizens” (II.xxiii.110). Indeed, the threat of war was often the only thing that cut short the periodic plebeian rebellions. And even then, on many occasions, the plebs would simply refuse to enlist when the consuls attempted to raise an army, holding out for concessions even in the face of serious foreign threats.

    Unfortunately for the plebs, what has been conceded can be taken away, once the threat has been removed. It was the former Etruscan Appius Claudius who sided with senate oligarchs, opposing his milder consul counterpart, Publius Servilius, who, in “steering a middle course… neither avoided the hatred of the plebs nor won the goodwill of the senators” (II.xxvii.115). “The latter considered that he was soft and courting popularity, whereas the plebs deemed him equally hateful” (II.xxvii.115). “At last, these consuls who were hated so hated by the plebs went out of office. Servilius had the goodwill of neither side, but Appius was amazingly popular with the senators.” (II.xxvii.116). Out of office, Appius Claudius, “harsh by nature and brutal because of his hatred of the plebs on the one hand and the senators’ adulation on the other, said that such a great uproar had arisen, not because of the plebs’ miserable lives, but because of license: the plebs were more out of control than enraged” (II.xxix.118). He diagnosed the problem as insolence stemming from their right to appeal the decision of one consul before his counterpart, and urged the appointment of a dictator to put a stop to that. He nearly got himself appointed to the office—”a move that would have alienated the plebs at a most dangerous time, since the Volsci, Aequi, and Sabines all happened to take up arms at once” against Rome (II.xxx.119). The senate prudently chose Manlius Valerius, whose brother had proposed the law that gave them the right to appeal; “they had no fear of harsh or arrogant action from that family,” and they went along with the military call-up (II.xxx.119). The resulting army went on to defeat the enemies.

    Victory merely returned the senators to their arrogance. They rejected Valerius’ call for a fair policy respecting credit and debt. “You don’t like it when I urge harmony,” he told them; “you will soon wish, I guarantee, that the Roman plebs had patrons like me”—a moderate, not some demagogue to inflame them against the patricians (II.xxxi.121). Sure enough, the plebs withdrew from the city, fortifying a camp, which caused “great panic” among the oligarchs (II.xxxii.122).

    The senators sent Menenius Agrippa as an emissary to the plebs. “An eloquent man who was dear to the people because he was one of their own by birth,” he brought them back into the city by telling them a parable “in an old-fashioned, rough style of speech” (II.xxxii.122). This was the famous parable of the belly, which recalls a mythical time when the parts of the human body were poorly coordinated, with each having “its own way of thinking and its own voice” (II.xxxii.122). All were angry at the belly, which alone among them appeared to consume without producing. They decided “starve the belly into submission,” but soon learned that the belly had a function after all, which was to supply “all parts of the body the source of our life and strength—our blood, which it apportions to the veins after it is enriched with the food it has digested” (II.xxxii.123). This showed the plebs “the similarity between the internal revolt of the body and the anger of the plebs toward the senators, and so won over men’s minds” (II.xxxii.123). 

    The plebs nonetheless exacted a major concession from the senators. The plebeians were given magistrates “who would be sacrosanct”; the “tribunes” would “have the right to give help to the plebeians in actions against the consuls” (II.xxxiii.123). The tribunate would endure as an important institution in the republic from then on.

    The next threat to plebeian rights came from a young soldier, Gnaeus Marcius, later given the cognomen Coriolanus. His rise, based on his military prowess, began at the same time as the death of Menenius Agrippa, the lifelong “promoter and mediator of civic harmony” between patricians and plebeians. Due to the plebs’ temporary secession, Rome suffered a grain shortage. Coriolanus was “foremost” among those who “thought that the time had come to repress the plebeians and recover the rights that had id been forcibly wrested from the senators as a result of the secession,” describing this as a “humiliation” comparable to that experienced by defeated soldiers forced to pass under the yoke by their triumphant enemies (II.xxxiv.125). The senate, he contended, should “annul the tribunician power” by withholding grain just as the plebs had withheld themselves (II.xxxiv.126). This infuriated the plebs, who intimidated the senators, who then exiled Coriolanus. 

    He settled at Volsci, where his host, Attius Tullius, shared his animosity toward the Roman people. Since the Volscians generally had lost interest in fighting Rome, “they would have to employ devious means in order to provoke the Volscians’ hearts with some fresh anger” (II.xxv.127). At the next session of the Great Games in Rome, Attius warned the Romans of a likely disturbance by Volscian youths; they were expelled, giving him the opportunity to complain, upon their return to Volsci, that the city had been humiliated, its youths treated as if unclean. “War has been declared on you—but those who made the declaration will greatly regret it, if you prove your valor” (II.xxxviii.130). Coriolanus led the march on Rome.

    This led to the dramatic story Shakespeare presented, as the women of Rome, including Coriolanus’ wife and mother, came out of the city to beg for mercy. At first “intransigent,” Coriolanus was intent on attack, but “the weeping of the entire crowd of women and their lament for themselves and their country finally broke the man” (II.xxxix.132). “The men of Rome did not envy the praise won by the women—people at that time did not disparage another’s glory” (II.xxxix.132); Livy marks the magnanimity of early republican Rome, glancing at small-souled contemporaries in passing. Coriolanus lived to an old age. The Volsci and their Aequian allies retreated, then fell to fighting one another after dumping Attius Tullius as their leader. “The good fortune of the Roman people destroyed two armies in a struggle that was as ruinous as it was stubborn” for their enemies (II.xxxix.132).

    Domestic faction re-ignited when the consul Spurius Cassius proposed to divide land gained by treaty from the Hernici between the Latins and the plebeians. The senators were “concerned for the state, thinking by his largesse the consul was building up an influence that endangered freedom”; he might be favoring the people in order to install himself as a king (II.xli.133). “This was the first time that a land bill was proposed, a measure that, from that day to within present memory, has never been brought up without causing great upheavals” (II.xli.133). The other consul, Proculus Verginius, sided with the senators and vetoed the bill. When Cassius then order that money received from the sale of Sicilian grain be allocated to the plebs, they “rejected this as an obvious bribe to get the kingship” (II.xli.134), despite the continued economic depression. Cassius was prosecuted for treason and convicted; his house was demolished.

    During a war with the Aequi and the Veientines, the plebeians, led by the tribune Spurius Licinius, withheld military service, this time “to force a land bill upon the patricians” (II.xliii.136). This caused the consul Quintus Fabius to suffer “considerably more trouble with his fellow citizens than with the enemy” (II.xliii.136). His foot soldiers did report for duty and defeated the enemy but then refused to pursue the fleeing Aequians. “The commander found no remedy for this ruinous and unprecedented behavior”; Livy observes that “men of talent are more often deficient in the skill of governing their fellow citizens than in that of defeating the enemy” (II.xliii.136). 

    The accounts of Coriolanus, Cassius, and Fabius illustrate a weakness of a military republican regime. Powerful in war, its way of life does not foster the kind of souls which readily master the arts of peace—souls inclined to civility, souls that do not carry the passions of war into civil life. In battle-ready Rome, factions inclined to militancy not compromise. 

    And so, in 480 BC, when another tribune, Tiberius Pontificus, sponsored another land bill, the plebs again obstructed a troop levy and the senators again “were thrown into confusion” (II.xliv.137). And again, Appius Claudius was unbending, confident that the senator “would never lack a tribune “who would be willing not only to seek for himself a victory over a colleague but also to ingratiate himself with the better element for the good of the state” by opposing any such proposal by an ambitious tribune who attempted to curry popular favor (II.xliv.137). The same policy of divide-and-conquer that works in foreign policy and war could be applied to domestic policy and faction.

    Rome’s enemies saw the city’s factionalism and attempted to exploit it. Rearming, the Etruscans were “spurred on… by their hope that Rome would be destroyed by her internal strife” (II.xliv.137). “This was the only poison; this was the decay that had been found to work on wealthy states, making great empires subject to mortality,” namely, that “two states had been created from one, each with its own magistrates and its own laws,” making “military discipline” shaky (II.xliv.138). “Under such pressure, Rome could be defeated through her own soldiers. Indeed, all [the Etruscans] had to do was to make a declaration and a show of war. The fates and the gods would automatically do the rest.” (II.xliv.138). Or so the Etruscans hoped, clearly not without reason. The Roman consuls themselves “dreaded nothing except their own forces and military might,” given “this new kind of mutiny when armed men were silent and inactive,” not loud and openly rebellious (II.xv.138). 

    On the battlefield, the Etruscans insulted the Roman soldiers, dividing plebeian hatred between the Etruscan and Roman aristocrats. That is, the attempt to divide and conquer the Romans only succeeded in dividing their outrage, refocusing part of it on the leaders of the enemy troops. Meanwhile, “the consuls put their heads together, as if they were deliberating, and conferred for a long time” (II.xlv.138), effectively employing what we would now call ‘reverse psychology’: “The more [the soldiers] believed the consuls did not want battle, the more their ardor increased” (II.xlv.138). For their part, the Etruscan officers, assuming that the Roman consuls feared engagement, redoubled their insults, thereby redoubling the fury in the ranks of the Romans, who finally “rushed to the consults,” clamoring for battle (II.xlv.138). The consuls still demurred, but finally Fabius demanded that “they swear” not merely to the consuls but to the gods “that they will return victorious from this battle” (II.xlv.138). So they swore, and so they returned, and when the soldiers returned to Rome he put the wounded soldiers under the care of his family, bringing his family to enjoy popularity for the first time, “a favor won by a skill that promoted the health of the state” (II.xlvii.142). The following year, the Fabii volunteered not only to lead the army against the Veientines but to pay for the expedition themselves. “People praised the Fabii to the skies. One family had shouldered the burden of the state.” (II.xlix.143). But success made the Fabii restless; all but one was killed in battle, the survivor “hardly more than a boy” (II.l.146). A year later, however, the arrogance lodged in the other set of heads, and the Veientines fell victim to a disastrous ambush.

    Once again, in the characteristic pattern, peace abroad brought strife at home, as “abundance and idleness again made the Romans irresponsible,” with tribunes “stir[ring] up the plebs with the usual poison, a land bill” (II.lii.148). Between 476 BC and 468, this kind of oscillation continued, with the plebeians winning the right to elect the tribunes through the Tribal Assembly, a move that “deprived the patricians of all their power of using their clients’ votes to elect the tribunes they wanted” (II.lvi.152). “While consuls and tribunes were each pulling in their own direction, there was no strength left in the middle. The state was torn and mangled. The question was in whose hands the state belonged, rather than how it might be safe.” (II.lvii.154). (At one point the Volsci won a rare victory over Rome in battle.) Rome now had a mixed-regime republic of sorts, but without the feature Aristotle regards as indispensable to that regime: a strong middle class to act as a balance-wheel between the many poor and the few rich. 

     

    Note

    1. See Numa Denis Fustel de Coulanges: The Ancient City. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980.

     

    Filed Under: Nations

    Some Thoughts Concerning Christian Liberal Education

    December 23, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    William V. Frame: The Dialogue of Faith and Reason: The Speeches and Papers of William V. Frame. Minneapolis: Lutheran University Press, 2006.

     

    Note: William V. Frame was my academic adviser during my time at Kenyon College, 1969-1973. He taught comparative politics and introduced me to the study of Charles de Gaulle. He eventually chaired the Kenyon Political Science Department before going on to a career in corporate banking. These two paths served him well when he became president of Augsburg College, a Lutheran liberal arts college from 1997 to 2006. His book consists of a carefully arranged sequence of (mostly) speeches to audiences at the College, reflections on the character of Christian liberal education in contemporary America.

     

    Frame situates his talks carefully within the College he governed as its chief executive officer. “Each was intended to draw into view a defining aspect of the college. It was this intention that led me back time and again to the foundings of the college, and then forward to contemplation of its modern mission”— and, it might be added, ‘above’ to its Christian character. With respect to the founding principles of the College’s regime, “during the nine years of my tenure, I became increasingly fascinated with the Reformation itself and the two giants who formed its traditions in Theology and Education—Martin Luther and Philip Melanchthon. The Reformation, he learned, was “modern but alternative to the Enlightenment; Christian but calling us into the world in service; rejecting works righteousness but discovering in unwarranted grace the motive power of our good works; faith-based but intellectually demanding and respectful of human reason.” Such “has been Augsburg’s great gift to me”—most immediately, Augsburg College, more remotely but decisively, Augsburg, Prussia, where Melanchthon wrote the Augsburg Confession in 1530, a document later integrated into the Peace of Augsburg, “the first formal truce in the dispute between the [Roman Catholic] Church and the Protestants.”

    He introduces his book with a speech given near the beginning of his presidency, at the College’s convocation ceremony in September 1997. On that occasion he pointed to the distinctive character of the place: “We have chosen—you and I—the one college in this part of the world”—he means Minneapolis, and he is almost unquestionably right—that “is dedicated to the provision of an education that is both practical and profound; that simultaneously supplies knowledge of the world and self-knowledge; that seeks liberation of the soul from cant of all kinds, both ancient and modern, and cultivates the capacity for obedience to the enduring principles revealed by both reason and faith; that silences our noisy prattle so that we may hear our calling, and returns us the new and literate voice of reflection so that our vocations—all of which will be pursued under the ascendant influence of urban, global and technological forces—are not only gifts to ourselves but serviceable to others and to God as well.” That distinctive character derives from the conjunction of two things: the founding of the College by “people self-consciously free of moral guidance by public opinion or governmental edict who wanted nevertheless to live rightly”; and the founding of the United States of America “by people anxious to give greater—not lesser—sway to the moral and ethical requirements of various faiths” precisely by establishing what Abraham Lincoln called “a system of political institutions, conducing more essentially to the ends of civil and religious liberty than any of which the history of former times tells us.” That is, Augsburg College could be founded and perpetuated within the American regime because that regime afforded political liberty, along with the political means of defending it, to any set of people—in this case, a set of Lutherans from Norway—who consented to rule and to be ruled under the United States Constitution, which instantiated in civil form the laws of Nature and of nature’s God, understood to consist of the unalienable natural rights of life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.

    Without the institutions of the Roman Catholic Church, what would take its place? Luther said, “The fine liberal arts invented and brought to light by learned and outstanding people—even when those people were heathen are serviceable and useful to people in this life.” By “serviceable” Luther mean not ‘pre-professional’ and surely not something conducive to “self-expression or personal success,” but vocational in the Christian sense, attending the ‘calling’ of God in the midst of the world and following it throughout life. “The capacity for reverence is the bedrock of our honor of God and of our respect for human excellence.” “Only a college that puts faith into the crucible with reason and cultivates the capacity for reverence as the foundation stone of humility, can effectively provide the setting in which free men and women can fill the vacuum left by the withdrawal or ejection of officially authorized moral regimen—a vacuum too often filled in our time by the various progeny of nihilism and value-relativism—with a voluntary embrace of the good.”

    In Part One, Frame gets right into the heart of the fundamental question facing any educator in a Christian liberal arts college. Do “the elements of Faith” in his college’s foundations “allow adequate room for Reason” and, complementarily, do “the disciplines of reason demanded by this mission” tolerate faith? Although “I have not and never will succeed,” “I would like to draw every member of the faculty away from partisan commitment either to faith or to reason and toward acknowledgment that the presence of each enhances the reliability of the other.” As Luther and the American Founders both acknowledged, reason and faith differ but they intersect. Luther called them the Kingdom of the Left and the Kingdom of the Right, neither meaningful without the other; the American Founders called them the laws of nature’s God, that is, laws stated in God’s revealed Word but also discoverable by means of human reason—for example, the unalienable rights upheld in the Declaration of Independence. To clarify this, Frame remarks the ‘Socratic turn’. The ’empiricists’ and ‘realists’ of Socrates’ Athens held, with Thrasymachus, that justice is the will of the stronger. They took their bearings from ‘natural philosophy,’ which had discovered a cosmos consisting of matter in motion. In such a cosmos, insofar as beings in it can speak, power is indeed the ultimate reality and ‘justice’ is what the most powerful say it is. Yet one of those powers, the powers of speech, leads the mind that exercises it beyond the empirical, toward the realm of ideas. The existence of varying opinions among speakers brings their opinions into conflict, inasmuch as those opinions contradict one another. In that collision of opposites, that dialectic, the ‘weaker’ argument—the one not propounded by the physically stronger—may overthrow the ‘stronger’ argument. 

    At the same time, Platonic dialogues show Socrates and his interlocutors at times reaching an impasse. There is often a “point at which speech reaches its limit and can go no farther.” “It is at this point that the instructed student can look up and just for a moment glance at the formal notion of beauty or at the formal notion of justice.” This moment of noēsis or insight amounts to little more than a glance, and should therefore implant due modesty in the one who glimpses it. At the same time, that “glimpse leaves an ineradicable mark on the soul, and the possessor of that soul, down through the ages, will burn and reach for confirmation of the truth which it senses beneath the articulate level of knowing.” There may be times, as Luther would be the first to insist, that the Spirit of God amplifies and corrects what dialectical reasoning reckons, and this is where pagans differ from Christians. But the Spirit of God, too, speaks, conveys Logos, respects the principle of non-contradiction which is the core of rational thought. No one can believe a self-contradictory speech, once he perceives the self-contradiction, because such a speech has no meaning in the first place. The Apostle Paul “is responsible for the conclusion that you can’t get faith from reason,” that “faith is a gift, not an achievement.” But that doesn’t make faith logically incoherent, somehow absolving it from the need to meet the criterion of rational truth. In “describ[ing] the Gospel as ‘foolishness’ from the point of view of Reason,” Paul means to say that you can’t reason your way to “the Good News of the Cross,” not that reason is foolishness in the eyes of God. Reason rather needs to understand its limits, as it should when it proceeds dialectically not dogmatically. 

    From his early childhood on an Appalachian farm to adolescence in a small town, to college (where he “led the fraternity chorus, had my own dance band,” and drove a cool car, Frame stumbled into graduate school, where “I encountered for the first time a form of learning that illuminated life,” the life he’d been living thoughtlessly. “I read a Platonic dialogue line by line with a small group of friends—voluntarily, no credit.” He then discovered philosophy as the love of wisdom, an inquiry into “the business of living: Who around us is living the best life? What distinguishes the good life from its alternatives? What is the nature of the noble and the beautiful, and why should we embrace these instead of such attractive alternatives as the powerful, the advantageous, or the pleasant?” He found that “the whole starting point of that great classical inquiry was an act of faith—a conviction, confirmed time and again by the testimony of thoughtful, open-minded, decent people but without demonstrable ‘facts’ or ‘hard’ data—that the universe, nature, made sense.” It was “composed by means of principles which people could grasp, and that those principles were implicit in ideas and ‘values’ as well as material.” What Christianity adds to this is the teaching of Revelation, of the God-given, ‘by-grace’ glimpses of the Person who created nature granted to human beings by that Person, through that Revelation. What Martin Luther “taught me” was that “faith is a form of knowing; that each of us relies on a conviction about the moral structure of life that cannot be vindicated by the facts and data that modern academe in its flight from conclusive recommendation of moral principles, or particular ways of life, depends upon. That Christian faith, as I learned it from Martin Luther, freed me from living rightly at the behest of duty” by seeing that the grace of a loving God absolves us from fulfilling the counsels of perfection that are true but humanly unattainable.

    But what about those who hide not behind moral relativism but behind a moral absolutism that insists on fulfillment in this world, indeed, and very ambitiously, by the whole world? “Each student comes into the college with a whole raft of opinions about the admirable and the objectionable. At the very least, we must ask them to answer a fundamental question: Where does this bunch of opinions come from?” For the most part, they come not from Plato’s Socrates, Aristotle, or Cicero—from the ‘ancients.’ They come from the ‘moderns’ (even when those moderns call themselves ‘post-moderns’). For Machiavelli and Bacon, logic is less a matter of speech, less what Frame calls a “bridge-builder” between the human mind and the nature of which it is a part, as a tool for controlling nature. “‘We are going to know the truth about nature,’ Bacon seems to say, ‘not be communicating with it but by “vexing” it. “We shall poke it with a stick and watch it react.'” The modern mind in principle alienates itself from nature, makes itself foreign from it. “Ultimately, alienation is a phenomenon inside the soul of an individual. As a college in the city, we have a challenge in that we are inviting our students into the midst of modern distraction. If we don’t run this college, so as to break the tyranny of that distraction and open up other realms of thought, we are remiss in our obligations as a college.” Accordingly, “we have declared the city the new field for our mission activity, replacing Madagascar and China and Japan.” The near should replace the far, with “joint and collaborative work” not “directed by a central bureaucracy.”

    Within that uncivil, because modern, city, civility can be made to stand as a Christian virtue. “There are those who believe that our religion is a ‘private’ matter, and that it has nothing to do with politics or economics—except to teach us, perhaps, that the two elements of this world that are truly corrupting—position and wealth—are the hallmarks of politics and economics, respectively.” Indeed, “many of see the act of voting as the key political act, just as we see ‘belief’ as they key element in our religious lives,” as “private in the secretive sense,” nobody’s business but our own. “But we Lutherans are called into the world in service”; Lutherans “have been given a little sliver of the Cross,” a burden, an obligation. To discharge that obligation will require the Christian to disagree with, to contradict, many regnant opinions. “Whoever reaches for a universal ipso facto reaches beyond the political and instantly comes into tension with it,” as Socrates knew before he tried and illustrated thereafter. The language of civility” enables one to do that, without destroying the indispensable bonds of fellowship among citizens in a country that recognizes speech and religion as free by their very nature, stunted if suppressed. “The speech of the city,” civility, “aims at agreement and ‘equity,’ not Truth or God or Perfect Justice. The participant in civil conversation is the citizens, not the philosopher, or the Preacher, or the true Believer.” “Plato knows that the order supplied by the city is the vital condition of the philosophic enterprise.” That enterprise must therefore proceed civilly. So it is with Christianity. “Christian Theology doesn’t appeal to the citizen but to the human being; not to the law but to the Gospel; not to peace but to the Peace that passes all understanding.” In making that appeal, the philosopher and the Christian both necessarily inflect the way of life of the city. The American Founders understood that they could do so in ways that would do well in the city, and for it, but only if neither withdrew from the city nor addressed it uncivilly, with contempt. Civility forms the basis for something even better than itself, friendship, “the human relationship that was crucial to the successful operation of the dialectic for both Socrates himself and for Plato’s Socrates,” along with the fellowship of the religious congregation. 

    What then of the office-holder within a civil society—specifically, the vocation of a president governing a Lutheran liberal arts college?  “There may be other jobs like this, but I’ve never had one of them.” He sought guidance, therefore, not among his contemporaries but among his predecessors. “I, for one, will look for the future of this college among the principles of its founding,” he announced, upon assuming office in October 1997. Those principles “suppose that the human condition is superficially relieved—not fundamentally changed—by the modern techno-mastery of nature or the replacement of national by global societies.” That, it might be noted, will depend upon how far modern techno-mastery of nature goes toward altering human nature, and whether Lutheranism can thrive in “global societies” (whatever they may be) without the protection of the nation-state, upon which it depended for protection from the global (that is to say) Catholic society with which it was surrounded in the sixteenth century.

    For his part, within the circumstances of modern life, Frame worked to strengthen citizenship within Augsburg College itself by “transform[ing] employees into engaged citizens of that polity” and by “deriv[ing] leadership authority entirely from understanding of and commitment to the institutional self-definition” set down by its founders. This definition of the principles of the College’s regime then must be adapted to the immediate and like future circumstances of the College, crystallized in the form of what amounts to a social contract among the several “constituents” of the College, including not only employees but students and alumni, accomplished in a series of committee meetings. Initially, the president can serve as the arbiter among the several constituencies, but crucial to his task is to “a structure of institutional governance,” a “home for lasting leadership.” By these acts he intended to re-connect the people within the College to its original founding principles, after some forty years of responding to such practical necessities as financial solvency and the renovation of its buildings. “Academic leadership is possible only when the academy is founded as a polity, leadership in it is understood as a form of statesmanship, and institutional rehabilitation as an undertaking of citizenship,” citizenship aiming at the Madisonian end of seeking the permanent and aggregate interests of the community rather than the interests of the several groups within it. “The effort to make a polity out of a college is inspired by the Aristotelian (and teleological) proposition that, “Whereas the comes into existence for the sake of mere life, it continues for the sake of the good life.”

    A college requires collegiality, that is, “the key element of social capital—trust.” By this Frame did not mean ‘Trust me’ but ‘I trust you.’ “Here, senior administrators are empowered to act outside the presence and blessing of the CEO”; “they are, after all, employees of the [College] vision not of the CEO, and so they are encouraged to establish their own reputations as leaders. This they cannot do except through the freedom to design the strategies for their particular jurisdictions through which the vision is realized.” As for the president, he “must take them as peers, reserving only two exclusive responsibilities—to relieve them of duty if they dissipate social capital and to maintain the official version of the mission and its reconciliation” with the overall goals of the College in its immediate circumstances. In this way, the way of limited but institutionally well-designed and responsible government, Augsburg College could become a civil association “that Tocqueville thought could restrain the growing epidemic of individualism,” by which he meant the ‘privatization’ of human life under conditions of social egalitarianism. Whereas Luther “intended vocation, especially for the lay professions, to reconnect the individual with society through work,” a Lutheran college in the modern world, now in many respects severed from the “ancient civil ideas at the dawning of the modern moment,” must itself work harder to teach its students but also its faculty and administrators, some of those ideas.

    Here Frame sharply departs from the principles of the American founding. Given the “three critical axioms” supplied by Luther—”that we can do nothing of value by ourselves,” that is, without God’s assistance; “that our redemption by Grace does not erase the limitations of our humanity and so in this world, even Christians remain in need of law and the thrall of reason”; and “that the service we give the world through work in gratitude for our redemption is corrective and is therefore offered in both love and hope for the world”—is, he asserts, “challenged” by “the idea of natural right.” In his estimation, natural right “strained the relationship between citizen and society” by holding that “the individual is shaped by certain natal forces that are prior to and beyond the salutary reach of civil society.” This “leaves us alienated and individualized.” Lutheran vocation specifically and Christian vocation generally “survived the victory of the natural right position largely because that victory was never consolidated,” thanks to the soberer ‘moderns’ (Rousseau, with his critique of Enlightenment rationalism, and the prudent institutionalism of such thinkers as Montesquieu, Tocqueville, and Madison) and also to “the political history of the United Kingdom,” guided as it has mostly been by blunt common sense. Since all of the thinkers he mentions considered political institutions as means of securing natural rights, Frame may mean that the Enlightenment conception of natural right tended toward French-Revolutionary-like dissolution of institutions, the ambition to re-make human societies even as modern science invites us to master nature, by poking it with a stick and watching it react. He may also mean that “nations and communities” “derive their legitimacy, their very identities, from history,” by which he means not the movements of Hegel’s Absolute Spirit but traditions, myths, legends. However this may be, Frame again inclines to overlook the political thing Luther never took for granted, and needed, the thing that stands between the civil association and “global societies”: the nation-state. Given his background in comparative politics, this may strike the reader as especially odd. 

    He himself supplies a corrective for such mis-thinking by considering the tragic story of King Oedipus. “His hubris was the condition of both his intellectual brilliance (he won the presidency by solving the Riddle of the Sphinx) and his radical lack of self-knowing.” From this monitory example he takes three lessons. First, self-knowledge “is not private even though it is exclusive to its owner”; one really does need to listen to the voices in the Chorus, even if determined not to obey them slavishly. Second, self-knowledge, especially in the soul of a king or president, “is constituted in part of learning, and about things that are profoundly public, it is acquired social, not in isolation.” Finally, in its quest for self-knowledge, by that quest, the soul (as it were) emerges as it engages in its vocation. For example, “the vocational president” will need “to be both serious and careful about his or her use of the rhetorical arts; he or she must do as did Churchill—labor incessantly over his impromptu speeches.” A college president is a sort of miner. His work consists of digging into the college over which he presides—not only by learning its founding principles but by studying how it has applied, misapplied, or even at times forgotten or knowingly rejected those principles, failed to live up to them even as it has believed itself to have been surpassing them. Only then can he refine his own vocation.

    What is this talk of vocation, this “life of service”? In Part Three Frame addresses this question, which he regards as “the greatest contribution of the Reformation,” offering “the Faithful a life fully engaged in civil society and yet theologically legitimate,” even as “the individualizing and anti-political propensities of the Enlightenment were beginning their ascendancy.” “Now that the a-social human habits rationalized by the Enlightenment have proven unsatisfying, the idea of vocation is coming into its own,” he hopes.

    Frame found these habits not mitigated but reinforced during his first job in liberal education at Kenyon College, which he doesn’t name but accurately describes as “a ‘highly selective’ liberal arts college in the countryside of the Midwest,” “purposely set well away from the city” by its founder, the marvelously-named Philander Chase, Ohio’s Episcopal Bishop, in 1824. Although Kenyon “introduced me to two of the critical axioms of the teaching vocation: great teachers begin and remain as serious student—of themselves as well as of the world—and learning improves life,” these “did not jell with the outgoing and service-oriented aspects of vocation.” At Kenyon, “most of us on the faculty preferred theoretical or classroom wisdom far above experiential learning.” “we diagnosed in those days; we did not propound therapies to advance civility or improve society,” whereas a city (he next worked at the Newberry Library in Chicago), “compels its aficionados to construct a coherent interactive public life.” 

    In his next career, at the Bank of Chicago, what Frame “wanted most was knowledge of how the commercial republic, so long the subject of my teaching and writing, actually worked.” To his surprise, he found corporate life “far more humane—more candid and encouraging,” than academia and also, “shockingly, full of better-educated people.” “The international division that I joined after banking boot camp had six or seven Ph.D.’s, not counting those in the country-risk and economic-analysis units. More musicians and artists were on my floor than at the entire college. Perhaps most surprising, there was more hunger for serious conversation than among my faculty colleagues.” And more trust. “Contrary to the academic arguments about the role of self-interest in financial transactions, I learned that the only deals that hold together and lead to new interchanges are mutually satisfactory ones. In the corporate world, a trusted colleagues’ word is better than a signature on a legal document.” Such as “the radically social character of [commercial]-corporate life,” where “no transaction was completed” unless “it could be publicly described as meeting the interest [each party to the transaction] held in common.” It was this experience in modern corporate life that prepared his mind for Lutheranism. Trust is a form of faith, and trust implies knowledge of the person trusted. Con artists will be ‘outed.’ His corporate experience “facilitated my fruitful contact with Luther” for Christianity as a faithful vocation, by “forc[ing] me to deny my original academic view that the private realm is the exclusive venue for personal growth.”

    This helps to explain both the strength and the principal weakness in Frame’s analysis. Corporate life has spread itself throughout the world. Far more than socialism, which has repeatedly fallen back on nationalism when crises erupt, it has proved a vehicle for internationalism or ‘globalism.’ At the same time, corporate life is indeed very much like socialism, when seen within the corporate body itself. Its ‘foreign policy’ may be competitive/’capitalistic,’ but its ethos is socialist. It is therefore disappointing but understandable that Frame can write, “One of the needs of society in our time is help in transitioning from national and regional parameters to global ones.” Like many corporate capitalists, he envisions ‘one world’ ruled by—well, he doesn’t come out and say it, but—corporate capitalists. Nation-states will go away. Christian vocation will aim “at the needs, not the preferences, of the world,” eliciting “the whole range of our gifts.” It transpires that both Christians and corporate bankers know better what’s best for us than we do. In Christianity, Jesus understands knowledge in a particular way. His sheep hear his voice because “I know them, and they follow me.” Now, “the distinctive characteristic of a sheepfold is that each of the sheep who constitute it is known. They don’t know; they are known.” Divine knowledge of the sheep “forms the sheep into a Sheepfold,” into the ecclesia, the Church, God’s assembly or regime. This way of rule makes sense in a liberal arts college—its students still young, even if adults. And Christianity of course insists upon the consent of the governed; like the college admissions process, it’s a two-way street. It isn’t clear that corporate bosses will much concern themselves with that. Evidently willing to take this risk, perhaps hoping to mitigate it, Frame set Augsburg College firmly along the path of the ‘internationalists’ mantra, ‘Think globally, act locally,’ with Minneapolis as its locale. There he stood, and he would do not other—at least as long as his presidency would last. This was his vocation, and the vocation he set for his colleagues and students.

    To understand the path of Christian vocation as it relates both to the liberal arts college and the world into which its graduates will venture, Frame points wisely and emphatically to Philip Melanchthon. Melanchthon will help in the task of “get[ting] hold of both the promise and problem of vocation.” As the newly-hired Professor of Greek at Wittenberg University in 1518, just after Luther posted his 95 Theses, Melanchthon taught many courses, including history, medicine political theory, rhetoric, “lov[ing] most of all to move among them at the gathering point, which he called Philosophy—the love of wisdom.” This included theology. His joy in learning and teaching, and his formidable capacity for both, finally earned him the title, Praeceptor of the Germans. His early book, Loci Communes, became “Lutherdom’s bestseller,” second only to Luther’s translation of the Bible into German.

    Melanchthon “blamed the political and moral collapse of Europe, but also the waywardness of the Church, on the decline of the ancient learning.” The Church had misunderstood antiquity, making of it a form of logic-chopping, of sophistry. By reading ancients in the original languages, Melanchthon could “leap over the dark valley of Scholasticism and get directly into conversation with the ancients, and with Aristotle in particular.” The greatest among the ancients, he discovered, did not direct their energies toward verbal deceit; on the contrary, they exemplified “the highest pre-Christian form of vocation.” They suffered two defects. The lived “these model lives of service in the narrow, cohesive, self-sufficient communities which had been stricken by empire, and then by chaos,” namely, the ancient poleis. And they overlooked original sin, “accomplish[ing] their work by means of a high regard for the human potential that was unacceptable to Luther’s and Melanchthon’s notion of fallen humanity,” a regard caused by their “conviction that reason and virtue were natural allies.” In refusing to believe that, Machiavelli was right. Unlike Machiavelli, however, Melanchthon never rejected Christianity on the supposition that it is too unworldly to engage in civil life. He “set out to extract and isolate” the “vaccine” of civility “through scholarship and then infuse it into Christian society through the medium of his students.” “Without civility, vocation would flounder on the selfish propensities of fallen humanity.” Although this by no means diminishes the indispensable character of divine grace, love of one’s neighbor needs the supplement civility provides, simply because the work of the Holy Spirit within us “is regularly frustrated by our egocentrism and our individualism.” This “idea of vocation was the principal contribution of the Reformation to the capacity and willingness of the Christian to love the neighbor as the self,” and the idea “had to be made at home in civil society.” “This is true whether or not the particular civil society in question was overwhelmingly Christian.” Without the “forms and images of virtues,” Melanchthon wrote, “which we follow in all decisions and in our judgments on all matters,” without the “humanity” which “shows the way to live properly and as a citizen,” men “are not very different from beasts.” With Aristotle, Melanchthon affirmed that man is a political animal.  Political philosophy, he wrote, can teach “the precepts for civil life [that] are necessary” for peaceful life with one another in a political community. In Frame’s words, “neither Christ nor the Gospel provide these to us” (Machiavelli’s complaint), but that wasn’t His, or their, purpose. Christ “expounded something else, about the will of god and trust in God, which human reason could not understand.” Aristotle, and behind him Homer, pointed the way to something else, “the sociality that is the bedrock condition of civility.”

    The central chapter of the book describes Melanchthonian civility as “the reconciliation of faith and learning.” Frame’s occasion for writing it was a speech describing the College’s projected Center for Faith and Learning, an institution whose mission it was “to establish a mutually advantageous relationship of faith and learning for application in every discipline in our curriculum and for infusion into our recruiting of students, solicitation of donors, and management of the extra and co-curricular life of the college,” a task which will require the “very development and cultivation of civility in the learning community itself and in the relationship of the college with its neighborhoods, its industry, and its global relations with Church and society.” Just as Melanchthon and Luther together created in the crucible from which the Reformation actually emerged a new political science”—one distinct from the new political science of Machiavelli and Bacon—and “a new theology which widened the availability of the Gospel as a blessing for human life on this side of the grave and for believers as well as strangers,” so too, one infers, the Center was intended to develop a still newer political science, and perhaps a new theology, designed crucially to inflect the emerging “global” society and the corporations likely to guide it. If this came to pass, would Lutheranism do a better job at influencing a world government than it did in influencing the Prussian, and eventually the German state? One can only pray that it would.

    Under the Dark Ages and then Scholasticism, “the disciplined study of literature reduced the quality of Theology,” rather as (one infers) certain late-modern philosophers and ideologues have reduced the quality of theology in the past two centuries or so. The Luther-Melanchthon “reform of both church and education, took form in the heat of the moment—in their joint effort to save and restore the Church and to recover learning from the only civilization that had so far as they knew, properly cultivated Philosophy—the ancients, particularly the Greeks.” Especially (again) political philosophy: from the civic life of the ancients he took what he called the “first law” of any “governing assembly, whether in the state or in the church,” namely, “freedom for those who speak and patience for those who listen.” Melanchthon continued, “How our century is afflicted more than anything else by the fact that the mighty cannot hear free speech, and not even any thought of freedom.” This is where learning intersects with civic life, and with the civil life inside God’s assembly. “Learning is accomplished only in community, by way of what he called ‘disputation’—not in an isolated carrel in a library, but in the classroom and ultimately in the town square.” The “eloquent deliberation” Melanchthon esteemed in the ancients “adds coherence to community be deepening its knowledge of itself.”

    Melanchthon of course sees the danger in such well-turned rhetoric as clearly as the philosophers he studied did. “The liberation of thoughtfulness, armed by high literacy and powerful rhetoric, opens the possibility that the greatest rhetor, rather than the wisest, will wind the day. This danger explains Melanchthon’s very heavy emphasis on moderation.” In his understanding, moderation is a virtue cultivated not only by careful moral habituation of the young but by the intellectual character of dialectics within a Christian framework. That is, if nature, “the essence of creation,” is “a work of mind,” the mind of God, and “therefore accessible to reason,” the capacity to make logical distinctions, then the practice of deliberation in an assembly and the dialectic employed therein must moderate, limit, the power of rhetorical flourishes. In the assembly you get to answer back, not just sit back. To take the most malign ‘German’ example, what Hitler told you was unanswerable, on pain of death. By contrast, “dialectics, and the collateral rhetorical skills on which it depended were, for Melanchthon, instruments designed to keep the ‘fallen’ human mind attentive to nature rather than itself, to keep the disputation focused on the truth rather than on a particular expression of it or on the reputation of the expresser, and to make of the truths so discovered additions to the coherent substance of the community, rather than the exclusive secrets of an elite”—this last phrase a jab at the ‘Straussian’ political scientists who were his colleagues at Kenyon. (He does, however, laud Strauss for his recovery of political philosophy, the philosophizing of Socrates as depicted in the Platonic dialogues and as practiced by Aristotle.)

    In this, Luther remained Melanchthon’s beau ideal of a statesman. The Great Reformer, he wrote, “adorned and defended civic life as it has never been adorned and defended by anyone else’s writings.” Luther “both knew the state and accurately perceived the frame of mind and wishes of all those with whom he lived,” understanding the Christian Church itself as a polity, having “read most avidly ancient and recent ecclesiastical writings and all works of history, relating their examples to the present business with outstanding dexterity.” Contrary to Machiavelli’s complaint about Churchmen, Luther, “said Melanchthon in the funeral oration, did not allow his piety to blind him to human reality.” The result, as Frame puts it, was that “the University, in which Theology and Philosophy meet and mingle, is the training ground of the response to the call, which the reformers named as vocational life.” Machiavelli and the ancients agreed on one thing, that civil life could not be made “dependent on an active, regularly intervening God, and not to forces that were perfected in heaven or some place other than right here.” What Machiavelli rejected, and what the ancients didn’t know, what Luther did know, is that “two kingdoms are better than one.” 

    Why? “What Luther and Melanchthon saw in the contemporary landscape of early sixteenth century Europe was a Church that had ascended from literally nothing to so mighty a position that it had absorbed political as well as religious authority” under the rulership of priests. Their majesty, mystery, and authority simultaneously denatured politics and corrupted religion by reserving political rule to an elite against which there could be no earthly appeal, no ‘back-talk’ or public deliberation, and by polluting the sacred, removing from it the innocence of doves and leaving it only with the prudence of serpents. In opposition to this, Luther and Melanchthon wanted to know what those who receive and keep faith in the Christian God “will do when we get the faith.” They urge that we “feel such gratitude for the unwarranted act of grace which has freed us from the embarrassment of our human limitations that we give up our lives to the service of our neighbor,” to “move forward in faith and into congregation, parish, party and polity.” In this way, both the Kingdom of God and the Kingdom of Man “hold sway, simultaneously, among us.” To argue, as Machiavelli does, that this shared rule fatally bifurcates the human soul, makes it incapable of surviving in this world, the Kingdom of Man, overlooks or despises the fundamental trust upon which all human regimes depend.

    As Providence (or Fortuna?) have it, the state of Minnesota during Frame’s presidency at Augsburg “possessed one the nation’s highest levels of ‘social capital'” or trust. Minnesotans could and did ‘bond’ with one another as a society of “similar or similarly situated people,” presumably a middle-class population with no shortage of ethnic Norwegians. To thrive in an increasingly ‘globalized’ world, in which “the ethnic and socio-economic diversity” of the Minnesota population was set to “expand dramatically,” Minnesotans would also need to enhance their capacity for “bridging,” for “reach[ing] across the boundaries of age, gender and socio-economic status and cultural and religious identity, then to find a joint and public purpose that pulls us together for social action.” To aid in this, the College could admit “emigrés from central Africa,” who are “among the most highly educated representatives of their societies” and ones “quickly absorbed into their new world despite their cultural and religious diversity.” What is more, the College should aim at “reconcil[ing] diversity (understood to include age, experience, cognitive capabilities, gender, sexual orientation”—what might Luther and Melanchthon say to that?—along with “religion, culture, and ethnicity).” Perhaps most immediately, “we need to run this business as a college!” That is, since “the corporate and academic worlds in the United States presently stand in desperate need of each other but remain isolated by a profound mutual distrust,” Augsburg should lead the way in their reconciliation.

    With respect to ‘diversity,’ academe’s much-valorized goal, forever receding, for about half a century now, “I regularly rejected the pluralist approach,” “whereby the community is literally constructed of the differences it includes.” As he learned from Plato, “the unity of a diverse community is created by its ‘one-ness’ rather than its diversity.” That is, “the diverse elements which originally constitute a society issue in a new kind of person, largely by means of a process of interaction with a founding vision or constitutional act,” as in the founding of the United States. (On the basis of natural right, it should be added, contra Frame’s earlier remarks at least as they might be interpreted.) This vision seeks to “narrow the existing gap at Augsburg” between the liberal arts and professional knowledge or ‘expertise,’ between “experiential and theoretic wisdom,” between knowledge gained through action and knowledge gained by observation, and between reason and faith, Athens and Jerusalem—all without denying the distinctions between the elements of those pairings. To bring discrete dimensions of human life closer together is neither to succumb to pluralism or moral relativism, the way of incoherence and ultimately of civil war, nor to mush them together in a Hegelian or Marxist synthesis, the way of modern tyranny or ‘totalitarianism.’

    Neither Hegel nor Marx but Jeremiah serves as a better guide. “As part of his call to the Jews in exile to sop dreaming idly of a return to Jerusalem and start constructing a decent life for themselves among their captors, he forecasts a new Covenant.” Christians see that new Covenant in Jesus’ call “to close the gap that all laws suffer to one degree or another—the gap between behavioral and heartfelt compliance.” In so doing, He “liberated us from our sin” by means of His graceful offer of forgiveness. Our acceptance of that offer does not “extinguish our sin” (“if that were done, we would become gods ourselves, and leave behind our defining humanity”), does what Abraham Lincoln would later imitate in his 1838 Address to the Young Men’s Lyceum of Springfield: maintain that law-abidingness finds indispensable support in the spirit of lawfulness against the “towering genius”/tyrant (Lincoln is likely thinking of Napoleon, then dead only 23 years). Just as Lincoln called that spirit, that “reverence for the laws,” the “political religion” of the American nation, so did Jesus demand that reverence for God’s laws, founded in reverence for God, animate the new polity, the new assembly or ‘church,’ the new regime consisting of reverent Jews and Gentiles alike. Does Lincoln “not illustrate by the clarity of his effort, the direction to which we are called by the Reformation?” A direction taken “in the name of a profound freedom accomplished not alone by the order sanctified by Washington and the Patriots of `76, but by that more complete freedom provided by the Gospel.” 

    Both the Declaration of Independence according to the Spirit of `76 and the Gospels place equality into the forefront of human deliberation, of human politics. Tocqueville saw this clearly, recognizing the importance of both the Christian equality of human souls before God and the natural equality of human souls as members of the same species, not to be separated by racial or class distinctions that treated any person as subhuman. But neither for Jesus nor for the American Founders, Lincoln, or Tocqueville did equality mean similarity. Indeed, “to the degree that equality amounts to similarity it is not satisfying,” failing as it does to give play to human excellence. Augsburg College, “for example, doesn’t want to be or feel equal” in that sense; it intends “to be outstanding, and to be recognized as such in the world.” How else could it participate in any degree to guiding the world? “All of us have been given but one Christ. But each of us has been given that Christ!” Such equality “does not bring God to our side, but more precisely it brings Him to each of us,” freeing us “to do and be our best,” opening “for our individualism a way to do God’s work” in the Kingdom of Man, which after all belongs to Him as much as the Kingdom of Heaven. And to do that work “in an outstanding way.”

    It is hard to resist the conclusion that William V. Frame did his work at Augsburg College in an outstanding way. His concessions to some elements of the regnant niaiseries of ‘diversity’ might well have been intended as politic accommodations carried to an impolitic extent. His eagerness to partner with international business corporations hoping to bring about some sort of ‘globalism’ or world government was likely ill-judged. But it is hard to doubt that his own governance of the College was anything but a blessing to it, an elevation and enrichment of it.

     

     

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Bible Notes

    The ‘Young Strauss’: A Critique from the ‘Left’

    December 16, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    Bruno Quélennec: Retour dans la caverne: Philosophie, politique et religion chez le jeune Leo Strauss. Paris: Hermann Éditeurs, 2018.

     

    Admired and decried in his adopted American home, Leo Strauss has enjoyed a more favorable reception in France, thanks in large measure to the kind and perspicacious Pierre Manent, who shares Strauss’ intention of defending natural right against its enemies, ‘modern’ and ‘postmodern.’ Bruno Quélennec enters the fray as a critic of Strauss from the ‘Left,’ but does so much more intelligently than North American Leftists have done, attempting to understand Strauss’s though in its own terms before condemning it in the name of egalitarianism and democracy.

    As Quélennec explains, in the past several decades Strauss has been (mis)understood as the progenitor of ‘neo-conservativism,’ despite his near-total avoidance of American political debates; illiberal, authoritarian-to-fascistic, and (most wildly) ‘La Rouchite,’ the Strauss depicted by the American Left was a very bad sort, indeed, somehow responsible for enormities ranging from Goldwaterism to the Second Gulf War. Central to this argument is a 1933 letter Strauss wrote to a friend in which he called for a sort of Unpopular Front consisting of the several right-wing Continental European regimes, including Mussolini’s Italy, to array itself against Nazi Germany. Having despaired of liberal democracy—already ruined in Germany, tottering in France—and shrinking from the Leninist-Stalinist regime in Russia, which he had rightly identified as malevolent the moment it appeared, Strauss shared with Winston Churchill the soon-to-be-disappointed hope that the ‘old’ Right might stand up and contain its radical challenger. From the Stalinists of the 1930s to the resolutely egalitarian ‘postmodernists’ of today, the Left is not amused.

    Quélennec examines Strauss’s writings before and after the Nazi revolution, focusing particularly on his critique of the political philosophy of the Enlightenment, “modern liberalism.” In the decade before 1933, Strauss saw the liberalism of Germany’s Weimar Republic in crisis, challenged both philosophically by critics of the Enlightenment thought upon which it was based and practically by the ideological Jew-hatred which set itself against the “liberal model of German-Jewish emancipation.” to do this, Quélennec begins with an incisive account of that model and of the Enlightenment thought behind it, as understood by prominent Jewish intellectuals of the time criticized by Strauss, particularly Julius Guttmann, Herman Cohen, and Franz Rosenzweig. Quélennec rightly understands Strauss not as an ideologist bending philosophy to political ends but rather as a thinker engaged first of all in the thought of his times in order to study its philosophic underpinnings, and only then to “return to the Cave” (Plato’s familiar image of life in the political community”) in order to defend the possibility of the philosophic way of life in that constrained, dimly-lit circumstance. Quélennec provides “a sort of map” of the German-Jewish regions within that cave, first of all in the pre-republican German regimes between 1780 and 1918. In the early decades of that period, German Jews were excluded or ‘ghettoized’ economically, socially, and politically; emancipation was intended to make “morally corrupt” (allegedly usurious and religiously prejudiced) Jews better, that is, more like German Christians. Jews were expected to ‘assimilate’ with Germans, free themselves from Jewishness.

    Many Germans were having none of this. Modern anti-Semitism arose, often led by ‘Left’ Hegelians (eventually including Karl Marx, no Aryan), who associated Jews with capitalism, but more usually by nationalists, who especially detested Jews from eastern Europe who had fled pogroms in Russia and Ukraine. Whereas the old Jew-hatred bespoke religious bigotry, the new Jew-hatred registered racial prejudice (animated by ‘race science’) and a sort of democracy (resentment of Jewish ‘elites’ in finance and commerce). The more assimilation progressed, the more virulent anti-Semitism became, leading to controversy among German Jewish intellectuals in the years prior to the First World War. One response, political Zionism, judged European anti-Semitism “incurable”; in his 1882 book, Autoemancipation, Leon Pinsker maintained that “liberalism could not fulfill its promises of liberty and equality,” that Jewish must establish their own national state on some other continent. Political Zionism’s leading thinkers, Theodor Herzl and Max Nordau, argued respectively for a “statist Zionism” (secular, nationalist, anti-socialist) and a “muscular Zionism” (anti-liberal, anti-progressive, anti-bourgeois). Another response, cultural Zionism, founded by Ahad Hasam and propound famously by Martin Buber, regarded political Zionism as unrealistic and rejected nationalism in favor of “a universalist and pacifist ethic.”

    Neither political nor cultural Zionism could stop Jew-hatred, which increased during the war and found an early, murderous expression in the 1922 assassination of Walter Rathenau, the German-Jewish Foreign Affairs minister of the Weimar Republic. At the same time, Weimar saw a “Jewish Renaissance,” a “return to the Jewish religion” led by Cohen and Rosenzweig. Both men attempted to resolve the ‘Jewish problem’ with grand philosophic syntheses. The neo-Kantian Cohen combined the “prophetic ethic” of the Bible with Enlightenment themes, all to be safeguarded by democratic socialism within the Jewish community (he was a firm anti-statist). Rosenzweig, also a neo-Kantian, came down on the “liberal-imperialist” side of modern politics, although his ‘imperialism’ was entirely pacifistic and anti-statist, consisting of a belief in the evolution of all European nations toward peace and equality, an evolution to be spurred by the unification of Germans throughout Europe, who would thereby establish a benign hegemony over the Continent. He saw the Great War rather a Woodrow Wilson did: the harbinger of the Kantian version of the end of History, resulting in a League of Nations (to be dominated by Germans, not Anglo-Americans) whose members would make war against one another no more. With the German defeat, the undaunted Rosenzweig formulated a “new synthesis,” this one combining the high-enlightenment rationalism of Kantian and Hegelian ‘idealism’ with a ‘subjectivist’ or ‘perspectivist’ theology: “They complement one another, Rosenzweig averred. This time, not Germany but the Jewish nation would serve as the catalyst for change, as its longtime statelessness provided a model for the world’s peaceful future. In sum, both Cohen and Rosenzweig affirmed Jewish “self-emancipation, but [in] a religious, not Zionist form.

    At these new forms of messianic utopianism the young Strauss raised a skeptical eyebrow above a cold, clear eye. In what would become characteristic of his thought throughout his life, Straus spurned attempts at combining opposites in grand syntheses; he ‘divided the house’ between national/secular Jews and universalist/religious Jews, between “radical atheism” and “religious orthodoxy.” He sided with Ze’ev Jabotinsky, founder of Revisionist Zionism, a political realist with no patience for utopianism who advocated Jewish national unity, corporatism, military discipline, the rapid colonization of Palestine, and a sharp rejection of Orthodox Judaism as quietist, subservient to the despots of eastern Europe. Resolutely tough-minded when thinking of practical politics, Strauss praised Theodor Herzl for his clear-eyed geopolitical realism and did not hesitate to propose an alliance of Zionism with neither Orthodox Jewry nor Italian fascism but with German liberals, who equally rejected submission to the divine Law while advancing religious freedom.

    This notwithstanding, Strauss interested himself much less in the practical side of Zionism as in Zionism as an instance of the “theologico-political problem”—that is, in Zionism’s theoretical implications. He expressed this problem in a paradox: there could be no Jewish nationalism without the (atheist) Enlightenment which—in its non-universalist form—valorized nationalism over the universalism of the revealed religions; however, without religion, there can be no Jewish people, ‘Semitism’ (and therefore anti-Semitism) being an excrescence of pseudo-science. Therefore, one must choose, and Strauss chose political Zionism, calling for “a strictly atheist and Zionist appropriation of the biblical text.” The liberalism, humanitarianism, and assimilationism of Enlightenment emancipation—that is, the universalist form of Enlightenment—had proved a weak reed, as had the German state which was supposed to guarantee it. Jews must face facts, abandon their utopian-socialist illusions whether purely secularist or ‘synthetic,’ understanding that they are not now and never will be Germans; in this, the anti-Semites are right, even if their malevolence i wrong; political societies are by nature exclusive, limited to the like-minded. Jews and Germans are not like-minded; absent thorough assimilation, they must separate. Quélennec objects, arguing that given the pogroms of 1922-24, any call upon German Jews to abandon their historical rights to German citizenship was “absurd.” But of course Strauss wasn’t calling upon Jews to abandon their rights; he called upon them to go someplace where they could secure them.

    Be this as it may, one cannot read Straus’s writings of the 1920s without recognizing how Zionism spurs his mind to thought much more than to action. “The central opposition which haunts the texts of the young Strauss is that between ‘belief’ and ‘unbelief.'” Indeed, Strauss concurred with Goethe’s judgment, that the “struggle between unbelief and belief” constitutes “the eternal and sole theme of the entire history of the world and man.” Against “unconditional submission to Jewish law,” affirmation of certain “fundamental dogmas” creation, miracles, providence) Strauss opposed what looks to Quélennec very much like the Nietzschean claim (itself borrowed from the Protestant Bible scholar Julius Wellhausen) of Judaism as originally a form of nature-worship, and thus potentially a pathway to the rational study of nature, to philosophy. On this basis Strauss could claim that Zionism, aiming at the founding of a state based on natural principles, could be reconciled with Judaism in its original form, a nature-religion opposed and buried by priests. This would overcome the impasse of Jewish nationalism. It would require the formation o a Zionist elite who would hold up Judaism as a civic religion for the Jewish ‘masses,’ obviating the need for “a democratic politics,” which was proving itself impotent against proponents of tyranny ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ in 1920s Germany.

    By the 1920s Strauss thus had established himself as an astringent critic of the ethics and politics of sentimentalism. It would be too much to call him a philosopher, yet, but his no-nonsense refusal to tolerate slovenly thought, sentimental moralism, and the wishful thinking resulting from them impelled him to an ascent from the ‘cave’ of the Weimar regime generally, and from its Jewish (and, as he saw it, insufficiently Judaic) milieu in particular. In the second half of the decade he began to turn away from “the political struggles of his time,” beyond the nationalist-Enlightenment critique of Orthodoxy as revised and radicalized by Nietzsche and toward a critique of the Enlightenment itself. For that, he turned to the study of Spinoza. Cohen had criticized Spinoza for his “aristocratic” concept of philosophy, for his naturalistic ethics founded not on divine law but on “the right of the stronger,” for his irreligious denial of prophetic inspiration, and for his use of revealed religion for merely civic purposes. “For Cohen, Spinoza totally lacked the universalistic dimension of Judaism, which was illustrated by the rabbinical doctrine of the Noachide [commandments], the source of modern natural right,” as Cohen thought. Strauss defended Spinoza for attempting “to deliver philosophy from the tutelage of the Church and for reinforcing the republic” in Holland, which was under attack by Calvinists who justified absolute monarchy by citing the Old Testament. Cohen failed to look at Spinoza in his political context, that is, as a ‘politic’ as well as political philosopher. Further, Cohen ignored the contradiction between Judaism and his own neo-Kantianism, itself an Enlightenment-based philosophy decisively inflected by Spinozist thought.

    As he concentrated more carefully on Spinoza’s philosophy itself, however, Strauss began to think of “the modern critique of religion” not so much in historical terms but as a “philosophic problem.” Spinoza took aim at three adversaries: Orthodox Jews, who suspected philosophy as such of heresy; Maimonides, whose defense of philosophy before the bar of Orthodoxy remained mired in ancient Greek thought; and Calvinists, as hostile to philosophy as the Orthodox but anti-republican as well. Strauss rejects Spinoza’s critique of Orthodoxy because his critique of miracles presupposes that we have comprehensive knowledge of natural law; further, and in step with the Enlightenment generally, Spinoza sought to disprove Scripture by ‘crowding out’ divine providence with what Strauss would later recognize as the Machiavellian notion of progress—the use of reason to master fortune. This obviously leads to an infinite regress (how does one know that the scientific discoverer wasn’t aided by God’s grace?). Moreover, as Strauss puts it in a 1925 essay, science “knows nothing, and can now nothing, of all these things since it does not permit itself to believe.” This goes especially for modern “Bible science” which, like all modern science, is atheistic in principle. These weaknesses in Enlightenment arguments induced Enlighteners to supplement their critique with ridicule, replacing piety and prayer with irreverent jeering. Strauss found such antics unimpressive, writing, in his 1928 essay on Sigmund Freud, “If God’s thoughts are not the thoughts of men, and men’s ways are not the ways of God, then God’s thoughts and ways are not experimentally controllable; moreover, every attempt to justify directly by scientific means the denial of the existence of God is fundamentally deficient.” That goes for satire as well as science.

    By contrast, in Spinoza’s estimation Maimonides is a fellow philosopher. But Maimonides concedes too much to biblical revelation, and his science consists of a now-discredited Aristotelianism. He has the wrong theological-political doctrine and the wrong philosophic doctrine. As Strauss observes, Spinoza sees that the new Cartesian science pays no respect to tradition, looking instead to the present and the future, regarding human thought alone to suffice for “the perfection of theory.” Contra Maimonides, no harmonization or even coordination of Scripture and philosophic theory need be attempted.

    Much more firmly anti-rationalist than Orthodoxy (let alone Maimonides), Calvinism regards the Holy Spirit as the sole “necessary guide for the conduct of life,” as reason merely evinces human pride. Enlightenment science simply cannot address such a claim, much less refute it.”

    Strauss finds Enlightenment philosophy as Spinoza and other neo-epicurean philosophers conceive it too ‘soft’ on religion, which is too ‘hard,’ stern and demanding, for epicureans of any stripe to withstand. “Biblical morality, as Strauss represents it, hardens the individual who has faith,” as seen in the example of Father Abraham, ready to sacrifice his own sons to his stern God. If atheism is to match faith, and overcome it, it must make itself equally stern. This is the dimension of Judaism Nietzsche praises. The young Strauss therefore joins Nietzsche in “valoriz[ing] all that which, in theism or atheism, favors the ‘hardening’ of man” against the mushy humanitarianism of Cohen and his predecessors. Strauss praises Hobbes as Nietzsche’s tough-minded forebear, deviser of “an authentically rationalist, atheist morality founded on fear” of death—that is to say, acknowledgement of grim reality far removed from ‘idealist’ illusions. But even Hobbes’s Leviathan, king of the proud, and Nietzsche’s new dawn of the Superman will not suffice: “the deification of mankind is no genuine atheism,” Strauss would eventually observe.

    Quélennec tips his hand at this point, finding all of this “meager and superficial” compared to the thought of the young Marx, who bases his critique of philosophic idealism on the claim that class struggle underlies human ideas and the thought that produces them. But even the young Strauss had a refutation of Marxism well in hand, having shown that scientific materialism at the service of the human mastery of nature and fortune—the promise of all ‘modern’ philosophic doctrines including Marxism—can only ‘speak past’ claims of divine revelation, and never refute it on rational grounds. To his credit, despite his own neo-Marxism, Quélennec usually engages Strauss’s thought on its own terms, even while occasionally assuring his readers of his Leftist bona fides. In this he follows the young Strauss after all, who wrote, “Every author is measured first of all by the standard that he expressly acknowledges in his own work. The best way to dispose of an author is therefore to prove that he fails to achieve what he strives for.”

    Having raised serious questions about the various contemporary attempts to ‘synthesize’ Judaism and Enlightenment philosophy and finding much of the latter inclined to soften human souls in a world that treats softness unkindly, Strauss turned away from Nietzsche and toward the philosopher many regard as the arch-idealist, Plato. What accounts for this turn?

    Against such Straussian thinkers as Heinrich Meier and Michael and Catherine Zuckert, and indeed against Strauss’s own testimony, Quélennec regards the “turn” as “less a rupture with his engagement of the 1920s than a transformation of his mode of political intervention” [italics added]. Strauss, he argues, was forced into ‘Platonism’ by the final political crisis of the Weimar regime and the philosophic crisis it embodied. The Weimar Republic’s weakness stemmed not simply from liberalism’s softness, but more specifically from the incapacity of liberalism founded upon historicist philosophy to defend itself. The historicist claim—that all ‘epochs’ exhibit the ‘values’ of the persons who rule at a given time and place—results in a combination of moral relativism and sociopolitical anarchy incapable of defending itself. Historicist-relativist versions of liberalism cannot justify their own continued existence in the face of challenges mounted by would-be rulers who despise the liberal ‘values’ of egalitarianism and toleration—not incidentally the moral claims enabling the liberation of Jewry. Whereas initially, in the nineteenth century, historicism had resulted in nationalism (to each nation its own values), which led to German unification and strength, in the twentieth century a radical, Nietzsche-inspired historicism led to moral crisis and indeed to German defeat in the Great War, a view Strauss unknowingly shared with a then-obscure French army officer, Charles de Gaulle. [1]

    To understand this radical historicism, Strauss examined the thought of Carl Schmitt, the proponent of a “political existentialism” pointing (very hard-headedly indeed) to the distinction between friends and enemies and the ensuing struggles to the death of friends with their enemies as the essence of politics and the revelation of the truth about human life. There isn’t a trace of epicureanism, or even eudaimonism, in Schmitt; he is no fuzzy-headed liberal. But, as Strauss sees, the confrontation of friends and enemies reprises Hegel’s struggle for recognition, a standard feature of historicist liberalism with its attendant desires for peace with liberty—the happy ending of mutual respect among the combatants. In asserting a ‘pessimistic’ account of the Hegelian dialectic, Schmitt offers only a ‘photographic negative’ of such liberalism. Whether pacifist or bellecist, historicist thought incorporates the Biblical and especially Christian themes it claims to overcome or at least to ‘synthesize’ within a grander ‘system.’ Recalling the imagery of Plato’s Republic and the aspiration of the philosopher to escape the ‘cave’ of political opinion and to ascend to rationally-discoverable truth, Strauss began to describe revealed religion as another nook in the cave, harder for philosopher to escape than the outer rooms, and then to see that historicism was a second cave beneath that enlarged cave. Instead of ascending to the light of the sun, philosophers were becoming more and more profound. But only in the sense of digging themselves a deeper hole. 

    This meant that to philosophize under conditions of radical historicism Strauss could not just go ahead and ‘do philosophy,’ as professors like to say, but engaged in historical scholarship with respect to philosophy, revisiting the “historical problem.” Intended as a “corrective” to the rationalism of the Enlightenment, which failed to overcome Biblical revelation or “theological absolutism” rationally, historicism, in incorporating or ‘synthesizing’ Biblical principles with those of Enlightenment rationalism, had produced “the illusion of a liberation from illusion,” not overcoming revelation but allowing itself to become parasitical on it. There remained “a fragile line of continuity” between Christianity, the Enlightenment, and historicism, “each position constituting itself in polemical negation of the preceding one,” each as dogmatic at its core as the other.

    Seeking to indict Strauss of failing to overcome his Nietzscheism of the 1920s, Quélennec charges that “to Christian modernity, linked historically to a project of intellectual and socio-political emancipation, Strauss would oppose another model of secularization and emancipation,” namely, a philosophic emancipation found in Platonism, approached via Maimonides. As Strauss explains in his 1935 study, Philosophy and Law, Maimonides confronted Christianity without having recourse to modern rationalism in either its Enlightenment or its historicist forms, finding ‘classical’ or Platonic rationalism (and not the Aristotelianism he apparently relies on) adequate to the task of addressing the challenge of revealed religion. “The moderns, from the radical Enlightenment to radical historicism, have wrongly universalized a limited and historically situated combat,” systematically confounding ‘natural’ opinion and ‘religious’ prejudice.” To distinguish such prejudice from such opinion will enable philosophers to ascend not to the ‘sunlight’ of truth outside the cave but to the first cave, reestablishing (as Strauss puts it) “philosophy in its natural difficulty” as the first step toward reestablishing “natural philosophy” undistracted by prejudice. [2] 

    Recurring to his neo-Marxist framework, Quélennec begins his final chapter with a quote from the famed neo-Marxist Louis Althusser, who denounces Plato as “this aristocrat” who “despises Athenian democracy,” proposing “a revolt against the course of things”—against ‘history’ defined as the course of events. In Althusser’s judgment, the philosopher-king merely represents Plato’s own “interests”—the “pride of philosophy.” (In this he echoes the critique of the Apostle Paul.) Quélennec begins more cautiously with Strauss, saying that Strauss defends the liberty of the philosopher against “the politicization of philosophy” seen in “modern thought from Hobbes to Marxism to existentialism,” but also against “apolitical” philosophy, the failure of many academic philosophers to begin their philosophizing with consideration of the images on the walls of the ‘cave’ of social and political opinion. But he quickly applies the Althusserian critique of Plato to Strauss, charging that Strauss shared the intention, the illusion of German conservatives, who intended to use Nazism a a bludgeon to end the liberal-democratic Weimar regime and to replace it with a “fascist, authoritarian, imperial” regime (as Strauss put it in a1933 letter to Karl Löwith), a regime he supported in principle, not merely as a political stopgap against the Nazis. At stake, then, is whether Strauss’s defense of rightist authoritarianism was a matter of principle as well as (im)prudence, and exactly what those principles were.

    Strauss began with what Quélennec calls “a radical critique of Hobbes,” the founder of liberalism and therefore (despite his monarchism) of the modern ‘Left’ in political philosophy. Quélennec rightly disagrees with critics of Strauss who describe him as a neo-Hobbesian, inasmuch as Strauss rejects “modern philosophy” in principle. Strauss’s Hobbes endorses monarchy only as a means to enforce such liberal principles as modern natural right and contractualism against ecclesiastical and aristocratic authority. To put it in Quélennec’s neo-Marxist terms, Hobbes would replace the vanity of the old-regime ‘few’ with a bourgeois morality valorizing economics over politics. Strauss disputes Hobbes because Hobbes makes the human fear of violent death the summum malum of human life, substituting the securing of peace over the securing of justice, effectively making political philosophy instrumental to the presentation of life and no longer a quest for life’s purpose. Add the doctrine of materialism to this, and reason becomes a technique of rule instead of a means of discovering the principles that justify rule. This means that the ‘right to life’ trumps duties which hitherto had imposed limits on the state because those duties derive from realities that transcend the all-too-human: God and nature.

    Strauss does not, however, recur to the old aristocratic celebration of courage, recognizing that Plato subordinates courage to reason; indeed, contemporary German nihilists had forgotten reason altogether. Instead, Strauss argues that “political authority” can only be “assured if it has a foundation outside itself, in a  transcendent and immutable order which is not in the free disposition of individuals.” Following the example of Plato’s Socrates, Strauss affirms the need for dialogue as the first step for philosophers, dialogue asking what justice is; the dialectical reasoning exhibited in such dialogues winnows out false arguments about justice, taking the abler participants closer to a glimpse of what justice is.

    Fearful of the physical warfare that has arisen from just such dialectical struggle, Hobbes endorses a mortal and philosophic egalitarianism whereby no distinction between the philosophic ‘few’ and the unphilosophic ‘many’ remains. Because reason is impotent, the dominant passion of the ‘many,’ the fear of violent death, replaces the quest for justice as the foundation of politics. Sovereign power inheres no longer in the exercise of reason (including and especially its exercise in theological dispute) but in the exercise of will—the strong will of the sovereign. “Faced with the union of the ‘tyrant’ and the ‘masses’ in National Socialism, of which Jews living in Germany are the primary victims,” Strauss “responds not with a critical analysis of authoritarianism and of anti-semitism in its political and socio-political causes, but…with a radical negation of equality among men.” It is surpassingly odd that Quélennec ignores the way in which so many Marxists themselves treated their fellow men as if they were subhuman, murdering millions of them in the quest to eliminate the supposed political and socio-political causes of inequality. On the theoretical level, Quéennec joins his fellow neo-Marxists in praising Strauss’s critique of liberalism’s “pseudo-neutrality” and pseudo-objectivity,” but criticizes him for failing to to recognize the “socio-historical” conditions of all thought, ‘ancient’ and ‘modern.’ “The Straussian return to nature ‘forgotten’ by the moderns is itself constructing on a forgetting, the forgetting of society and history.”

    Given the fact that Strauss concentrates his attention on the Platonic dialogues titled The Regime and The Laws, one must wonder how ‘forgetful’ of society Strauss really was. It rather looks as if the young Strauss consciously rejected historicist reduction of philosophy and politics to economic and social causes understood as the motors of ‘History.’ This may be seen even in Quélennec’s own account of Strauss’s approach to Platonism through the philosophy of Moses Maimonides. In studying Maimonides, Strauss concluded that the problem of Orthodoxy and Enlightenment must remain insoluble “as long as one clings to modern premises.” Strauss “puts Orthodoxy against modernity” in view of Orthodoxy’s firm endorsement of divine revelation as fundamental to Judaism. But Platonic rationalism as understood by Maimonides approaches revelation differently. But Orthodoxy and Plato center their understanding of political life on consideration of law, ultimately on the regime—the “concrete and obligatory order of life” in the political community, as Strauss puts it. Plato requires the philosopher first to make a dialectical scent from the ‘cave,’ the city, but then requires him to return and to submit to its laws even while continuing, cautiously, to philosophize. Maimonides stands with Plato on this, while adding the additional and crucial argument that the prophet, not the philosopher, is the true lawgiver, the one who has the imaginative capacity to communicate theoretical truths to ‘the many’ in a form they can comprehend. The prophet thereby serves as a link between philosophy and legislation, “a political function,” his laws aiming at the perfection of the individual, body and soul, and of the city as a whole. Judaic prophecy realizes what Platonic philosophy leaves in the realm of the (practically unattainable) ideas.

    Where does this leave philosophers? While recognizing the divine law as the starting point of their inquiries, both Jewish and Muslim medieval philosophers reserved the right to interpret that law. In so doing, they also recognized the limits of reason, which cannot (for example) say whether the world is eternal or was created by God. they therefore contented themselves with indirect influence on the city—interrogating, interpreting, unifying, repairing the law in accordance with reason, establishing “a sort of State in and under the State, the ‘ideal’ State united in its disjunction with the ‘real’ State and the ideology which sustains it.” Philosophy is a ‘guide for the perplexed’ for the young and perplexed potential philosopher, who wonders about the divine law, its apparent paradoxes, and the difficulties of applying it in hard cases. Quélennec suggests that “many German philosophers” were similarly perplexed in the wake of the Nazi revolution; their “unconditional submission to the new regime often went together with a certain defense of the autonomy of the field [i.e., philosophy] in the face of direct interventions of the State in the functioning of the [academic] institution.” This was surely true of Heidegger, although not true enough; as for Strauss, it is only just to say that the moral and political content of Nazi law precluded any such submission, a refusal based precisely on the hyper-modern content of that law. Quélennec recognizes this much later, observing that Strauss criticizes the Nazi sympathizer Carl Schmitt for giving the ‘total’ law a folkish or democratic foundation and for endorsing the Führerprinzip. Strauss understands law as endorsed by the medieval philosophers as “a counter-model to Schmitt,” a “neo-aristocratic program which inscribes inequality of intelligences and capacities into Being.” This is partially correct, except for the “inscribed” part. Inequality of intelligences and capacities isn’t somehow imposed by philosophers upon nature; they recognize it in nature. This in no way precludes the more fundamental equality of human beings as members of the same species. Quélennec misconceives Strauss as attempting to found a “reactionary utopia.” Strauss had no truck with utopianism, ‘reactionary’ or ‘progressive,’ precisely because he was no historicist. He never assumed that ‘History,’ conceived as the course of events, is necessarily going anywhere. 

    In what Quélennec calls Strauss’s first “Platonic phase”—1932-36—Strauss “linked the liberty of the philosopher to the submission to and justification of the authoritarian political order.” Obviously, in theory Strauss justified only “authoritarian” political orders founded upon the divinely revealed law as interpreted by philosophers; no modern regime of ‘the few’ qualified. Strauss did in practice justify authoritarian political orders in order to contain the Nazis, but that hardly means he endorsed them on the highest level. No less a defender of republicanism than Winston Churchill continued to hope that Mussolini’s Italy, the archetype of fascism, would either join in alliance with the commercial republics against Hitler or at least remain neutral, as Franco would do in Spain. In his second “platonic turn”—1936-38—Quélennec’s Strauss abandoned his claim that Maimonides limited reason with a prophetic-revelatory framework while adhering to Maimonides’ assertion of the political need for a prophet to address ‘the many.’ With his well-known distinction between esoteric thought and exoteric dogma in hand, Strauss now argued that the ‘esoteric’ teaching of Maimonides proved him no pious Jew but “a radical critic of religion”; Strauss adopted the same stance for himself. In practice this meant that Strauss “now describ[ed] the relation of philosophy vis-à-vis the political and religious authorities as purely defensive,” while in practice advocating not the rule of ‘the few’ but Aristotle’s mixed regime, with its compromise between the wisdom of the philosophers and the consent of the people. he also took up his claim that Plato intended his regime in speech as an ironic construct, never to be implemented in practice.

    Quélennec rejects all that. In his reading of Strauss, the mixed regime was only an exoteric shell covering a call for American or “Anglo-Saxon” imperialism, or what Strauss calls (thinking of Churchill’s imperialism) a “decent hegemony.” Such an empire would be ensured by Straussian disciples practicing a “Gramscianism of the Right”—that is, a ‘long march through the institutions’ initiated in the graduate program at the University of Chicago, where Strauss spent most of the last two decades of his life. In pursuit of this alleged goal, Straussians eventually allied with ‘neo-conservatives,’ who (Quélennec rightly remarks) were not conservatives in the European sense at all but old-fashioned liberals. The proffered evidence of this is Strauss’s argument in Persecution and the Art of Writing: Some degree of persecution of politically heterodox views is natural in any political regime, including the relatively tolerant liberal regimes, because any regime must resist its most radical enemies. As far as Quélennec is concerned, this amounts to “philosophic endorsement” of McCarthyism and “Anglo-Saxon propaganda for the ‘free world.'” Although Strauss presents philosophers as persecuted, in his Rightist-Gramscian scheme they are really pulling the strings of the political figures who do the actual persecution of the regime’s enemies, discreetly defending Strauss’s “reactionary utopia.”

    It should be unnecessary to observe that one need not be a ‘McCarthyite’ to support the identification and removal of foreign agents from the government of the United States. Further, Quélennec produces no evidence that the ‘neo-conservatives’ had anything to do with McCarthyism; since there is none, his silence is understandable. It should also be unnecessary to observe that the original, leftist, Gramscians propounded an equally ‘elitist’ vanguardism. So does the ‘postmodernist’ Left of today, which acts exactly as Strauss expected every regime to acting—lauding and hiring its friends, condemning and excluding its enemies. Regimes impose limits and elevate ‘elites,’ period; even democracy requires an elite, namely, the majority that rules. The charge that Strauss thereby endorses McCarthyism thus invites an obvious reply of tu quoque. As for those scare quotes around the Cold-War phrase, the ‘free world,’ it is noteworthy that Quélennec never so much as mentions Strauss’s exchange with the self-proclaimed Hegelian Soviet sympathizer Alexandre Kojève. In his one philosophic dialogue with a real ‘totalitarian’ thinker, Strauss stood on the side of liberty.

    On the practical/moral level, Strauss also testified that the example of Churchill made him see that the republican regimes could still defend themselves; it was not only or event mostly as an imperialist that Churchill galvanized Strauss’s attention. That is where Strauss drew the line in practice, even as he drew it between himself and Kojève in theory, for the balance of his life. Every one of his students knew that. (As an aside, it might be added that Strauss regarded his students, or that they regarded themselves, as the core of a new, Nietzschean ‘planetary aristocracy’ can only be seriously entertained by someone who never knew those guys. Stanley Rosen, Harry Jaffa, and Allan Bloom lacked nothing in self-esteem, but there were limits to it.)

    With this intelligent and stimulating essay, Quélennec climbs to the top of the substantial heap of scholars who charge Strauss and his students with elitism, authoritarianism, imperialism, and so on. With regard to “the young Strauss,” Quélennec most likely wishes that he had favored not an anti-Nazi coalition of ‘Rightist’ regimes or even an Anglo-American alliance based partly on assaults launched from territories within the British Empire, but the Popular Front strategy of the 1930s Left. Honorable men took this position, including George Orwell and André Malraux, but they also abandoned hope of ‘one big Left’ after the moral and geopolitical  realities of the Cold War sank in.  Quélennec hasn’t learned enough from them.

    As for the more recent controversies, it is hard to resist the opinion that the ‘Strauss Wars’ have really amounted to not so much a critique of American foreign policy under the Reagan and Bush administrations as an attempt to discredit faculty colleagues in North America, Britain, and continental Europe. The struggle is unquestionably a political one, very much among academic ‘elites,’ over who will be permitted to teach students and thereby advance the political principles and policies of the regimes they favor. Plato was right about Socrates and Athens, philosophers and sophists, philosophers and demagogues, and from the universities of seventeenth-century Europe to the universities in the West today, such struggles continue. 

     

    Notes

    1. See Charles de Gaulle:  The Enemy’s House Divided. Robert Eden translation. Durham: The University of North Carolina Press, 2002.
    2. In this passage, Strauss does not mean “natural philosophy” in the sense of the pre-Socratics; he means rather philosophizing that begins in the polis, ‘the city,’ and ascends from there to insight into nature. 

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • 1
    • 2
    • Next Page »