Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for October 2020

    Chateaubriand’s Critique of Rousseau’s State of Nature

    October 29, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    François-René Vicomte de Chateaubriand: Atala/René. Irving Putter translation. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967.

    Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Discourse on the Origin and the Foundations of Inequality among Men. In Victor Gourevich, editor and translator: The Discourses and Other Early Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

     

    In the second Discourse, Rousseau sets his task: How to discover what “Man” is, “as Nature formed him,” before he had been “altered in the lap of society” (R124). In society, “all one still finds is the deformed contrast of passion that believes it reasons and the understanding that hallucinates” (R124). The self-obscuring of Man has occurred because “the more new knowledge we accumulate, the more we deprive ourselves of the means of acquiring the most important knowledge of all,” self-knowledge (R124). Indeed, “in a sense it is by dint of studying man that we have made it impossible to know him” (R124), since study itself, resulting in the accumulation of knowledge, not only distracts us from attending to the core of human nature but contributes to the mass of conventions in which it is unmeshed. “It is no light undertaking to disentangle what is original from what is artificial in man’s present Nature” (R125); to do so, experiments will be needed, experiments in which philosophers and sovereigns collaborate. Rousseau offers a thought-experiment to this project, a project that carries on the original philosophic attempts to distinguish nature from convention.

    Why bother? Because the ideas of both natural right and natural law depend upon the nature of Man; that right and that law undergird conventional law, the law by which a sovereign might condemn a philosopher or exile a prince. An exile himself, Chateaubriand knows the stakes, and in his Essai Historique, Politique, et Moral, sur les Révolutions Anciennes et Modernes he follows Rousseau in questioning the moral value of civilization. 

    Rousseau identifies two principles “prior to reason” in human souls: the instinct for well-being and self-preservation; and repugnance to human death or suffering, that is, “the force of natural pity” or compassion (R153), as distinguished, evidently from the conscience that receives the divine grace of caritas, of agape. Natural right derives from these two principles, “rules which reason is subsequently forced to reestablish on other foundations, when by successive developments it has succeeded in stifling nature” (R127). Man is not by nature political or even social, nor is he naturally rational; Aristotle is all wrong about that, as he is when he contends that man naturally desires to know. 

    How could such a being fall into the state of civil society, with its artificial/conventional hierarchies? There are two types of inequality: natural or physical inequality, which includes qualities of Mind or Soul; and moral or political inequality, which “depends on a sort of convention” and rests on “men’s consent” (R131). In this, Rousseau obviously follows previous modern natural rights philosophers such as Hobbes and Locke, but these philosophers, he contends, didn’t get to the core of the matter, as they “spoke of Savage Man and depicted Civil man” (R132). Rousseau’s inquiry will eschew empiricism and “the uncertain testimony of history” (R142), offering instead “hypothetical and conditional reasonings better to elucidate the nature of things than to show their genuine origin” (R132). If, say, scientists could conclusively demonstrate the theory of Darwinian evolution with unquestionable empirical evidence, that would matter little if at all to Rousseau. Why not? Because his task is to identify the moral origin of inequality, not its physical origin. As he instructs himself and his reader, “You will look for the age at which you wish your Species had stopped” ‘evolving’ (R133). 

    If human beings originally do not differ from other animals in their capacity to reason, how do they differ? They differ in their capacity to imitate other animals. Man has “the choice of fleeing or fighting” (R136). This flexibility or adaptability makes it easier for him to find his subsistence in nature. Original man is hardy, vigorous; what the ascetic laws of Lycurgus’ regime did for Spartans, nature’s ‘regime’ did for original man, who needs no tools, no inventions, to aid in his well-being and survival. Pace John Locke, the state of nature—and Rousseau regards it as the alternative to all political ‘states,’ a state with a regime of its own—is not a condition of scarcity. Nor is original man a fearful being, as per Hobbes, as he surpasses other animals in skill (skill learned from observing and imitating those animals) “more than they do him in strength” (R136). Living dispersed in nature, he has no fear of other men, either, as he seldom encounters them. Rousseau takes as his example the Caribs of Venezuela, secure in the forest.

    Natural man never agonizes over death—or life, for that matter. No French or German ‘existentialism’ for him: “the immoderate transports of all the passions, the fatigues and exhaustion of the Mind, the innumerable sorrows and pains” that “constantly gnaw away at men’s souls” are ills “of our own making” within civil society, where we have consented to live packed together, envying, lusting, fighting, and thinking altogether too much (R137). “The man who meditates is a depraved animal” (R137). “As he becomes sociable and a Slave, he becomes weak, timorous, groveling,” in his “soft and effeminate way of life” (R138-39). Machiavelli accuses Christianity of effeminizing modern man, but Rousseau accuses civil society itself, of any kind. Civilization is savagery in the conventional sense of the term: not solitary or poor (except for the exploited lower classes), but nasty and short. Would that it were brutish! Would that men were still savage in the way they once were. His paradox, “the noble savage,” itself recalling Socrates’ paradox, the noble lie, finds its explanation there. Given Rousseau’s rejection of empiricism, the noble savage himself exemplifies a sort of noble lie—a lie if one defines truth exclusively in terms of ‘facticity,’ a truth if one does not. 

    “Self-preservation being almost his only care,” original, natural, savage man’s “most developed faculties must be those that primarily serve in attack and defense” (R139-40). Those faculties are sight, hearing, and smell, not touch and taste, those senses most refined in civil society. Beyond these physical attributes, unlike other animals, natural man “contributes” to his machine-like natural “operations” as “a free agent” (R140). As long as he employs his freedom to choose between fleeing or fighting, hunting or gathering, and similar actions that contribute to his well-being and self-preservation he remains a good animal. But freedom also enables him to deprave his senses. Man has a moral as well as a physical nature, by which Rousseau means that in man, “the will continues to speak when nature is silent” (R140). Other animals have ‘ideas’ in the Lockean sense of sense-impressions, and can even combine those ideas, but in man not only has freedom but is conscious of his freedom. “It is mainly in the consciousness of this freedom that the spirituality of his soul exhibits himself,” a spirituality not explicable by “the laws of Mechanics” (R141). 

    With this self-conscious freedom, man has “the faculty of perfecting oneself,” a faculty “distinctive” to his species and “almost unlimited” (R141). Here is “the source of all of man’s miseries,” as the self-perfecting faculty “eventually makes him his own and Nature’s tyrant” (R141). The Machiavellian attempt to conquer Fortuna, the closely related Baconian attempt to conquer Nature, seen in those philosophers who take man’s emergence from the state of Nature as a human triumph to be extended and completed, leads instead to Man’s self-denaturing in a very bad sense, his misery in civil society. Had he lived to see them, Rousseau would have looked upon the invention of weapons of mass destruction and the possibility of human extinction by ‘environmental’ cataclysm as inevitable results of civil society, itself the result of man’s free, but wrong, choices.

    We civilized men only seek to know because we want. The more we know, the more we want. The desires of Savage man, by contrast, “do not exceed his physical needs” for food, a female, and rest; his aversions do not go beyond pain and hunger (R142). This being so, “Who fails to see that everything seems to remove from Savage man the temptation as well as the means to cease from being savage?” (R142-43). There are five reasons for this. “His imagination depicts nothing to him; his heart asks nothing of him,” as he has “neither foresight nor curiosity,” never wondering, centering himself in “the sole sentiment of present existence” (R143). He has no need to work and does no sustained work; agriculture (for example) can occur only when the human population has increased, families formed, and settlement instead of natural roaming becomes attractive, attractive because necessary. Savage man engages in no sustained thinking, having no language, only signaling cries; this is Rousseau’s answer to the Biblical claim that the First Man spoke with God. Savage man of course mated, but otherwise led a solitary existence, not forming families. Finally, Savage man experienced no misery, as he was a free being in mind, peaceful at heart, and healthy in body. Civil society has produced exactly the opposite effect. “Almost all the People we see around us complain of their existence and some even deprive themselves of it as far as they are able, and the combination of divine and human Laws hardly suffices to stop this disorder: I ask whether anyone has ever heard tell that it has so much occurred to a Savage, who is free, to complain of life and to kill himself?” (R158).

    “Nothing, on the contrary, would have been as miserable as Savage man dazzled by the enlightenment, tormented by Passions, and reasoning about a state different from his own” (R150). In Atala, Chateaubriand will present Chactas, a noble savage who experiences exactly this dazzlement and torment. But for the Savage still in the state of nature, still ruled by nature’s regime, “in instinct alone he had all he needed to live”; today, “in cultivated reason he has no more than what he needs to live in society” (R150). In neither the natural nor the civil state, Rousseau silently suggests, does man need divine revelation. Rousseau does assent to a teaching of the Book of Genesis, that Man’s original condition was a condition of innocence. “Savages are not wicked precisely because they do not know what it is to be good” (R151). But this has nothing to do with obedience to God’s command, expressed in words incomprehensible to a being without language. Rather, it is the calm of the passions and the ignorance of vice that “keep them from evil-doing” (R152). Morally, Savage man recognizes his fellow humans as akin to himself and pities them, “a sentiment that is obscure and lively in Savage man, developed but weak in Civil Man,” the being in which reason, initially supported by natural pity, “turns man back upon himself,” causing him to separate himself from “everything that troubles and afflicts him” (R153). Reason isolates men after human beings in their natural freedom choose the civil state over the natural one, choosing ‘society,’ by giving Man the prudence he needs to protect himself when others are in peril from the very conditions civil society entraps them, and him, in. Natural pity says, “Do your good with the least possible harm to others”; unnatural reason says, “Do unto others as you have them do unto you”; natural pity is the “less perfect but perhaps more useful standard” (R154). Rousseau thus suggests that Jesus’ Golden Rule, presented as divine revelation, really amounts to an abstract and therefore practically unattainable command proposed by the reason which has its origin in natural pity but subverts and revolutionizes the regime of the state of nature in which the sentiment of pity is both right and attainable. 

    Of the passions Savage man experiences, sexual passion is the most dangerous, as even in his condition of isolation his natural desire for a female might lead to a fight with some competitor. At the same time, this passion is obviously the one most necessary for species preservation and, although the individual Savage man scarcely conceives of species preservation the human species would not have survived without the passion that has neither justification nor prohibition in the mind of the beings that experience it. Savage man experiences sexual passion as a purely physical love; insofar as it is, this passion is natural and good. Civilized man, however, in the grips of unnatural imagination, experiences “moral” love—in fact unnatural and bad—an instrument whereby women “establish their rule” over men, “mak[ing] dominant the sex that should obey” (R155). Once again, Rousseau points to the Caribs, “the most peaceful in their loves and the least given to jealousy” (R156).

    What about the “savages” Chateaubriand will present in the Atala and the René? In his first Discourse, the Discourse on the Moral Effects of the Arts and Sciences, Rousseau observes that the savages of the Americas are “impossible to tame.” “What yoke could be imposed upon men who need nothing?” (R7n.). They are peoples of “simple and natural polity,” rightly admired by Montaigne (R11). Consistent with his portrayal of Man in the state of nature, Rousseau writes, in his Essay on the Origin of Languages, that “the Savages of America almost never speak except when away from home; in his hut everyone remains silent and speaks to his family by means of signs, and these signs are infrequent because a Savage is less restless, less impatient than a European, because he has not as many needs and takes care to attend to them himself” (267n.). Savage man’s roaming issues not from restlessness but from ease, from freedom from the self-exaggerated passions of man in the civil state. In his Essay, Chateaubriand had already diverged from Rousseau, locating restlessness in the natural condition of the human heart. He does not need to ask himself how free, untroubled Savage man chose civil society. Rousseau explains this by citing natural disasters and natural population growth as altering the natural state in such a way as to tempt Savage man to make choices that seem correct to him at the time he makes them, but concatenate into civil societies and their attendant miseries. 

    Slightly over a year after Chateaubriand published his Essai, he experienced a religious conversion described in his Mémoires d’Outre-Tombe. His brother and sister-in-law had been killed by the Jacobins, a few years before he wrote the Essai. But after his mother died in 1798, followed by a sister, Julie-Marie, in 1799, “I wept and I believed.” The exact character of his conversion has remained a matter of speculation—following as it did from his understanding of religion as a matter of moral sentiment—but it is undeniable that his subsequent writings bear ‘a Christian mark.’ Published propitiously in 1801, the beginning of a new century, his novella Atala was seen immediately as a sign of a literary conversion as well, inspiring a turning of the French intellectual class away from France’s Enlightenment rationalism and toward what would be called Romanticism, a movement often considered to have been inaugurated in European literature by the publication of Goethe’s The Sorrows of Young Werther in 1774. Atala made Chateaubriand an intellectual celebrity; he followed it a year later with the equally influential René. He rightly brought out them out in one volume in 1805, emphasizing their complementarity. 

    He presents Atala as a story told by a Natchez Indian to a young European, René, then re-told by “the Indians” to himself, “a traveler in far-distant lands” (76). In the Epilogue the narrator identifies the elements of the story: “a portrayal of the people of the hunt and the people of the plow”—Indians living their traditional way of life and Indians living the European way of life, respectively; a portrayal of “religion, the supreme lawgiver to men”; of “the perils of religious ignorance and all consuming fervor set against the light, the charity, and the true spirit of the Gospel”; of “the struggles of passion and virtue in an innocent soul,” the soul of Atala, a Muskogee princess; and of “the triumph of Christianity over the most ardent feeling and the most terrible fear—love and death,” the triumph of agape over eros and Thanatos (76).

    Having learned from Rousseau that the state of nature has a regime, the narrator begins by recalling France’s state and France’s regime, its “vast empire in North America” “in days gone by” (17). Louis XIV ruled, somewhat nominally, a portion of an even vaster continent, dwelled in but not yet truly ruled by men. The central feature of North America’s natural regime was the Meschacebe River (pronounced as ‘Mississippi’ by the French), flowing through the center of the center of the continent, “which the inhabitants of the United States call New Eden, while the French have bequeathed to it the gentle name of Louisiana” (17). The Meschabe is central not only to the land but to the waters of North America: “A thousand other rivers, all tributaries of the Meschacebe…enrich it with their silt and fertilize it with their waters” (17). Flowing past “the forest colonnades and the pyramids of Indian tombs,” the Meschacebe “is the Nile of the wilderness” (17), the cradle not so much of a unified civilization as of a set of hunting-and-gathering tribes, often at war with one another. Chateaubriand’s state of nature is not Rousseau’s state of nature. Human beings live in families and tribes within that state. Nature itself consists of tensile dualities. Its heartland river has two currents, the main current flowing south to the Gulf of Mexico, “pushing dead trunks of pines and oak trees down to the sea,” and the two side currents flow upstream carrying “floating islands of pistia and water lilies, their yellow blossoms rising like little banners” (18). The river banks also contrast with one another. On the western side “savannahs spread out as far as the eye can see”; thousands of bison “wander about aimlessly,” one occasionally will find its way to a river island, “his brow crowned with twin crescents,” his jaw decorated by an “ancient muddy beard”; “he might be taken for the god of the river, casting a satisfied eye over the grandeur of his waters and the wild abundance of his shores” (18). Against the “silence and calm” of the prairies, the eastern shore features “trees of every shape, of every hue and every odor” and vines which form “a thousand bowers,” supporting “a host of animals placed by the Creator’s hand”—all “radiat[ing] gladness and life” (18-19). “Everything stirs and murmurs,” and the bears, “drunk with grapes, and reeling on the branches of the elm trees,” celebrate in Dionysian contrast to the Apollonian bison of the west (19). 

    To the dualities of these “primeval fields of nature,” men have added their own dualities. The French settled in Biloxi and New Orleans, allying with the Natchez, “an Indian nation with formidable powers in those territories” (19). Chactas is a survivor of those times, now an elder of 73 “whose age, wisdom, and vast knowledge of life made him the patriarch of the wilderness beloved of all” (19). As “a primitive and tender harmony” fills the west bank of the Meschacebe, so ‘Chactas’ means “harmonious voice”; at the same time, “like all men, he had acquired his great virtue at the cost of suffering” (19); for Chateaubriand as for Burke, there is the beautiful but also the sublime, and for Chateaubriand the beautiful comes at the cost of the struggle of sublimation. In the wars between the French-Natchez alliance and the “the powerful Muskogees of the Floridas,” the young Chactas had lost his father and himself was wounded (22). “Oh, Why could I not then have descended to the land of souls! I would have avoided all the sorrows awaiting me on earth. The spirits willed it otherwise.” (22). He would go on to be “held prisoner in the galleys of Marseilles through a cruel injustice,” never specified, then “set free and later presented to Louis XIV” at Versailles” (20). “He had spoken with the great men of the age and had been present at the celebrations of Versailles, the tragedies of Racine, and the funeral orations of Bossuet”—a “savage [who] had beheld society at the pinnacle of its splendor” (20). 

    Having long since returned to his homeland, Chactas tells his story to René, a young Frenchman who arrived in Louisiana in 1725, “impelled by passion and sorrow,” by his own experience of the sublime (20). René asked to be admitted to the Natchez as a warrior; “Chactas questioned him closely, and, finding him unshakeable in his resolution, adopted him as his son and gave him as a wife an Indian girl” (20). He does so in honor of the French, for “in spite of the many injuries” he had suffered at their hands, “he loved them,” remembering Fenelon, “who had once been his host,” and wishing to “render some service to the countrymen of such a righteous man” (20). No Christian, Chactas instead exhibits the classical virtue of magnanimity and the Indian (and Homeric) virtue of hospitality, which Chateaubriand had described in the closing chapter of the Essai. On his first hunt with the Natchez, René asks Chactas to relate “the story of his adventures” (21). The story has four parts. The first centers on the Indian way of life and is titled “The Hunters.”

    Chactas tells René, “I see in you the civilized man who has become a savage; you see in me the savage whom the Great Spirit has (I know not for what purpose) chosen to civilize” (22). This duality sets up a sort of Rousseauian thought-experiment: “Having entered life’s path from opposite ends,” “we must have had a totally different view of things” (22). “Which of us has gained or lost more by this change of position?” (22). That question will be answered, insofar as it is answered, only at the conclusion of René.

    After fighting that losing battle to the Muskogee, Chactas arrived as a refugee in St. Augustine, where an old Castilian named Lopez befriended him, sparing him the fate of being shipped to a mine in Mexico. But, as Rousseau would have predicted, “after spending thirty moons in Saint Augustine, I was overcome by a strong distaste for the life of the city” (23). At the age of 20, in the year 1672, he “was wasting away”; he tells Lopez, who has been a father to him, “You can see for yourself, I shall die if I do not go back to my Indian life” (23). In tears, knowing the danger the young man will face if he falls “into the hands of the Muskogees,” Lopez replies, “Go, son of nature! Go back to man’s freedom. I do not wish to rob you of it”(22). With that, “Lopez prayed to the God of the Christians, whose faith I had refused to embrace, and we parted sobbing” (23). Like Chateaubriand, Lopez understands nature as Rousseau understands it, as the Eden of human freedom, while knowing that nature’s dualities bring forth war, sublimity, realities in need of Christian sacrificial grace. The story of Chactas encompasses all three of the ‘races’ then living in southeastern North America: the Indians (themselves divided into two principal nations), the French, and the Spanish. Early in that story, it is the Spaniard who speaks and acts as a Chateaubriand. 

    Chactas was indeed captured by the Muskogee and condemned to death by burning. A Muskogee woman, Atala, befriended him; although Chactas initially mistakes her for the “Maiden of Last Love,” the one in Indian practice was “sent to the prisoner of war to charm his grave” (25). She is no such person but a Christian, wearing a golden crucifix, a maiden of agapic love who takes pity on him and falls in love with him, regretful that “my religion separates me from you forever,” but choosing to aid the “wicked heathen,” nonetheless (25). 

    Chactas is a savage, but no Rousseauian savage. “What enigmas men are when they are buffeted by passions! I had just abandoned the kindly Lopez, I had exposed myself to every danger for the sake of my freedom, and now, in an instant, a woman’s glance had changed my desires, my intentions, my thoughts! Forgetting my country, my mother, my cabin, and the horrible death awaiting me, I had become indifferent to all that was not Atala. I was powerless to rise to a man’s mature reason, for I had suddenly sunk into a kind of childishness,” needing “someone to take care of my sleeping and feeding needs” (29)—a sort of return to nature experienced not as independence, as freedom, but as infantile dependence. The encounter of Savage man with woman results not in mere mating but in love; Rousseau would of course reply that Chactas is no true Savage, having already been exposed to civilization by the Spaniard, and indeed by the Natchez’s French allies before that. 

    The lovers escape into the forest, and to “some vague far-away harmony permeating the depths of the woods,” “as though the soul of solitude were sighing through the entire expanse of the wilderness” (29). They overhear a young Seminole singing a song as he goes to ask a girl to marry him, and then a Seminole mother weeping over the grave of her infant child, saying, “Happy are those who die in the cradle, for they have known only the smiles and kisses of a mother!” (31). Love and motherhood: Atala herself seems to be “yielding to nature,” but prays “a fervent prayer to her mother and to the Queen of Virgins” to counter its spell (31). As Chateaubriand had written in the Essai, Chactas now tells René: “I have marveled at that religion which, in the forests, in the very midst of all the privations of life, can lavish untold blessings on the unfortunate. It is a religion which sets its might against the torrent of passions and alone”—alone—suffices “to subdue, though they be stirred by every circumstance,” which in the case of the lovers includes “the seclusion of the woods, the absence of men, and the complicity of the shadows” (31). Atala, a “simple savage girl,” seemed to him not so much noble as “divine” as she “offer[ed] prayers up to her God for an idolatrous lover,” “radiat[ing] immortal beauty” (32).

    The Muskogee recapture them. Christianity nearly saves Chactas, anyway. Christian missionaries to the several Indian nations had persuaded them “to substitute a rather mild form of slavery for the horrors of the stake,” and while the Muskogee “had not yet adopted this custom,” some of them “had declared themselves in favor of it” (32-33). The tribal council deliberates. One side wants him tortured and executed, so as not to “alter the customs of our ancestors”; a matron, speaking for the women, rejoins, “Let us change the customs of our ancestors when they are destructive,” since we can use Chactas as a slave to “cultivate our fields” (34). The Muskogee are hunters, but agriculture, along with Christianity, has begun to filter in. This duality of savagery and civilization stays his execution but would not have prevented it, as the men, guardians of tradition, prevailed.

    Atala breaks with the tradition, rescuing him. To Chactas’ grateful attempt to deify her (“You are a spirit, you have come to me, and I am speechless before you”), she demurs with a simple and naturalistic explanation: She bribed the medicine man and got his would-be executioners drunk (38). She has acted with justice more than charity: “I had to risk my life for you, since you had given up your own for me,” effectively delaying his escape from his captors by bringing her along in the forest (38). This time, they exercise natural prudence, heading north, not west to the Meschacebe in the direction of his nation, where the Muskogee will expect them to go. 

    In their flight they cannot escape the dualities which divide both of their souls, and each from the other. To be sure, they “bless Providence,” which “places hope deep in hearts sore with sorrow and makes virtue spring from the bosom of life’s miseries” in Christians and heathens alike (40). But “the constant struggle between Atala’s love and religion, her unrestrained tenderness and the purity of her ways, the pride of her character and her deep sensitivity, the loftiness of her soul in essential things and her delicacy in the little ones—everything made her an incomprehensible being” to Chactas (41). She prays to God but also sings “of the lost homeland,” a song whose refrain is “Happy are they who have never seen the smoke of the stranger’s celebrations and have sat only at the festivals of their fathers!” (42). But to the pull of agapic, patriotic, and familial love (“she seemed anxious to appease” the “angered shade” of her Christian mother), she feels the push of a love that strengthened “with every passing moment” (43). “Atala’s strength was beginning to fail her, and the passions weakening her body seemed about to overcome her resistance” (43). She nonetheless holds out, appealing not to Christian chastity, a virtue issuing from a religious sentiment Chactas cannot be expected to feel, but to his patriotic honor, adjuring him to remember that “a warrior is bound to his country” (43). “What is a woman beside the duties you must fulfill?” (43). 

    It is at this point of stasis that Chactas interrupts his story to advise René with some decidedly un-Rousseauian wisdom. “If you dread the agitations of the heart, beware of solitude. Great passions are solitary, and when you take them out into the wilderness”—as René evidently has done—you “are setting them into their very own sphere” (43). For all its beauty, its harmony, the state of nature has its torments. “O dreadful, sublime Nature, were you no more than a device contrived to deceive us, and could you not for an instance conceal a man’s joys in your mysterious horrors?” (46) The lovers’ sorrows in nature ended only “by chance,” as pagan Chactas puts it (43). 

    Before that happens, Atala answers a perplexity. Her mother had given her Christian witness to Atala, but who had brought Christianity to her? Her father, she tells Chactas, was not a native of Florida, “the land of the palms” (45). Pregnant with both Atala and the Holy Spirit, Atala’s mother had returned to her people, and her mother had “obliged her to marry the magnanimous Simaghan,” the king of the Muskogee (45). Again, the ‘ancient’ and in this case Indian parallel to Christian charity is magnanimity: to Atala’s mother’s offer to suffer punishment for adultery, Simaghan correctly observes that she hasn’t committed adultery against him. “You have been sincere and have not dishonored my couch,” and so “the fruit of your body shall be my fruit” (45). She knows only that her natural father was named Lopez, whom Chactas at once recognizes as the man who had been a father to him in St. Augustine. They are in this sense brother and sister.

    “The fraternal affection which had come upon us, joining its love to our own love, proved too powerful for our hearts” (46). They embrace, and “I held my bride in my arms by the light of the flashing thunderbolts and in the presence of the Eternal” in a “nuptial ceremony, worthy of our sorrows and the grandeur of our passion”—a wedding solemnized under the regime of “sublime Nature” (46). But “an impetuous bolt of lightning, followed by a clap of thunder, furrowed the thickness of the shadows, filled the forest with fire and brimstone, and split a tree apart at our very feet”—sublimity indeed, a suggestion of Hell within nature itself (46). 

    Christianity then intervenes. “There in the ensuing silence we heard the ringing of a bell,” which can only betoken a church, a mission church. “An aged recluse,” bearing a lantern, emerges from the shadows (47). This Christian Diogenes has been seeking persons no abstract philosophic truth. His dog had picked up their scent when the storm began and he has been trailing them. “God be praised in all his works!” he exclaims. “His mercy is great indeed, and His goodness is infinite!” (47). Atala venerates him, telling him that she is a Christian, that “Heaven has sent you to save me” (47). As for Chactas, “I could scarcely understand the hermit,” as “such charity seemed to far superior to mortal man that I thought I was in a dream” (47). As an Indian, however, he praises the man’s courage in braving the lightning strikes. “‘Fear!” replied the father with a kind of intense fervor, ‘shall I fear when men are in peril and I can be useful to them! Surely I would be a most unworthy servant of Christ!'” (47). When Chactas admits that, unlike Atala, he is no Christian, Father Aubry admonishes him: “Young man, have I asked you your religion? Christ did not say, ‘My blood shall wash this man and not that one'” (47). Atala has gone from a natural father to an adoptive father to a Christian father; Chactas has gone from a natural Indian father who was killed in battle to an adoptive Spanish father whom he left to return to his fatherland, into the presence of a Christian father, whose Father is in Heaven, the Kingdom of God that the settlement named for St. Augustine prefigured. 

    The lovers now emerged from the regime of the hunters and the regime of nature to the regime of “The Tillers”—the second part of Chactas’ story. He begins with a portrait of its founder. With his “simple and sincere” face—passing Rousseauian muster—Father Aubry “did not have the lifeless, indistinct features of a man born without passions: plainly his days had been hard, and the furrows on his brow revealed the rich scars of passion healed by virtue and by the love of God and man”—Christlike (49). “Everything about him possessed something strangely calm and sublime,” as Christian sublimity culminates in peace (49). “Whoever has seen Father Aubry, as I have, wending his solitary way in the wilderness with his staff and his breviary, has a true idea of the Christian wayfarer on earth” (49). He lived in a cave with his crucifix and “the book of the Christians,” solitary except for a symbolic, “tamed snake” (49) and perhaps, unnoticed by Chactas, the Holy Spirit. To the scars of passion “heathen Indians” had added scars to his body, but “the more they made me suffer the dearer I held them” (50). As pagan Chactas had responded to unjust punishment with the crown of the classical virtues, magnanimity, so the Christian Father Aubry responded to it with agape.

    Father Aubry’s solitude is purposeful, no burden forced upon him by Providence or by Fate. “When I arrived in this region,” he told Chactas and Atala, “I found only wandering families with fierce customs and a pitiful way of life” (50). Without settlement, they had no state, no political community; they had a regime—customs and a way of life—but it was miserable, not idyllic, no state of nature according to Rousseau. “I have given them an understanding of the word of peace, and their customs have gradually grown gentler” (50). With the Word replacing the sparse sign language of Indians, he did not neglect their material well-being; “I have tried to teach them the basic arts of life, not taking them too far, and still preserving for these good people the simplicity which brings happiness,” as Rousseau recommends (51). But like many other founders, “I have been afraid of hampering them by my presence, and so I have withdrawn to this grotto, where they come to consult me” (51). The founder must leave, or at least distance himself, lest the people for whom he has founded a new regime come to depend excessively on him, fail to learn to think and act in accordance with their rulers, their institutions, their way of life, all in accord with its purpose. 

    Leaving Atala behind, the men leave the grotto to visit the mission village. On the way they pass oaks carved with verses from “an ancient poet, named Homer, and a few maxims of an even more ancient poet, called Solomon” (52). “There was a strange and mysterious harmony between this wisdom of the ages, these verses overgrown by moss, this old hermit who had engraved them, and these aged oak trees which served as his book” (52). It is the harmony of ‘Athens and Jerusalem’—but really of Greece before Athens, the Greece of the old religion, the old gods and heroes, and of Jerusalem before Jesus. The verses show that wisdom transcends times and places, written as it is in the book of Nature and embroidered by living nature. This is how Chactas understands Father Aubry, at this point. But in the village itself, at mass the next morning, “I cannot doubt that the great mystery was fulfilled when we prostrated ourselves, and that God descended to earth, for I felt him descend in my heart” (54). He experiences this not as an occasion for weeping but as joy.

    The village of “the tillers” includes not only farms but property (with surveyors to delineate it and arbitrators to settle disputes over it), forges to shape the inorganic fruits of the earth, and wood-choppers who clear the land to be farmed and mined. “I wandered in delight amid these scenes, and they grew even lovelier with the thought of Atala and the dreams of joy gladdening my heart. I marveled at the triumph of Christianity over primitive culture. I could see the Indian growing civilized through the voice of religion. I was witnessing the primal wedding of man and the earth, with man delivering to the earth the heritage of his sweat, and the earth, in return, undertaking to bear faithfully man’s harvests, his sons and his ashes” (55). Chateaubriand answers Rousseau by recalling the curse of Adam and showing the way to a Christian Sparta, not the Lycurgian Sparta Rousseau prefers but the only Spartan regime that can civilize without the harshness of the warrior ethos. “I have given them no law,” Father Aubry explains. “I have taught them only to love one another, to pray to God, and look forward to a better life, for in these simple teachings are all the world’s laws” and, one might add, all God’s laws, according to the Founder of the Christian Regime. Father Aubry calls it “this kingdom of God” (56). As for Chactas, “I felt the superiority of this stable, busy life over the savage’s idle wandering” (56). “How joyous my life had been could I have settled with Atala in a hut by those shores!” (56).

    But “fortune” or “fate” has played with him in a different way (56). The third part of Chactas’ story, titled “The Drama,” recalling the colliding dualities of nature in its mode of sublimity, recounts the end of Chactas’ “dream of happiness” (57). Returning to the grotto, they did not see Atala “hasten[ing] out to greet us” (57). Stricken with “a strange terror,” Chactas dared not enter the grotto. “How weak he is whom passions buffet, how strong the man who rests in God!” (57). Father Aubry entered the cave. Chactas could only find “my strength again” when he heard Atala’s moaning; natural pity overcame natural fear. Atala was seriously ill. “Transfixed as though by a thunderbolt”—parallel to the thunderbolt that interrupted the lovers in the forest—Chactas stood motionless before her (57). The thunderbolt therefore betokened God’s or nature’s warning, setting a barrier to eros, a passion which does not limit itself.

    Father Aubry then made a mistaken diagnosis and spoke a mistaken prophecy; priest and kingly founder, he was no prophet; Christlike, he was no Christ. “This is probably nothing more than a fever caused by fatigue. If we resign ourselves to God’s will, He will take pity on us.” (57). Atala knew better. She now made her confession. No one had expected her to survive for long after a painful childbirth. “My life was given up for lost, and to save me from death, my mother vowed to the Queen of Angels that, if I were spared, my virginity would be consecrated to her. That was the fatal vow which is now forcing me to my grave!” (58). When her mother died, she asked and received Atala’s vow of obedience to that vow made by her mother at her birth. She consoled her by saying that in accepting “the virgin’s veil, you give up only the cares of the cabin and the mortal passions which distressed your mother’s bosom,” and warned her that “I gave my word for you in order to save your life, and if you do not keep my promise, you will plunge your mother’s soul into everlasting woe” (58-59). The Christian religion therefore has proven “at once my sadness and my joy”: “O Chactas, you see now what has made our fate so grim!” (59). She could neither keep her vow nor abandon it. This is the sublimity of Christianity, which demands of its converts unattainable perfection of a new set of virtues beyond those of the ancients, a sublimity nature itself shows forth when it is not beguiling men and women with its beauty, its harmony. 

    Chactas evidently had converted to Christianity, but Atala’s confession turned him to a crisis of faith. “A curse on the oath which robs me of Atala! Death to the God who chokes off nature! Priest man, why did you ever come to these forests?” (59). Father Aubry had the Christian answer for that. “To save you, to subdue your passions and prevent you, blasphemer, from drawing down on your head the wrath of Heaven!” (59). How much have you really suffered, compared to me, much less to Christ? “Where are the marks of your suffering? Where are the injustices you have borne? Where are your virtues which alone could give you some right to complain? What service have you rendered? What good have you done?” (59-60). To these unanswerable questions he added an observation: “You offer me but your passions, and you dare censure Heaven!” (60). Only having suffered as long as I have done, only having worked as I have worked, will you understand “that you know nothing, that you are nothing, and that there is no punishment, however severe, no suffering, however terrible, which the corrupt flesh does not deserve to suffer” (60). To the one thing Socrates says he knows Father Aubry added the one thing that Job learns. Chactas could only ask forgiveness, which Father Aubry immediately granted, as God grants forgiveness for his own sins.

    He turned to attend Atala’s spiritual suffering, what she described to Chactas as the “terrible contradiction” in her soul between obedience to her mother and “remorse for not having been yours” (61). Father Aubry taught her that this “extreme passion” is “not even natural, and therefore it is less guilty in the eyes of God, because it is an error of the mind, rather than a vice of the heart,” a product of her “impulsive imagination,” which “has given you needless alarm about your vows” (60). This means that Christianity answers Rousseau’s critique of the imagination, which he considers an excrescence of civilization, with its own kind of correction. “Religion does not exact superhuman sacrifices,” even if it does command superhuman perfection of virtues (61). Christianity’s “genuine feelings and temperate virtues are far loftier than the impassioned feelings and extreme virtues of so-called heroism” (61). Here Father Aubry could offer recourse to the formal ruling institutions of the Catholic Church regime, whose priests can, in the name of the forgiving God, “absolve you of your vows which are not permanently binding,” enabling Atala to “end your days beside me with Chactas as your husband” (62). 

    This only sharpened Atala’s suffering. It was too late. She must die “the very moment I learn I might have been happy” (62). She wasn’t sick; she had poisoned herself, and Indians know which poisons have no anti-toxins. As Chactas raged “with bursts of frenzied fury known only to savages,” Father Aubry, “with marvelous tenderness, hurried between brother and sister, lavishing on us infinite care” with a “faith [that] lent him accents even more tender and burning than our own passions” (63). Throughout the day into evening, “Spreading numbness gripped Atala’s limbs, and her hands and feet began to grow cold” (63). Why is it that Chateaubriand makes Atala’s death by poison reminiscent of Socrates’ death by poison? She is young; Socrates is as old as Father Aubry. She is a faithful Christian, Socrates a philosopher who never heard of Christianity. Her “primitive education and the lack of necessary teaching [had] brought on this calamity, as “you did not know that a Christian may not dispose of his life as he wishes” (64). She had the one thing most needful to her salvation, the Christian Spirit, but had lacked the Christian civilization offered by the Christian regime on earth, the Christian ecclesia or assembly, the Church. Atala has now learned a wisdom that, in Christian eyes, must far surpass both that of Socrates and of Rousseau, knowing not only herself as a child of God but knowing the wisdom of God. To know the wisdom of God is not of course to have divine wisdom in its entirely; a Christian will therefore remain humble in a way unlikely in a philosopher, ancient or modern. The ancient philosopher’s humility rested in the natural self-knowledge expressed in the confession, ‘I know that I do not know.’ The modern philosopher is considerably less humble, insisting, ‘I know that I can know, and someday will know.’ Rousseau’s proud humility says, ‘I know that knowledge itself is an impediment to knowledge, but I can overcome it.’

    For Atala’s sake, Father Aubrey refined Atala’s Christian wisdom with additional knowledge. God “will judge you for your intention, which was pure, and not for your action, which was guilty” (64). And as for her “mortal life,” “how little you lose in losing this world!” Although you have lived in solitude, you have known sorrow; what would you have thought had you witnessed the evils of society, had your ears been assailed, as you set foot on Europe’s shores, by the long cry of woe rising out of that ancient land?” (64-65). Both Rousseau, with his critique of civilization, and the Christian apostles’ critique of ‘this world,’ concur. But why does Father Aubry suppose that Atala would ever see Europe’s shores? It may be that he considers the French and the Spaniards as constituting Europe in the New World. Or it may be that this is Chactas’ own interjection, placed in Father Aubry’s mouth but reflecting the course of his own life, which would bring him to Europe, to the civilization Rousseau abominated.

    Perhaps it isn’t the world but “your love you regret losing?” (65). If so, “you might as well weep over a dream” (65). The “heart of man” is full of desires, and desires change; you rely on them (65). The “most beautiful love of all was doubtless that of the man and woman formed by the hand of the Creator,” who provided them a paradise better even than the New Eden of the New World (65). “If they were unable to abide in that happy state,” if they could not tame the snake, “what couple after them will ever be able to do so?” (65). The marriages of “the first-born of men” too were troubled, incestuous marriages whereby “love and brotherly affection were blended in the same heart and the purity of one swelled the delight of the other”; these too were troubled by jealousy, these “holy families from which Christ chose to descend” (65). This is the restlessness Chateaubriand identified in the human soul in the Essai. “If man were ever constant in his affections, if his feelings remained eternally fresh and he could strengthen them endlessly, then solitude and love would surely make him God’s equal, for those are the Great Being’s two eternal pleasures” (66). This is why Man is not God. We see this also in man’s mortality, his life soon forgotten by his family and friends as they get on with their own lives. “So natural is man’s infidelity, so trivial a thing is our life even in the hears of our friends!” (66). She can now be a bride of Christ, the only trustworthy bridegroom and, one notices, as her mother had desired. Atala became calm, and now could pass the Christian message to Chactas. “Heaven may be trying you today,” she told him, “but it is only to make you compassionate for the sorrows of others,” as “the human heart,” like “the trees of the forest,” “do not yield their balm for the wounds of men until they themselves have been wounded by the axe” (67). And she answered the question of Nietzsche, decades in advance of his asking it, the question of whether you would will to live your life over again: “If I were to begin life anew, I would still prefer the joy of loving you a few moments in the hardship of exile to a whole life of repose in my native land” (68). 

    “I have one last request of you” (69). Since “there is after this life a longer life,” “how terrible it would be to be separated from you forever” (69). Therefore “if you have loved me, learn the lessons of the Christian faith, and it will prepare our reunion” (69). That is, she wanted him to confirm his salvation, of which she was unsure. Chactas’ reply was remarkable, given his apparent prior conversion. “I promised Atala that I would one day embrace the Christian faith” (69). Father Aubry exclaims, “It is time to summon God hither,” and “scarcely had he pronounced these words when a supernatural power forced me to my knees and bowed my head down at the foot of Atala’s head”; “I thought I saw God Himself emerging from the mountainside” (69). 

    Again interrupting his story, Chactas took out Atala’s crucifix and asked René, more remarkably still, “How can it be that I am still not a Christian?” (70). “What petty motives of politics and patriotism have kept me in the errors of my fathers? No, I will not delay any longer.” (70). He will go to the priest.

    In the fourth and concluding part of his story, Chactas relates how Father Aubry consoled him before Atala’s funeral, saying merely, “It is God’s will” and embracing him (71). “Had I not experienced it myself, I would never have believed there could be so much consolation in those few words of a Christian resigned to fate” (71). Chactas promised, “I shall endeavor to grow worthy of the eternal wedding promised me by Atala” (71). Father Aubry prayed to God to “restore peace in this troubled soul, and leave with him only humble and useful memories of his sorrows!” (71). After her burial, he advised Chactas not to stay in the village but to return to his people. “You owe your life to your country” (74). For him, and for Chateaubriand, Christianity need not mean withdrawal from the life of politics in one’s fatherland. It may be that a Christian mission will take a Christian away from his fatherland, as it did for Father Aubry. But Father Aubry founded a new, Christian regime when he arrived in the New World. It may also be that a Christian mission will bring a Christian back to his fatherland, as it does for Chactas and as it did for Chateaubriand himself. 

    As for his Chactas’ passions, now sorrowful, the same inconstancy that makes eros unreliable, impermanent, causing sorrow, also ends sorrow. Sorrows “must come to an end, because the heart of man is finite” (74). Father Aubry’s answer to Goethe’s sorrowing young Werther, to German Romanticism, is that “we cannot even be unhappy for long,” and therefore ‘Romantic’ suicide is not noble but foolish and wrong. “Such were the words of the man of the rock”—the man of the grotto carved into the mountain and of the Rock of God; “his authority was too great, his wisdom too profound to be questioned” (74). With experience, Chactas has come to know what he then accepted only on authority. “I have never yet met a man who has not been disappointed in his dreams of happiness, nor a heart without its secret wound. The heart most serene in appearance is like the natural well of the Alachua savannah; its surface seems calm and pure, but look down in its depths, and you will discern a great crocodile, nourished in the waters of the well” (75). 

    In his Epilogue, the narrator relates the sequel to the story of Chactas, told him at Niagara Falls by a descendant of the Natchez who survived the French massacre in 1730, found refuge among the Chickasaw, only to be exiled again by British colonists. The granddaughter of the man she calls “René the European” (80), she confirms that Chactas did receive baptism in the Catholic Church. Both men died in the massacre, René having joined the tribe, marrying a Natchez woman. Father Aubry in his turn died at the hands of the Cherokee, “enemies of the French, [who] invaded his mission, guided by the sound of the bell as it rang to succor travelers” (80). The peaceable Kingdom of God on earth flourished in isolation, perished in its first war, a war brought on precisely by its evangelizing welcome to all passersby. Such are the worldly limitations to the Christian Rousseauian founding.

    The founder was captured, tortured, and burned. “Not once could [the Cherokee] draw from him a single cry reflecting shame on his God or dishonor on his country”; on the contrary, “he never ceased praying for his torturers or commiserating with the victims”—the other captives—in “their plight” (80). “To prevent him from talking, the enraged Indians forced a red-hot iron down his throat” and, “no longer able to be of consolation to men, he yielded up his ghost” (80). To suffer torture “stoically” was no novelty to the Cherokee, who had seen many other captives do the same, and whose warriors had themselves done the same under torture. But “they could not help admitting that there was something in the humble courage of Father Aubry which they had never before known, something which went beyond all earthly courage. A number of them were so impressed by his death that they became Christians.” (81). To those who would argue that his founding ended in predictable catastrophe, Father Aubry would likely remark the souls saved as the result of that catastrophe. His kingdom was in, but not of, this world; its purpose pointed beyond this world.

    Chactas visited the burned-out village a few years later. The tame snake was the only living survivor; it “came out of the nearby brush, and curled up at his feet” (81). He found the ashes of Father Aubry and Atala, gathered them; the Natchez woman who tells the story has been carrying them with her, and the narrator, Chateaubriand, venerates them as saints’ relics. “Thus passes all that is good and virtuous and sensitive on earth! Man, thou art but a fleeting vision, a sorrowful dream. Misery is thy essence, and thou art nothing save in the sadness of thy soul and the eternal melancholy of thy thought!” (82). 

    Chateaubriand’s final sentence recalls the last chapter of the Essai. “Hapless Indians whom I have seen wandering in the wildernesses of the New World with the ashes of your ancestors, you who showed me hospitality in the midst of your misery, today I could not return your kindness, for, like you, I wander at the mercy of men, and less fortunate than you in my exile, I have not brought with me the bones of my fathers!” (82). 

    The Epilogue to Atala leaves unanswered questions, questions about René. Why was René self-exiled in the New World? How did he live during the years between Atala’s death and his own death at the hands of the French? 

    René at first lived among, but not truly with, the Natchez. “His melancholy nature drew him constantly away into the depths of the woods,” “a savage among savages” (85). His only companions were Chactas and Father Souël, a missionary based at nearby Fort Rosalie. “These two elders had acquired a powerful influence over his heart, Chactas, through his kindly indulgence, and Father Souël, on the contrary, through his extreme severity” (85). Both men “desired to know”: specifically, to know how René had come to live among them. For years he refused to say, but a letter from Europe arrived, and its contents “so increased his sadness that he felt he had to flee even from his own friends” (85). The come to him, “and so great was their tact, so gentle their manner, and so deep the respect they commanded, that he finally felt obliged to yield” (85).

    They met on the bank of the Meschacebe. “Tents, half-built houses, fortresses just begun, hosts of negroes clearing tracts of land, groups of white men and Indians, all offering a striking contrast of social and primitive ways in this limited space” (86) betokened the regimes of the New World, past regime conflicts, and regime conflicts yet to come. These conflicts also occur in the human soul, and René told of them in his. “The peace in your hearts,” in his friends’ beautiful souls, mirroring “the calm of nature all about me,” put him to shame, given “the disorder and turmoil,” the sublimity, “of my soul” (86).

    He expected them to pity him, “a young man with neither strength nor moral courage, who finds the source of his torments within himself, and can hardly lament any misfortunes save those he has brought on himself” (86). Having “already been harshly punished,” he begged that they temper their condemnation with mercy as they listened to his story.

    His mother died in childbirth. His father bestowed his estate to the eldest son, not René, who “was soon abandoned to strange hands,” returning to the family château only once a year (87). “Spirited in temper and erratic in nature,” he “found freedom and contentment only with my sister Amelia,” with whom he shared “tender affinities in mood and taste” (87). In youth he turned to poetry, as befits “a heart of sixteen” (87). His father died, and René tended him on his deathbed; “it was the first time that the immortality of the soul was clearly present before my eyes,” as “I could not believe that this lifeless body was the creator of my thought; I felt it had to come from some other source,” and too, “I hoped one day to join the spirit of my father” (88).

    He and Amelia went to live with “some aged relatives,” and he considered entering a monastery, as indeed many younger sons of the aristocracy did (89). But “whether it was my natural instability or a dislike of the monastic life, I do not know, but I changed my plans and decided to go abroad” (90). He did not understand Amelia’s “almost joyful gesture” when she saw him off; “I could not repress a bitter thought about the inconstancy of human affections” (90).

    He embarked on an extended Wanderjahr, visiting “the ruins of Rome and Greece, those countries of virile and brilliant memory, where palaces are buried in the dust and royal mausoleums hidden beneath the brambles,” testimony to the “power of nature and weakness of man” (90). Wearying “of searching through graveyards,” he turned to “living races” to see if they “had more virtue and less suffering to offer than those which had vanished” (90). They did not. Workmen building monuments to recently-deceased great men scarcely knew the name of those heroes, and, having “discovered nothing stable among the ancients” he found “nothing beautiful among the moderns,” only the “endless agitations” of his fellow Europeans (89, 92). Even, now, among the Indians, living in the Rousseauian state of nature in which “your needs [are] our only guides,” he had found no rest (93), having brought his modern-civilizational cares with him to the woods, cares that exacerbate the already restless nature of all human beings. 

    Chactas offered him the advice of the ancients: “You must try to temper your character, which has already brought you so much grief” (93). To moderation he added the appeal of magnanimity; “a great soul necessarily holds more sorrow than a little one” (93). He intended to calm René’s passions and to elevate his soul by having him tell of greatness, the France that Chactas remembered, the France of Louis XIV. René cannot comply. “Alas, father, I cannot tell you about that great century, for I saw only the end of it as a child; it had already drawn to a close when I returned to my land. Never has a more astonishing, nor a more sudden change taken place in a people. From the loftiness of genius, from respect for religion and dignity in manners”—from the France of Corneille and Racine—everything “suddenly degenerated to cleverness and godlessness and corruption”—to Voltaire and Diderot (94). Upon returning to France, his sister continued to avoid him. “I found myself lonelier in my native land than I had been on foreign soil”; “everywhere I was taken for an impractical dreamer” (94). He retreated again to solitude, this time in half-deserted churches. He eventually found even solitude intolerable; “weary of constantly repeating the same scenes and the same thought…I began to search my soul to discover what I really sought” (95). Longing for a woman companion, “a mysterious apathy” gripping him, “I resolved to give up my life” (98). Like Atala, “I was imbued with faith, and I reasoned like a sinner; my heart loved God, and my mind knew Him not” (99). 

    Amelia, “the only person in the world I had ever loved,” the only one “who could understand me and to whom I could reveal my soul,” returned to him when he alarms her with a letter telling her to make “arrangements about my worldly goods” (99-100). She stayed with him, but her health began to decline and she left a few months later, writing him of her intention to take the veil. She requests his pledge never to kill himself: “Is there anything more pitiful than thinking constantly of suicide? For a man of your character it is easy to die. Believe me, it is far more difficult to live. (102). René now suspected his sister harbored a secret, for “Who was forcing her into the religious life so suddenly?” (103). He agreed to stand in for their deceased father at the altar on the day of her profession, inwardly raging that he would disturb the service, stab himself in the church. But at the ceremony, “so beautiful was she, so divinely radiant her countenance,” that, “overcome by the glorious sorrow of her saintly figure and crushed by the grandeur of religion, I saw my plans of violence crumbling” (106). Feeling himself “bound by an all-powerful hand…instead of blasphemy and threats, I could find in my heart only profound adoration and sighs of humility” (106). 

    Wrapped in a funeral shroud, Amelia laid herself on the marble slab, an action symbolic of her death to this world, and “the priest began the service for the dead” (107). From under the shroud “a confused murmur emerged”; leaning over her, only René could hear her sister’s confession: “Merciful God, let me never again rise from this deathbed, and may Thy blessings be lavished on my brother, who has never shared my forbidden passion!” (108). At this, “I lost control of my senses”; upon reviving, he learns that his sister, “taken with a violent fever,” had asked never “to try to see her again” (108). 

    This time, for the first time, he “knew what it meant to shed tears for grief which was far from imaginary,” no longer self-imposed and self-exaggerated (109). “I even felt a kind of unexpected satisfaction in the fullness of my anguish, and I became aware, with a sense of hidden joy, that sorrow is not a feeling which consumes itself like pleasure”; “now that my sorrows were real, I no longer wished to die” (109). If “in every land the natural song of man is sad, even when it renders happiness,” the true return to nature must be sorrow, as only in it can man find beauty in sublimity, satisfaction in his natural restlessness (109). Amelia learns this too, in the convent. She writes to him that the regime of the convent—the regular chime of the church bell, the hymns, the waves of the ocean nearby, “the simplicity of my companions, the purity of their vows, the regularity of their life”—all act as “healing balm over my days” (110). Christianity “substitutes a kind of burning chastity in which lover and virgin are at one” (111). The religion of burning chastity parallels the nature of joy in sorrow, stability in restlessness. 

    The letter René had received came from the Mother Superior at the convent, informing him of Amelia’s death, “a victim of her zeal and charity,” as it was incurred while caring for her sisters, afflicted by a contagious disease. Chactas comforted him in his grief. Father Souël did not.

    He had expected pity, and Chactas had wept for him, but in Father Souël’s judgment “nothing in your story deserves the pity you are now being shown” (112). You are in love with your own illusions, dissatisfied with everything, “withdrawn from society, and wrapped up in idle dreams” (113). Melancholy does not make you superior to the world; “only those of limited vision can hate men and life” (113). As Father Aubry had told Atala, your griefs are “absolutely nothing” and your self-isolation in the woods consists only in neglect of your duties (113). Yes, saints have retreated to the wilderness, “but they were weeping and subduing their passions, while you seem to be wasting your time inflaming your own,” a “presumptuous youth” who thinks “man sufficient unto himself” (113). But “solitude is bad for the man who does not live with God,” increasing “the soul’s power while robbing it at the same time of every opportunity to find expression” (113). You have talent, but unless you “devote it to serving [your] fellow men, you will “first [be] punished by an inner misery,” and eventually by God (113). Father Souël’s love for René evinces the toughness of agape but does not extend to a call for conversion. He may have judged this premature.

    At this, Chactas smiles, recalling Father Aubry’s rebuke of his own sorrows. “My son, he speaks severely to both of us; he is reprimanding the old man and the young, and he is right…. Happiness can be found only in the common paths” (113). He tells a story of the Meschacebe, which overran its banks, destroying everything around it in a show of its power, only to become troubled at the solitude it had made for itself. “It longed again for the humble bed which nature had prepared for it, and it pined for the birds and the flowers, the trees and the streams which were once its modest companions along its peaceful course” (114). It is a Christian parable, a lesson in humility against ambitions of self-sufficient pride, and also a Rousseauian one, as man’s civilization evidences exactly such an attempt to master nature. The Meschacebe is the human heart.

    “René returned to his wife, but still found no happiness. Soon afterwards, along with Chactas and Father Souël, he perished in the massacres of the French and Natchez in Louisiana” (114).

    In Atala and René, Chateaubriand attempted to correct the French Romanticism he unintentionally spurred on by those very writings. They answer Rousseau, and even more immediately Goethe’s Sorrows of Young Werther. The Sturm und Drang of the thunderstorm in the forest; the ennui and self-torment, which tempt René to suicide and which goad Werner to commit it; the retreat to village life (for Werther, among German peasants, for René, American Indians); the love triangle (rivaled by a man, Chactas rivaled by God): these are the marks of Rousseauianism turned in on itself, finding misery in souls either too civilized to feel the natural moral sentiments of the savage or perhaps finding that even human nature purged of civil society’s cares can find no rest. 

    And like Goethe, Chateaubriand came to regret writing in this vein, for the same reason. The natural human capacity for imitation, noted by Rousseau, prevailed in their young readers. Werther touched off the “Werther Fever” in European youth, complete with merchandise and copycat suicides. Goethe denounced the “sickness” of the Romantic movement he had initiated, turning instead to a manly and measured classicism. Chateaubriand eventually wished he had never written either of the books, but especially René, which fostered an affectation of ennui in French youths that, well, bored him. But he also found the ‘ancient’ or ‘classical’ moderation and magnanimity of his Chactas and of the mature Goethe an insufficiently powerful antidote to the sorrows of the modern human soul and its psychic mirror, the rage of murderous revolutionaries. Chactas smiles once, but never laughs, and neither does any other person in these books. There is copious weeping, and a Mississippi forest of exclamation points at the end of sentences, indications of passion. In keeping with this, and again following his thought in the Essai, he would next extend his consideration of the answer offered by religion, writing The Genius of Christianity.

    With regard to Rousseau, Chateaubriand endorses several of his principal claims. With him, he holds that civilization, and especially the accumulation of knowledge, obscures the nature of man from men. He also regards the state of nature as a condition of fecundity and abundance, not scarcity; men in the state of nature enjoy freedom of will and hardiness of body. Sexual passion is dangerous, not liberating but enslaving. Savages endure few or none of the agonies civilized men experience; they do not commit suicide. (Atala does so, but only because the contradiction between her love and her religious vow to her mother seems irresolvable; she has been touched by civilization.)

    Philosophically and as an artist, Chateaubriand shares Rousseau’s conviction that facticity is not truth, or at least not the whole truth. In his eyes, his fictions are as true as his histories, and his Mémoires combine facts with fictions. A noble lie can be a true reflection of the nature of man.

    Chateaubriand departs from Rousseau in placing his savages within civil society, albeit primitive ones. They follow religion, there—worshipping many gods and one Great Spirit—also unlike Savage man according to Rousseau. Chateaubriand’s savages live poorly within the abundance of nature; they see the advantages of agriculture and, when shown how to do it, adopt it. They are not exactly poor in spirit, and indeed rich in natural spiritedness, in war-ready courage, even to the point of enduring torture. Yet they also see the difference between their courage and Christian courage, which goes beyond the endurance of one’s own agony and reaches out to bless the torturer. Some of them esteem that difference, accepting Christianity for their souls along with agriculture for their bodies.

    Chateaubriand insists that they need to do this because the physical and psychic ills of man inhere in his nature, even as they are exaggerated by civilization, and especially by modern civilization. Dualities, even antimonies, pervade all of nature, which is both beautiful and sublime, harmonious and stormy. This affects the question of natural right. For Rousseau, natural right consists of bodily well-being and self-preservation along with freedom of the mind and the natural sentiment of pity or compassion. If nature is sublime as well as beautiful, natural right as so conceived will not suffice. Divine right and divine law must supplement natural right and natural law, if human beings can be made to resist destroying one another with envious rage or ruining the foundation of the family with incestuous love, family love carried to its extreme because the passion of love knows no limits—the love seen symbolically in the souls of Chactas and Atala and literally in the souls of René and Amelia. 

    Chactas wonders, who gains more? The savage who becomes civilized or the civilized man who retreats to the savage life? He, the savage who became civilized, suffered greatly, steadied his soul with the morality of the ancients, took up the responsibilities of civil life. René, the civilized man who yearned for natural simplicity, found solitude miserable; after Father Souël’s reprimand, he too returned to civic life. Both resist the agapic appeal of Christianity. Chactas has experienced the Holy Spirit and received baptism; he seems to have been saved. René, although moved by Christianity, finds no happiness in the civil life he returns to. It may be that Chateaubriand does not think Christianity offers happiness in this life. It surely does not offer life in this life: René, Chactas, Atala, Father Aubry, and Father Souël all die violently, Atala by her own hand, the men by the hands of other men.

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    The Temptation of the West: Solzhenitsyn in America

    October 21, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn: Between Two Millstones: Book I: Sketches of Exile, 1974-1978. Peter Constantine translation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2018.

    Originally published in Social Science and Modern Society, Volume 56, Number 6, November/December 2019. 

     

    We know Solzhenitsyn the anti-Soviet dissident, Solzhenitsyn the chronicler of Leninist-Stalinist mass-murder and mass-incarceration, Solzhenitsyn the prophet of Western decline, Solzhenitsyn the Russian patriot and Christian witness. Here we meet Solzhenitsyn the writer, a man searching for a quiet place to gather his thoughts, refine them, and put them on paper. Between the ruthless tyranny of the East and the clamorous democracy of the West, he will not relinquish his vocations as dissident, prophet, witness, and patriot, but he needs to find a place where he can pursue these vocations in his way, the way of an heir to the legacies of Dostoevsky and Tolstoy, legacies deformed by two generations of partisan hacks. “I do not fit in with either system”; Christians seldom do, entirely, with any, and surely not with the modern ‘project,’ East or West.

    The exile he sketches began with his 1974 expulsion from the Soviet Union, the first and heaviest “millstone.” Solzhenitsyn published his sketches of his life there in The Oak and the Calf, which appeared a year later. The Communist-Party oligarchs (“a pack of horned devils flitting through the early dawn before the matin bell rings”) finally chose to persecute him from afar, having vainly tried imprisonment, poisoning, blandishments, and blackmail in Russia during the previous three decades. Hosted initially by the German Nobel Prize winner and recent president of PEN, Heinrich Böll, he immediately confronted an alien species of ‘writers,’ the Western journalists, whose “persistent tracking by photo and film crews, documenting my every step and move,” amounted to “the flip side of the relentless, but secret shadowing to which I was subjected at home” by the KGB. Although their “penchant for sensationalism” “saved me” by making it too costly for the Soviet regime to silence him, fundamentally any writer needs simple peace and quiet. By refusing most interviews (“Were they to ensnare me with glory?”), Solzhenitsyn meant no offense; nonetheless, what he intended only as “a literary defense mechanism” provoked media indignation. Under regimes of doctrinaire social egalitarianism, ‘celebrity’ bestowed by the princes of mass media takes the place of grace granted by God, its refusal anathematized as similarly sinful. He couldn’t avoid the censures, but at least he avoided “the danger of becoming a blatherer,” the temptation to issue statements on every passing ‘issue’ journalists through at him. “Political passion is embedded deep within me, and yet it comes after literature, it ranks lower.” To put it in language even ‘we moderns’ understand, Solzhenitsyn was playing the long game—knowing that what ‘the media’ giveth ‘the media’ can take away.

    Looking back on the situation from the vantage point of 1978, when he wrote Between Two Millstones, Solzhenitsyn remained grateful to the Russian novelist and fellow émigré Anatoli Kuznetsov, who likened a writer coming to the free West from the tyrannical East to a diver suffering from the bends, “coming from a high to a low pressure zone where one ran the risk of bursting.” “How right he was!” Above all, he knew, he must “continue working steeped in silence, not allowing the flame of writing to expire, not letting myself be torn to pieces, but to remain myself.” A writer’s discipline, but also a man’s, and a citizen’s: “It was so difficult to get used to the full freedom of life and to learn the golden rule of all freedom: to use it as little as possible.”

    Offered a quiet home in Norway, he and his wife reconnoitered, only to see that Soviet military forces would likely invade there first, if a European war broke out. Zurich made more sense; Lenin had lived there, before being smuggled back to Russia by the Germans as a knife aimed at the all-too-soft underbelly of the czarist regime during the Great War. Solzhenitsyn was writing his vast historical novel, The Red Wheel, early chapters of which would appear in his 1976 title, Lenin in Zurich. Residence in Switzerland would prove indispensable not only for the necessary historical research but for what every novelist needs: a sense of the place, its physical and moral atmosphere. Finally, however, he saw he could not stay. After a press conference presenting From Under the Rubble, a collection of essays critical of the Soviet regime written by himself and some fellow dissidents, the Swiss authorities notified Solzhenitsyn that in future he must request authorization to hold such a meeting from the Zurich police. He now understood why so many Soviet exiles had left Europe for America. Europe had lost it sense of civic freedom. “We had to move on.”

    But not before visiting a Swiss canton during the election of its chief magistrate, the Landammann. The winning candidate gave a fine, sober speech on the need never to surrender “to the folly of total freedom” while also never “making the state almighty.” In the face of the recent abandonment of the South Vietnamese people to the Communist North, raising the question of “whether America will remain loyal to its alliance with Europe,” Europeans must remember to associate their “individual freedoms” with “our obligations and self-defense”—a suggestion that the Swiss regime of self-defense by an armed and vigilant citizenry might deter Soviet-bloc aggression more effectively than the NATO alliance. More, the Landammann continued, “There cannot be a rational functioning state without a dash of aristocratic and even monarchic elements”—without a modern version of what Aristotle calls a ‘mixed’ regime, with its balance of popular representation, administrative expertise, and executive vigor: The Swiss Confederation, “now the oldest democracy in the world,” “did not spring from the ideas of the Enlightenment” but from experience, from “the ancient forms of communal life.” “This is the kind of democracy we [Russians] could do with,” Solzhenitsyn thought—a democracy resembling their own medieval town assemblies. Self-government in political communities small enough for personal knowledge of fellow-citizens: This was the best feature of Switzerland, of old Russia, and even, he would find, some parts of modern America. It is likely that Solzhenitsyn recalled the early Christian communes, as well.

    Before leaving Europe, Solzhenitsyn found himself embroiled in political controversies with Russian writers who were far from being journalists, each of whom understood democracy, and politics generally, in ways that diverged sharply from his own moral sensibilities. The first was the renowned physicist Andre Sakharov, who, very much like a man accustomed to thinking in abstractions, in formulae, criticized Solzhenitsyn for having advocated a transition period, frankly described as “authoritarian,” between the Soviet regime and a popularly-based ‘mixed’ regime. Sakharov wanted an immediate regime change from Communist oligarchy to parliamentary democracy, with no intermediate steps. For Solzhenitsyn, “the collapse of Russia in 1917 was like a fiery image before my eyes, the insane attempt at transforming our country to democracy in a single leap,” a leap into “instant chaos” that issued not in democracy but in the triumph of Lenin’s tyranny. “This thirst for ‘instant’ democracy was the impulse of the big-city desk-dwellers, who had no notion whatsoever of real people’s lives.” “In my view, democracy means the genuine self-government of the people, from the bottom up,” whereas social-democratic, scientistic and literary political commentators alike “see it as being the rule of the educated classes” who undertake to lead the people. Solzhenitsyn’s stance, however sensible, could only further irritate the journalists, who now pegged him as “a reactionary and a nationalist.” He was a sort of Christian Aristotelian, not only in his esteem for the ‘mixed regime,’ the regime Aristotle esteemed as the best practicable regime, but also in his insistence on the importance of fitting regime institutions to a given people’s way of life, its “spirit” (as Montesquieu termed it), it “culture.” A ‘liberal’ like Sakharov “was in fact related to the socialist wing…by way of the fathers of the Enlightenment.” “Russia’s moral development” couldn’t advance on abstractions generated by such unreasonable rationalism.

    A writer who should have understood the importance of culture was the émigré novelist Andrei Sinyavsky, a satirist who wrote under the pen name of Abram Tertz. Sinyavksy lived in Paris, where he edited the dissident journal Syntaxas. In its inaugural issue he wrote an article blaming Russia’s agony on Russia itself. “Even the lowest criminals—men who in their mindset are practically animals—revere their mothers,” Solzhenitsyn riposted. “But not Abram Tertz.” The two men remained sharply at odds for the remainder of Sinyavsky’s life, with Sinyavsky going so far as to assert that Solzhenitsyn’s exile was a KGB ruse. Solzhenitsyn was gentler in his critique of the celebrated émigré writer Vladimir Nabokov, who in a sense made the same error of “turning his back on Russia,” but not with contempt; Nabokov took a purely literary/esthetic stance, ignoring history for the cultivation of stylistic elegance. Although both a trained scientist and an accomplished novelist, Solzhenitsyn steered away from the pleasurable simplisms of both scientistic and literary politics—really anti- or a-political thought—by using political history as his intellectual ballast, keeping his mind on an even keel, provisioning himself to practice what Aristotle considered the preeminent political virtue, prudence.

    It transpired that his sudden, secret departure from Switzerland foiled yet another KGB plot to murder him—forgiving and forgetting never having served as leading characteristics of the Soviet regime-ethos. Moving his family first to Canada—that “timid giant pushed aside in the onrush of the daring and the ruthless,” “immersed in a slumber of oblivion”—he finally chose residence in the United States. After visiting Alaska (“too much of a national park steeped in the nineteenth century”), the family next stopped in northern California, where an “Old Believers” Russian Orthodox community would not allow them to worship with them in the church or to eat at the same table with the adults. But his most important ‘stop’ turned out to be a two-month stay at the Hoover Institution at Stanford University, where he delved into the vast collection of materials on the February Revolution of 1917, which preceded the Bolshevik Revolution, a year later.

    Alone in the archives, “My eyes opened as to what had really taken place.” Having studied the 1917-1918 ferment for some forty years, in preparation for composing the Red Wheel, he now made crucial discoveries that “caused a shift in my thinking that I did not expect.” Previously, Solzhenitsyn had “clung to the universally accepted view that Russia in February 1917 had achieved the freedom that generations had striven for, and that all of Russia rejoiced and nurtured this freedom, but alas, alas, only for eight months, as the Bolshevik fiends drowned that freedom in blood, steering the nation to ruin.” But as he perused the documents in the Hoover collection, he say “that Russia was inescapably lost… from the very first days of March,” as a powerless Provisional Government took direction from “a narrow, closed committee in Petrograd, itself “hiding behind the many thousands of noisy members of the larger Soviet.” “A beguiling pink cloud” of leftish opinion continues to shroud what really happened, to this day. Readers of the latest volume of the Red Wheel to be published in English, March 1917, will see how Solzhenitsyn integrated these new insights into his narrative.

    Although Solzhenitsyn frequently called for the institution of the rule of law in Russia, he never could accustom himself to its actual operation in the United States and in the West, generally. Facing important questions concerning translations and re-translations of his books, copyright tangles, and all the attendant difficulties, he found “the world of the Western law courts” to be “alien to me,” often because litigation was driven by calculations respecting the mass market of modern commercial democracy. Tocqueville would have understood the jarring effect of democratic egalitarianism on an aristocratic sensibility. For Tocqueville Christianity sharpens this conflict, having been revealed under aristocratic, hierarchic conditions amenable to truths delivered from ‘on high’ but being itself a teaching of equality, a revelation of the universal responsibility of all men “created equal” before God. One senses this tension in Solzhenitsyn’s soul, his life and work.

    For his part, when it came to the rule of law, Solzhenitsyn would come to laud the much smaller, local law courts of medieval Russia, where litigation remained on a human scale. The “megacities” of America could offer no such justice. In the hands of a writer like Sinyavsky, all of this would be the stuff of comedy, but for Solzhenitsyn, for whom writing remained a matter of life and death—physical and spiritual—the Western legal process was a torment, reanimating in him the Christian impatience with what men like Luther and Calvin (somewhat unfairly) regarded as Old-Testament legalism. “Legal battles are a profanation of the soul, an ulceration,” Solzhenitsyn thunders. “As the world has entered a legal era, gradually replacing man’s conscience with law, the spiritual level of the world has sunk.” In the courts as in politics, “I was torn by the never-ending conflict within me: to write or to do battle?” In modest defense of Western legalism, it must be said that these battles eventually turned out well for him, as his works have appeared in good translations, with profits now going where he intended them to go—often to persecuted Soviet writers and their families. He even found a big-city lawyer he respected, the Washington insider William Bennett Williams, who assisted in the liberation of Russian dissident Aleksandr Ginzburg from a Soviet prison.

    A friend found him a suitable property in rural Cavendish, Vermont, where he built a house for his family. His new home proved his refuge from modernity’s pressures, a place where he could think and write. Initially, his new neighbors took offense at the fence he built around his property, but he followed the smart suggestion of Governor Richard Snelling, who advised him to explain himself at the next town meeting. He not only explained his family’s unique security needs, but he took the opportunity to explain the difference between the words ‘Russian’ and ‘Soviet,’ the former being to the latter “as ‘man’ is to ‘disease.'” “Immediately, the tension in the town eased, and a staunch neighborliness was established,” reaffirming Solzhenitsyn’s esteem for the personal touch of small-town life. He nonetheless continued to long for return to his own country, rightly anticipating that it would happen someday.

    After making peace with his neighbors in early 1977, Solzhenitsyn’s life settled into a sort of routine. He spent most of his time gratefully at work on the Red Wheel, a work that “encompasses all of Russia—Russia in flux.” It was crucially important to write it all down, to look back, to understand and assess a time when “many people could not see what was coming upon them, not even a day ahead.” If Russians were to have even a slight chance of fostering a decent life for themselves in the future, they needed a reliable account of the errors of the past, the malice of those who exploited those errors, and the rare heroes who saw clearly and acted with acumen and justice. They needed a civic education to prepare their souls for the practice of self-government. At the same time, Solzhenitsyn also needed to tend to his reputation among Russians, not for reasons of petty vanity but because he needed to be trusted as a reliable witness and researcher, a truth-teller—precisely because he had indispensable moral-political and spiritual truths to tell them.

    Unfortunately, many of his fellow exiles and dissidents distrusted him. They didn’t know him personally, but there was more: “In truth we had sprung from different roots, expressed different aspirations, and had almost nothing in common but the time and place of action.” Most of Solzhenitsyn’s cohorts were secularized, urban intellectuals who “remained unresponsive to the plight of the Russian countryside and especially to the renewed persecution of the Orthodox Church.” While many of the dissidents “took advantage of every person’s natural right to leave a place they do not want to live” (emphasis added), they turned their backs on the Russians, and the Russia, they left behind. They eschewed Russia as a place for Christians, and for the Orthodox Christianity that Solzhenitsyn never ceased considering the highest form of Christianity, even if his was a ‘genial orthodoxy,’ esteeming all decent forms of worship as bulwarks against atheism. Not for the new generation of exiles was the prayer Solzhenitsyn composed and recited with his sons in Vermont: “Grant us, O Lord, to live in health and strength, our minds bright, until the day when you will open our path home to Russia, to labor and to sacrifice ourselves so that she may recover and flourish.”

    The dissident exiles found a sympathetic audience among the similarly secularized intellectuals in the West, who welcomed them, “offered financial support, and heaped [them] with praise.” Solzhenitsyn, however, offended American secularists with his Harvard commencement address in 1978. “For thirty years in the USSR, and for four years now in the West, I kept slashing and hacking away at Communism, but in these last years I had also seen much in the West that was alarmingly dangerous, and here I preferred to talk about that.” At Harvard he publicized his dissatisfaction with Western legalism, a standard “far lower than the true moral yardstick”; he criticized the mis-definition of freedom as “unbridled passion” and its consequence, the weakening of “a sense of responsibility before God and society.” It is well to speak of human rights, he observed, but more urgent to speak of human obligations; few in the West of 1978 were. He judged the likely consequences to be harsh. “The reigning ideology, that prosperity and the accumulation of material riches are to be valued above all else, is leading to a weakening of character in the West, and also to a massive decline in courage and the will to defend itself, as was clearly seen in the Vietnam War, not to mention a perplexity in the face of terror”—that is, the increasing acts of terrorism committed by Muslim militants against Western people. Most deeply, and perhaps most gratingly to his critics, Solzhenitsyn traced all of this to Enlightenment “rationalist humanism,” the “notion that man is the center of all that exists, and that there is no Higher Power above him.” In this “irreligious humanism” the democratic West and the oligarchic East join hands. “The moral poverty of the twentieth century comes from too much having been invested in sociopolitical changes, with the loss of the Whole and the High.” To lose the Whole and the High is to divest oneself of riches greater than those won by capitalists or promised by socialists.

    It is almost needless to say that such criticisms found few sympathetic echoes. “It turns out that democracy expects to be flattered. When I called out ‘live not by lies!’ in the Soviet Union, that was fair enough, but when I called out ‘live not by lies!’ in the United States, I was told to go take a hike.” All the more reason to write, “When I return home to Russia one day, I am certain that everything will fall back into place; it is for that moment that I live and write.”

    This first volume of Between Two Millstones ends with Solzhenitsyn’s account of his struggle to vindicate his reputation against KGB slanderers, one a former friend from childhood. Physical and spiritual exile from Soviet Russia and spiritual exile from the West were the exactions Providence inflicted on the writer who took up the task of prophetic witness against the world of his time.

    In this book above all others, perhaps, Solzhenitsyn shows how he subtly shifted the emphasis of Russian Orthodox Christianity toward a path of greater sobriety. Just as Roman Catholic Christianity brings Aristotelian philosophy in as a supplement to Christian spirituality, thereby fulfilling the Christian command to strive for the prudence of serpents along with the innocence of doves, Orthodox Christianity brings in Platonic philosophy. Rightly understood, Platonic philosophy equally commends prudential reasoning on moral and political matters. (Hence the term political philosophy.) But Orthodox Christians thinkers too often avail themselves not so much of Platonism but of Neoplatonism, with its impatience for undertaking a spiritual and intellectual ascent beyond the conventions, the traditions, of the Christian’s immediate ‘worldly’ surroundings. It’s a bit too easy to be a saint in a desert; the Apostles set out to talk with their fellow-subjects in Imperial Rome, seeking to persuade them, not to leave them behind. In lauding and, more tellingly, practicing the life of moderation or self-limitation, strict justice, unshakable courage, and practical wisdom, in partnering with his wife to hold their family together, and in looking to the founding of a ‘mixed’ and balanced regime that respects long-settled ways of life  including local self-government and work on the land, and in always intending to return to his own people, his own beloved country, Solzhenitsyn faithfully upheld his very Aristotelian and Christian agapic witness “between two millstones.” He hoped that someday Russians themselves would uphold that witness, take up its sacrificial burdens but also its true honor.

    Filed Under: Nations

    Chateaubriand and Political Philosophy

    October 15, 2020 by Will Morrisey

    François-René Vicomte de Chateaubriand: Essai Politique, Historique, et Morale, sur les Revolutions Anciennes et Modernes considerées dans leurs Rapports avec la Revolution Française de nos Jours. London: J. Deboffe et al., 1797.

    François-René Vicomte de Chateaubriand:  An Historical, Political, and Moral Essay on Revolutions, Ancient and Modern.  Miami: HardPress, 2019. Originally translated anonymously by “an English lady” and published by Henry Colburn, London, 1815.

    Heinrich Meier: “Why Is Political Philosophy?” In Meier: Political Philosophy and the Challenge of Revealed Religion. Robert Berman translation. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2017. Chapter One.

     

    Note: The English translator abridges the French edition, cutting more than 100 pages and combining parts of chapters into one; this reduces the number of chapters from Chateaubriand’s 138 to 52. Chateaubriand divided his book into two parts, the first on the revolution that overthrew the Athenian monarchy, replacing it with a democracy, and the second on the revolution effected by Philip of Macedon and Alexander the Great. Part I has 71 chapters, Part II has 57. The translator ignores these divisions. Accordingly, I have at times cited sentences from the French that do not appear in the translation; I have also changed the occasional English word in the translation to make it more faithful to the French. The parenthetical page references place the French edition first, the English second; where there is no reference to the English, it wasn’t translated.

    The book is the first of a projected two-volume work. The second volume, Études our Discours Historiques sur la Chute de L’Empire Romain, la Naissance et le Progrès de Christianisme, et l’Invasion des Barbares was published in 1831.

     

     

    Meier begins his chapter with Aristophanes’ Clouds, which satirizes pre-Socratic philosophy. Philosophy takes nature as its object of inquiry. But it lacks self-knowledge; philosophers make themselves absurd even as they claim to hold their studies to the standard of reason. For this reason, philosophers cannot defend themselves, or philosophy itself, against ridicule or worse, persecution. Nor can philosophers offer a rational justification their way of life. Even Socrates so lacks self-knowledge that he never mentions the soul at any time in the play. 

    Meier takes Aristophanes’ play as a warning, but a friendly warning, to the philosophers. Socrates himself took note, becoming what we now consider Socratic, no longer the ‘pre-Socratic’ Socrates but a philosopher who turned his soul around, not away from philosophy but toward political philosophy. Political philosophy still inquires into nature, but it no longer overlooks human nature, which comes to sight in the polis, in the political community. As a way of life distinct from the way of life, the regime, of the polis, philosophy must offer a political defense of itself if it is to continue within the framework of human life. More, the philosophic way of life must justify itself philosophically, rationally, and that justification must survive the scrutiny of philosophers themselves. In taking its first subject as human nature, human nature situated in the political community, and in defending itself both before the bar of the polis and the inquiry of philosophers, philosophy will bring philosophers to the self-knowledge they had hitherto lacked. 

    This means that the polis has done philosophers and their way of life a signal if unintended favor. By its ridicule, even by its persecution, it has spurred philosophic minds to attain more of the wisdom that they love. It has pushed them not only to greater prudence or practical wisdom but to greater sophia, theoretical wisdom, a better understanding of nature. 

    The blessing does not come unmixed. Like philosophy, the polis seeks the right, the good, the best way to live. Athens or Sparta? The United States of America or the People’s Republic of China? And it seeks self-understanding; it wants ‘I am an Athenian’ or ‘I am a Spartan’ to mean something. The polis in antiquity differs from philosophy because it bases itself not on natural reason but on divine revelation, laws said to have been revealed to its founder by the gods. The philosophic way of life, the way of unreserved questioning, departs from the political way of life (no matter what the regime), departs from the sway of opinion, from authority, tradition, faith—things not be questioned but to be defended unhesitatingly although not thoughtlessly, and with civic courage, ‘the courage of one’s convictions.’ The philosophic way moderates the passions for the sake of a sort of intellectual mania. The political way moderates the passions for the sake of prudent discourse on what course of action the polis should follow, and for the sake of ‘manning up’ in order to act decisively and vigorously in pursuing that course. The philosophic way of life looks to nature as its standard and to reason as its means of knowing nature better; the political way of life looks to God or the gods as its standard and to revelation, especially revealed law, as its means of knowing God better, of getting closer to Him.

    In its perennial challenge to philosophy, the political way of life thus proves indispensable to philosophers by spurring them to become and stay fully philosophic, self-knowing inquirers into human nature, and from that to nature as a whole. As Meier writes, “political philosophy is the part of philosophy in which the whole of philosophy is in question.” One then wonders, is philosophy also indispensable to the political theology of the polis? Is it in any way indispensable to faith in revelation, or is it the enemy of revelation? Does philosophic questioning of revelation strengthen the self-understanding of the pious, or merely corrupt them by tossing them into doubt’s boundless sea? Meier does not address that side of the matter in this chapter. In Christianity, an apostle of which warned against the vanity of philosophy—vain because it always seeks but never finds—the philosophic way of life appears wrong, simply. Nonetheless, if (as another apostle puts it) in the beginning was the Logos, and the Logos was with God, and the Logos was God, then God evidently proceeds ‘logically,’ never violating the principle of self-contradiction. A God who never contradicts Himself is a God one may trust, have faith in. The core activity of philosophers, rational thought, might find some divine support, even as the commitment to revelation insists on limiting the always-tentative results of reasoned inquiry by the things revelation asserts: hence theology an inquiry into the logic, the reason, of God. Political theology inquires into that reason insofar as it pertains to ruling and to being ruled, never forgetting that the prophets themselves argue with God, and sometimes persuade Him. God even questions Himself, as when His Son asks His Father, “Why have Thou forsaken Me?”

    In his Essay, Chateaubriand presents himself as a philosopher, a philosopher in exile from his country. He was not, however, exiled by his fellow citizens for philosophizing; he fled the French revolutionaries because they had killed several in his family, giving him clear cause to fear for his own life. In England for the past four years, he has no friend to console him and no one to listen to him. “Solitaries live in their hearts,” surviving “on their own substance” like hibernating animals (iv). The heart is the seat of morality; a solitary philosopher will rely on the resources of his character. Being a philosopher, he will also think about morality, inquire into it. In this inquiry, he overcomes his solitude with the society of ideas: In “opposing philosophy to philosophy, reason to reason, principle to principle…I have only exposed the doubts of an honnête homme” (v). In Rousseauian solitude he engages philosophers, theologians, and political men dialectically, while remaining an aristocrat, a man of professed honor, accustomed to the responsibilities of rule. He is, moreover, a man “who would be useful to my fellows, so that they may begin to judge for themselves” the philosophers, theologians, and political men; he would strengthen their minds and hearts for that task (iv). In dedicating his book to “all the parties” in France, and perhaps more broadly in philosophy, theology, and politics generally, he stands, as a political philosopher does, to one side of impassioned partisans, but as one who desires the good for all of them.

    “Solitaries live in their hearts.” A Frenchman could not write that sentence in France in the 1790s without thinking of Rousseau, especially as Rousseau presents himself in his Reveries of a Solitary Walker. As it happens, Meier holds up Rousseau as an exemplary specimen of the political philosopher in modernity (the other is Nietzsche)—a thinker who, precisely in his account of his solitary reveries, never loses sight of the political, the topic of his Discourses and his Social Contract. Among the thoughts Chateaubriand will suggest to his readers is the Rousseau’s most ‘solitary’ writings and his most political writings must be brought into dialogue with one another, and that the revolutionaries have misunderstood the snatches of conversation they’ve overheard.

    In the main body of the text, his first words are, “Who am I?” (3,1) Chateaubriand explains who he is, discloses his self-knowledge, by ‘objectifying’ himself, by describing himself in the third person. “He,” he tells us, began as a ‘pre-Socratic,’ having been “born with an ardent passion for the sciences,” “devot[ing] to them the labors of [my] youth” (3,1). He has long “been consumed by a thirst for knowledge,” by the philosophic mania, the philosophic eros (3,1). And he took the Socratic ‘turn,’ experienced the Socratic ‘conversion,’ before his forced exile, having “torn himself away from the enjoyments of fortune”—his aristocratic privileges—to “go beyond the seas, to contemplate the greatest spectacle which can be offered to the eye of the philosopher, to meditate on free man in a state of nature and in society, placed near each other on the same soil” (3,1). He alludes to his travels in America in 1791, where he met both Amerindians and newly-independent Americans, some of them in very civil society indeed, including a dinner with President Washington. Meier too compares philosophic inquiry to a voyage, and the image of breaking away from the traditions, the customs, the beliefs of one’s country has long been associated with such inquiry. Now in exile, in a forced separation from French traditions, customs, and beliefs, he has learned, “in the daily experience of adversity,” to “estimate the prejudices of life” (3,1). Not only the voluntary but the involuntary voyage, not only the beautiful and longed-for but the sublime, the work of overcoming, may serve the philosophic way of life. 

    He returns to writing in the first person, to matters of his soul. In England, in “the situation in which I am placed,” he looks at things not with an impassioned and prejudiced but a “tranquil eye”; he finds his exile to be “favorable to truth” (4,2). “Without desires and without fear as I am, I no longer indulge in the chimeras of felicity, and mankind can inflict on me no greater evils than I experience” (4,2). He compares “misfortune” to a mountain in a torrid climate; climbing it, “you see nothing before you except barren rocks,” but at the summit “you perceive the heavens above your head and the kingdom of Kashmir at your feet” (4,2): The nature of the pre-Socratics and the political nature of human life, both visible to the political philosopher.

    “This observation, which at the first glance may appear somewhat too personal, is nevertheless indispensable” (5,2). Indispensable, because the political philosopher begins with persons, including himself, but also because the philosopher must be politic: He must lessen the reader’s “unfortunate distrust, which puts us on our guard against an author’s opinions (5,2)”. Not being a god, being at most an all-too-human imitation of the self-sacrificing God, Christ, he cannot command that trust. But he can request it. The reader “in his turn [should] make some sacrifice to me.” “O you, who read me, banish your passions for a moment, while you peruse this dissertation on the greatest questions which can occupy the attention of mankind (5,2)”. Think along with me. “If you sometimes feel your blood take fire, shut the book and wait till your heart beats calmly before you begin to read again (5,2-3)”. In return, Rousseau-like, “I promise that my sentiments shall proceed from a heart as devoid of prejudice as an human heart can be” and a mind that “will always reason upon principles (6,3)”. I sincerely intend to be “useful” to you (6,3). “I am not a writer of any sect, and I can easily conceive that there are very honest people whose opinions differ from mine” (8n.4n.).” Perhaps true wisdom consists in being not without principles, but without fixed opinions” (8n.,4n.)—to be, as ancient philosophers would say, zetetic.

    Having pled for a fair hearing, he proceeds to outline the plan of his book, a plan consisting of six points. First, “what revolutions have heretofore occurred in the governments of mankind,” what was “the state of society” in which they occurred, and “what has been the influence of those revolutions on the age in which they occurred, and on the ages which have succeeded”? (6,3) Second, are there any revolutions among these which, “from the spirit, moeurs, and the lights of the time, can be compared with the French one”? (6,3) Third, “what were the primitive causes”—the origin, the archē—of “this revolution, and those which effected its sudden development”? (7,4). In this, Chateaubriand’s later readers will see not only the political philosophers prior to him but also ahead, to his cousin by marriage Alexis de Tocqueville, whose The Old Regime and the Revolution remarks the importance of the interaction between governments and civil societies in modern states, which are no longer the small, tightly organized poleis of antiquity, where political philosophy first came to sight.

    Fourth “What is now the government of France,” in 1797, “is it founded on true principles,” and will it endure? (7). Fifth, if the current regime of France does endure, what effect will it have on the nations and the other governments of Europe? Finally, if the regime is destroyed, what effect will that have? While “much has been written on the French revolution, yet each faction having been satisfied by decrying its rival, the subject is still as new as it had never been discussed” (7,4). Above the partisans–Republicans, Constitutionalists, Girondists, Royalists, and yes, his fellow emigrés— there is the philosophic judge. The political philosopher is indispensable because “the period of individual felicities is past,” as “the little ambition and confined interest of a single man sink into nothingness before the general ambition of nations and the interest of the human race” (8,4). In this age of democratization, egalitarianism, political mass movements which might be likened to shifts in the earth’s techtonic plates, you can no longer “hope to escape the calamities of the present age by retired moeurs and the obscurity of your life” (8,4); Epicureanism is no longer an option. Now, “friend is torn from friend, and the retreat of the sage resounds with the fall of thrones” (8,5). With no friendship, the possibility of the kind and just dialectic of the political philosopher may become possible only with his readers; with no friendship, there can also be no political life, no trust among citizens. “We are sailing along an unknown coast, in the midst of darkness and the storm” (8,5). Nonetheless, “with the torch of past revolutions in our hand, we shall boldly enter into the darkness of future ones” (8,9).

    We are undertaking this sailing, philosophers and citizens alike. “Every one,” not only philosophers, “therefore has a personal interest in considering these questions with me, because his existence depends upon them” (8,5). “My subject is a chart which must be studied while in danger,” the danger of European man in 1797, as the Jacobin Terror subsides but wars continue on the Continent and, as it will happen, Napoleon is to come (8,5). Only with such study can “the sagacious pilot ascertain the point we have left, the place in which we are, and the one to which we are steering, so that in case of shipwreck we may save ourselves on some island where the tempest cannot assail us” (9,5). That island “is a conscience without reproach” (9,5) We will know ourselves, and know ourselves to have done our part. It is impossible not to see in this Tocqueville’s work, sixty years later, and beyond it the still worse terrors of the century which followed him, and quite possibly of our own century, as well.

    Chateaubriand supplements his account of his plan with an account of his method. “A deficiency in method is the general fault of political works, though there is no subject which requires more order and clarity” (10,5). His own method has five features: an examination of “the remote and  immediate causes of each revolution”; the “historical and political parties” involved in each; “the state of moeurs and sciences” in each nation, and “such as were generally prevalent among the human race at the moment of each revolution”; the causes “which extended or confined” the influence of the revolution; and the similarity or difference between that revolution and the French Revolution, “in order thereby to form a common focus, to which all the scattered rays of morality, history and politics may converge” (10,5-6). The modern, French Revolution will serve as the touchstone for each revolution analyzed in terms of its origins, the factions that contended within it, the hearts and minds of the nation revolutionized and of humanity generally, and its influence on other nations.

    What is a revolution? It is a regime change, that is, “a total change in the government of a nation, whether from a monarchical to republican, or republican to monarchic” regime (10,6). In true revolutions, moreover, “the spirit of the peoples changes,” not only the government. “Indeed, if the spirit of the people does not change, what does it matter if they were agitated for a few moments in their misery, and that their name, or that of their master, is changed?” (11) By focusing our attention on regimes and regime change, the study of revolution, Chateaubriand insists, as political philosophers since Socrates have done, that his inquiry has paramount importance philosophically. “If the greatest subject be that from which the greatest number of natural truths may be deduced; and if by summing up historical truths we are led to a solution of the problem of man, was there ever an object more worthy of philosophy than the plan laid down for this work?” (13,8) Boldly, he claims “I will conduct the reader by a path of philosophy hitherto untrodden, in which I promise him important discoveries and new views of mankind” (14-15,9). Yet he remains not only Socratic in thinking of politics but in his ‘zeteticism.’ “By my title of an Essay”—that is, an attempt, an effort, in the spirit not only of the ancient, Socrates, but of the modern, Montaigne—I “have publicly avowed my inability; but I shall be sufficiently gratified in having pointed out the road to those of superior genius” (13,8-9). A road Tocqueville did not neglect to take.

    Before turning to the revolutions of ancient Greece, Chateaubriand briefly considers human ‘pre-history.’ The Amerindians Columbus saw were “far from being in a state of nature” (15,10); they were, however, for the most part stuck in barbarism. Nor had they made much progress by the time Chateaubriand arrived. Why? “Nature has denied them flocks and herds of cattle, those first legislators of mankind”; those nations and tribes that had attained civilization lived “precisely in those districts in which there was a species of domesticated animal” (15n.,10n.). Herders learn to rule by ruling animals. In the forests of North America there was no space for pastureland. From the Fertile Crescent to Egypt to Greece, human beings could learn to rule, could achieve civilization.

    He excludes Asia from his consideration. The Assyrians, Medes, and Persians, who “built their power on the ruin of each other,” conquered then lost great empires under tyrannical regimes (24,14). “Let the crimes of tyrants and the misfortunes of slaves sleep in equal obscurity and oblivion.” Greece was where republics developed and maintained themselves for a long time, “a most interesting subject for the consideration of the philosopher” (25,14). “If the causes of their establishment had been transmitted to us by history, we might be able to obtain the solution of the famous political problem: What is the original convention of society?” (26,15) Chateaubriand rejects Rousseau’s solution—a social contract founded upon the general will. “To establish this train of reasoning, must we not suppose an association already existing? Would a vagrant savage, taken from his deserts, to whom the doctrine of mine and thine is unknown, pass all at once from natural to civil liberty?” (27,15) No: the notion of liberty understood in terms of justice and property is too abstract for a creature that, as in Rousseau, lacks speech and reason. 

    Primitive man first organized under monarchy, as “not one of the savage hordes, which has been found upon the globe, existed under a popular government” (28,16). It may be that these hordes “almost immediately tired” of their kings and called for “some valiant or sagacious citizen,” some lawgiving founder, to address the problem (28,16). Either way, how did they begin to conceive of civil, as distinguished from natural, liberty? It wasn’t “public opinion” that overthrew the regimes of Homeric Greece; only royalty itself could have abolished royalty (30,18). Why? The monarchic regimes were unstable. The order of succession was easily violated, and as a consequence, monarchs lost their power to “the spirit of the rich,” a usurping and factitious spirit (33,19). “It is a feature common to all revolutions, in the republican sense, that they have rarely begun on the part of the people (33,19). “It has always been the nobility, who, in proportion to their wealth and influence, first attacked the sovereign power,” whether out of envy, resentment of corruption in high places, libido dominandi, or the Fate of the tragedians which blinds monarchs to their own good (33,19). 

    After that first, oligarchic, revolution, “the people, oppressed by their new master, soon repent of having seated a multitude of tyrants in the place of one legitimate king” (33,19). Under these circumstances, “the people eject them as a disgraceful faction, and the state is changed into a republic, or returns to monarchy, according to its moral feeling” (34,19-20). In addition, and consistent with his claim that kings themselves undermined monarchy, a king established the Amphictyonic Council, which consisted of “deputies of the people,” an institution “calculated to generate the idea of republican forms among the nations which it represented” and giving that idea an institutional ‘space’ in which to gather authority (34,20). But “the great and real reason” for revolution in Greece was that Greek poleis “never were real monarchies” in the first place (35,21). Chateaubriand promises an explanation of this claim in a later volume. 

    Whatever its causes, the effects of the republican revolution “was far from producing happiness to Greece,” resulting rather in “a state of anarchy” wherein the well-organized ‘few’ soon regained rule of the disorganized ‘many’ (37,22). “Sparta alone” had in Lycurgus a man who combined the qualities of “a revolutionist and a legislator,” enabling his country to enjoy “the fruits of its new constitution” immediately (37,22). For their part, the Athenians “habituated themselves by degrees to popular government, passing slowly from a monarchy to a republic,” avoiding the miseries of most Greek poleis while never attaining the stability of the Spartan regime (38,23). Their regime was always “a mixture of truth and error” (38,23). Theirs was the polis that most resembled modern France, “liv[ing] in a perpetual state of trouble,” with “excessive” “antipathy between the rich and poor” (39,23-24). Modernity has, if anything, made this worse. “In this age of philanthropy we have declaimed too much against fortune. The poor of every state are infinitely more dangerous than the rich, and often less valuable members of society.” (39,24)

    Democracy in Athens, as in France, led to overreaction. In Athens Draco, “an inexorable philosopher, was fixed upon to frame laws for humanity” (39,24). But “he considered passions as crimes; and equally punished, with the utmost severity, the weak and the wicked; by which he appeared to pass sentence of death upon the human race” (39,24). Such “sanguinary laws, like the fatal decrees of Robespierre, were favorable to insurrection” (40,24). As in France, “this reign of terror passed away; but it left behind it relaxation and weakness” (40,24). Unlike France, however, the Athenians turned to the gods, who “filled the consciences of the people with dread” (40,25). “So necessary is religion to man!” (40,25) Chateaubriand exclaims; the atheism of France has resulted in a much worse outcome. The Greeks turned to “a sage named Epimenides,” who wisely “built temples to the gods, offered sacrifices to them, and poured the balm of religion into the secret recesses of the heart” (41,25). “He did not treat as superstitious what tends to diminish the number of our miseries; he knew that the popular statute, and the obscure penates, which console the unfortunate, were more useful to humanity than the volume of the philosopher, who knows not how to wipe away a tear” (41,25). The “philosopher” Draco, like Robespierre and the Enlightenment philosophes who inspired him, foolishly rejected religion, overlooking the heart’s portion of the human soul. They didn’t understand human nature, and thus failed to be adequately philosophic. 

    It took Solon to design more lasting political institutions. Chateaubriand concurs with Aristotle and Montesquieu in considering mixed regimes to be “the best”; “man, in a state of society, is himself a complex being, and to a multitude of passions there should be a multitude of restraints” (43,26). Athens “really possessed what France pretended to have acquired in our days—the most democratic constitution that ever existed among any people,” wherein the people assembled as a body to frame their own laws. France, a modern state, can do no such thing (43,26); accordingly, it has had, at best, representative governments, never a democracy. But this pretended democracy, in reinforcing its pretense, divided the property of the rich and paid money the people owed to usurers. Solon resisted demands to partition property equally but did remit all debts. Neither policy was strictly just, but Solon’s policy enabled landed wealth to survive even as it injured monied wealth, and that, Chateaubriand judges, shows the superiority of antiquity over modernity, of the more moderate habits of the landed wealthy who often dominated ancient poleis the limitless desire for acquisition money beckons men to satisfy in the modern states.

    Chateaubriand moves from the political to the moral dimensions of the revolutions in Athens and in France. “Purity appeared at Athens to be indispensable in the women, who were to give virtuous citizens to the state, and divorce was only permitted on very rigid conditions” (44,26). Under the republican regime in France, however, a woman “who wantonly offered her person to husband after husband” was somehow deemed no “less likely to prove an excellent mother” (44,26). As for the men, in Solon’s democracy they were judged unfit for public office and even “the benefits of the temple” if they exhibited “depravity of morals” (44-45,27). “The magistrate, who appears before the people in a state of intoxication, shall be instantly put to death” under Athenian law (45,27). “These decrees were undoubtedly not made for France, or what would have become of the whole constituent assembly on the night of the 4th of August, 1789?” (45,27-28) when the legislators abolished feudalism by eliminating the seigneurial rights of the nobility and the tithes of the Catholic Church. There could be no mixed regime, after that, and therefore no political check on the passions of the people. “The French, who are fanatics in their admiration of antiquity, seem to have borrowed all its vices without any of its virtues,” “naturalizing among them[selves] the devastations and murders of Rome and Athens, without attaining the grandeur of those republics,” thereby imitating “the tyrants, who, to embellish their country, caused the ruins and tombs of Greece to be transported thither,” in anticipation of Hitler’s pillages 150 years later (45,28).

    Solon exiled himself after founding the new regime, to see if Athenians could keep their new democracy, govern themselves without the guidance of their local sage. The factions promptly returned, factions Chateaubriand compares with those of revolutionary France. There was the Mountain party, which “wished for pure democracy”—the “Jacobins of Athens” (48,29). There was the Valley party, oligarchs who called themselves aristocrats. And there was the Coast party, consisting of merchants who did business by trading throughout the Mediterranean; they wanted a mixed regime; “they acted the part of the Moderés” during the French Revolution (48,30). “Thus Athens was nearly in the same situation as republican France” (49,30). Even the two ‘moderate’ parties had similar leaders—not really moderate so much as persons (as Chateaubriand nicely puts it) “remarkable for the versatility of their principles,” who quarreled with the other party leaders and eventually sank “into obscurity beneath historical notice” (52,32). “Such is commonly the fate of men without character” (52,32).

    Upon his return, Solon found that “each person was a faction unto himself, and though all agreed in hating the last constitution, all differed from each other as to the mode of régime to be substituted for it”—exactly like the French during and long after their republican revolution (54,33). Mistaking the “patriotic exterior” of the democratic leader for his nature, Solon favored Pisistratus, who went to the length of inflicting injuries upon himself in order to inflame popular passions in his favor and then, “having disarmed the citizens,” seized military power and “reigned over Athens with full power, unrestricted by republican principles” (55-56,35). “A democracy no longer exists when a military force is active in the interior of a state,” as for example when a Napoleon arises (55,35).. Indeed, as with Napoleon, so with Pisistratus: “Victory will always be on the side of the popular party, when it is directed by a man of genius; because this faction possesses an influence above others through the brutal energy of the multitude, to whom virtue has no charm, and guilt no remorse” (57,35). Unfortunately for the tyrant, “success does not insure happiness,” as Pisistratus was driven out by rivals, then recalled (57,35). “The storms, which roar around tyrants, twice forced Pisistratus from his throne, and he was twice restored by the people” (57,35). He managed to survive, passing his sovereignty to his two sons, exiling both the moderates and the self-styled aristocrats—even as the French revolutionaries drove out men of Chateaubriand’s class. One of his sons, Hippias, turned bloodthirsty, and some of the democrats who were not killed in this latest purge jointed the moderates and oligarchs in exile. “But they were more fortunate than the French emigrants” who fled Robespierre’s Terror, “for they carried their riches with them, and consequently, in the estimation of the world, their virtues” (61,37). Joining together, the Athenian exiles obtained military assistance form Sparta. Predictably, the Lacedaemonians tried to take Athens for themselves; failing this, they also failed at restoring Hippias, who then turned to the Persian general and satrap Artaphernes, whose assault only served to consolidate Athenian democracy. These events parallel the wars undertaken against the French republic by European monarchs unified the otherwise factitious French. With his older contemporary James Madison, Chateaubriand sees that republican liberty is to faction what fire is to air. Athenian democrats and French republicans could only escape faction through war, but sustained war would make military forces active not only outside but within the country, whether an ancient polis or a modern state. And army officers threaten republicanism.

    Why was each Athenian a faction unto himself? It isn’t only a matter of the moral condition of Athenians, or even of Greeks. It is a matter of human nature. “The thirst for liberty and for tyranny are mixed together in the heart of man by the hand of nature: independence for oneself, slavery for all the others, is the devise—the watchword, the motto—”of the human type” (63). In Platonic terms, thumos or spiritedness, the part of the soul that so-to-speak lies between logos or reason and epithumia or appetites, can become the servant of reason, the means by which reason rules the appetites, or the servant of the appetites, the means by which they rule reason, turning it into a means of calculation for self-interested acquisition. Spiritedness ruled by practical reason, prudence, finds its exercise in political rule, in the measured pursuit of justice. Spiritedness ruled by the appetites turns slavish among the weak-spirited, tyrannical among those of stronger spirit. 

    The Lacedaemonian regime founded by Lycurgus differed from that of Athens because it more thoroughly reflected the design of the lawgiver, not the mere “turn of affairs” (65,39). Further that founder was “the greatest genius that has existed” (65,39), in Chateaubriand’s estimation, a man “ignorant of nothing which could affect mankind,” a political genius rivaled only by Newton, the genius of natural philosophy (67n.,41n.). When the Jacobins imitated his laws, they failed to consider that “what was possible in a small nation, not yet far removed from the state of nature” cannot be “equally practicable in an ancient kingdom, containing twenty-five millions of inhabitants” (66,40). Each of these differences is decisive. “The Lacedaemonians possessed the immorality of a nation existing without civil forms—an immorality rather to be called a disorder than real corruption” (66,40). It retained its “vigorous coarseness” but now had institutions to give that energy a more just direction (66,40). The French, by contrast, were “legally immoral,” that is, accustomed to living under laws that were themselves corrupting (66,40). “In this case the woof is worn, and when you attempt to stretch the cloth, it tears in every part.” Thus “the most sublime constitution of one community may be execrable in another” (66-67,40-41). 

    With respect to morality, Lycurgus “left his countrymen their gods, their kings, and their popular assemblies,” all long established (69,42). “He did not cause all the chords of the human heart to vibrate by imprudently attacking every establishment,” nor did he “undertake his labors amidst the disturbances of war, which engender every sort of illiberality” (69,42). Nor did he “murder the citizens in order to convince them that his new laws were efficacious; he even behaved kindly to those, who carried their hatred of his innovations so far as to strike him” (69-70,43); Aristotle would have called him a great-souled, a magnanimous man. The Jacobins legislated as if human nature were infinitely malleable. “The grand basis of their doctrine was the famous system of perfection,” the ideology which claims “that mankind will one day arrive at a purity of government and morals, now unknown,” a purity all the more needed, given the “inequalities of fortune, the differences of opinion, the sentiments as to religion” that stood in the way of French democratization (71-72,44). Since the moral condition of the French was far more corrupt than that of the Lacedaemonians, this would have required a vast renovation, indeed. And they attempted this even as France was beset by the armies of European monarchs.

    “The Jacobins possessed minds rarified by the fire of republican enthusiasm, and they may be said to have been reduced, by their purifying scrutinies, to the quintessence of infamy,” combining “at the same time a degree of energy which was completely without example, and an extent of crimes, which all those of history, put together, can scarcely equal” (74,46). By “purifying scrutinies” Chateaubriand means the forced exile by the Jacobins of all members of their own party “suspected of moderation or humanity” and the guillotining of members of all the other parties (74,46). The Terror forced citizens into the Army of the Republic, where “the courage natural to the French, the inconstancy and the enthusiasm of which they are occasionally susceptible,” the pay, the food, the women, and the wine afforded victorious soldiers made many an ordinary man “become a hero” and, against expectations, repel the onslaughts of the paid soldiers of the monarchies (77,48). The Jacobins “created armies of enchantment” organized in the modern way, deadly to all comers (77,48).

    But ultimately deadly to the French themselves. “The people, now hearing of nothing but conspiracies, invasion, and treason, were afraid of their own friends, and fancying themselves upon a mine which was ready to burst beneath them, sunk into a state of torpid terror,” as “the Jacobins had foreseen (82,51).The “unfortunate confounded people” were supposed by the Jacobins to have been reduced to clay, pliable in the hands of their rulers (82,51). “A republican,” the Jacobins taught, “ought to have neither love, nor fidelity, nor respect, except for his country”; children went to military schools, “where hatred and abhorrence of all other governments were instilled into their minds”—whereby “all the morality of Lycurgus was evidently perverted and molded” to the purposes of the Jacobin regime (83,52). Chateaubriand emphasizes that all of this was undertaken by adherents of the “speculative views and abstract doctrines” of “the men of letters,” many of whom Jacobin party members themselves, “endeavor[ing] to bring back the manners of antiquity into modern Europe” (86,54). But the French, in their love of the arts, their immoderation (oscillating between over-refinement and restlessness in peaceful times, savagery “during political troubles”), a people “floating like a vessel without ballast at the will of their impetuous passions,” more nearly resembled not the Lacedaemonians but the Athenians (94,59). 

    What should the literary Jacobins have learned from the Greeks? Starting with the poems of the remotest age, the Jacobins could have learned liberty, including martial enthusiasm, from Homer; from Hesiod they could have imbibed “a tendency to bring mankind back to nature” (101,63). From both of these poets they would have learned “there is no real revolution, unless it is effect in the heart”—the lesson of poetry, not natural philosophy, one ignored by natural philosophers of antiquity and ‘rationalist’ philosophes of modernity (101,64). The political philosophers of antiquity “soften the rigor of wisdom by imparting to it the embellishments of the Muses” (101,64). In modernity “the English have had the honor of being the first in applying poetry to useful subjects,” as seen, for example, in Shakespeare but not only in Shakespeare (101,64). From the ancient Greek “middle ages” the Jacobins could have learned the value not “of the greatest liberty” but of energy, not of poetic beauty but of moral sublimity (104,64-65). Here, Draco (in measured doses) would become a healthy tonic, even as Rousseau’s Emile has done for modern times. Neither Draco’s laws nor Rousseau’s education can safely be taken literally; Chateaubriand reports smiling at naïve French mothers who would use Rousseau’s book as a guide to the education of their children, rightly suggesting that he never intended it as such. But sublimity can balance beauty in a ‘mixed’ regime of the soul. 

    Solon’s Athens, like the France of the eighteenth century, saw “one of the greatest revolutions in the human mind,” in which “all the seeds of the sciences, which had been so long fermenting in Greece, burst forth together” in the tragedy of Thespis, the comedy of Susarion, Aesop’s fables, Cadmus’ history, Thales’ astronomy, Simonides’ grammar (106,66). Architecture and statuary flourished, too, “but philosophy and politics more particularly soared to a height before unknown,” as they did in Europe with Locke, Montesquieu, and Rousseau, who “imparted to modern nations ideas of liberty” (107,66). In France, however, the Jacobins combined Spartan militarism with Athenian democracy, a virulent mixture, a ‘mixed regime’ badly mixed. Whereas Aristotle and Montesquieu understood that different peoples needed different regimes, regimes adapted to their national ethos and circumstances; and whereas they understood humanity (in Montesquieu’s words) “more fitted for a medium than for extremes”; and whereas Rousseau himself wrote that “the best mode of government” varies with the “conditions of nations”; the Jacobins ignored the central practical insight of their putative philosophic mentor (139,90). In Chateaubriand’s Plutarch-like search for parallel lives, he for parallels between ancients and moderns rather than Greeks and Romans (although for Plutarch the Romans were the moderns), he compares Rousseau with Heraclitus: self-taught, “ow[ing] everything to the vigor of his own genius”; accused of “pride and misanthropy”; and therefore persecuted for decrying the depravity of his contemporaries (144,93-94).

    Summarizing the results of his inquiry so far, Chateaubriand distinguishes morality from philosophy. In this section of his book, he takes his bearings more and more from Rousseau, claiming that “we lose in sentiment what we gain in science” (212,135). By this he means two things. First, insofar as the philosophy of the ancients looked ‘out’ at the world, it inclined toward metaphysics; “the souls of the ancients liked to plunge into the infinite void” (212,135). When modern souls look ‘out,’ they are “are circumscribed by their knowledge” (212,135). Second, insofar as the philosophy of the ancients looked inward, they considered morality. “Morals, taken in their absolute meaning, are our obedience or disobedience to that internal feeling which points out to us honesty and dishonesty, which induces us to do one thing and avoid another (147,96). Moderns scarcely look inward at all. Politics isn’t a sentiment but an art, “that prodigious art”—that architectonic art, Aristotle calls it—by which “a whole nation exists, though the individuals composing it differ widely as to morals in many instances” (147-48,96). In their moral and political admonitions, too, the ancient Greeks differed sharply from the modern French. The Greek sages wanted man “to deduce his happiness from the recesses of his own soul” (148,96). The French philosophes have viewed man “with reference to his civil connections, and have attempted to make him levy his pleasures as a tax on the rest of the community” (148,96-97). This makes human nature into a work of art, but no thing of beauty. The Greek sages said, “Respect the Gods, and know yourself” (148,97). The philosophes taught, “Purchase what society has to offer at the lowest price you can, and sell yourself at the highest” (148,97). It is Greek theism against modern atheism, Greek morality against modern “policy” (149,97). The Greeks “said to the people, Be virtuous and you will be free” (149,97). The moderns “called to them, Be free and you will be virtuous” (149,97). “Greece, with such principles, became a republic, and attained happiness; but what have we attained by the opposite philosophy?” (149,97) For the Greeks, “being still a moral people, and having passed from a monarchy to a republic by long years of trial, were likely to gain advantages by their revolution, of which the French could entertain no hope” (152,99). In Greece, “the spirit of liberty refined the age which gave it birth, and raised succeeding generations to a height that no other people has been able to reach” (152,99). Not so, the French.

    The two revolutions did have one similarity, a largely deleterious effect on other nations. Chateaubriand first describes the moral and political condition of the nations of the ancient world around and near the Mediterranean during the time of the “republican revolution” in Greece (151,98). Egyptian theocracy and slavery, the first regime to teach the “fundamental principle of all morality,” the immortality of the soul (161,104), but also the first to institutionalize the life of the mind in its great libraries, resisted political change thanks to the rigidity of their class structure, “which imparts such empire to custom” and empowers the rule of priests, that is the rule of the fear of death, that moral foundation of despotism and anathema of moral and political liberty (164,106). Carthage, the England of antiquity, was already a republic, and a commercial one at that. But, also like England, it was a mixed republic; unlike England, its legislature consisted of the people “assembled en masse,” as is possible in a polis (174,113). “Both these governments proved excellent; the first at Carthage in a simple poor community, the other in England among a great, cultivated, and wealthy people (174,113)” As maritime peoples, both gained experience and skill in both commerce and war—giving them a distinct advantage over purely commercial and purely military peoples. As a result of these geopolitical features, Carthage and England alike resisted the influence of the democratic-republican revolutions of their time. Citizens occupied by commercial pursuits “have little time to embarrass themselves with political reveries” (215,136). “Where the arm is at work, the mind is in repose” (215,136). Chateaubriand places the chapter comparing Carthage and England in the center of Part I.

    The more thoroughly martial spirit of Rome similarly shielded it from “the verbose politics of Attica” (229,146). “The citizen, accustomed to exercise himself in the Field of Mars, to obey the laws and fear the gods, never went into the schools of demagogues, to hear them vociferate about the rights of man, and the means of overturning their country,” and Roman magistrates “took care that the youth should not be corrupted by useless knowledge” (230,146). This enabled Rome to oppose its republicanism against Greek republicanism, its liberty against Greek liberty. 

    The ancient Scythians exemplified the primitive herdsmen Chateaubriand regards as the forerunners of civilization. “The Scythian, reposing in the shade of the valley, saw his young family and flocks sporting round him,” and “the gratification of his heart” was friendship with his fellows (250,159). “A thousand delights are the lot of uncorrupted man” (251,159). Chateaubriand had seen such men among the Amerindians of the Canadian woods, “this favorite of nature, who feels much and thinks little, who has no reasoning faculty beyond his wants, and who arrives at the results of philosophy like an infant, through his gambols and sleep” (251,159). They are not solitary, like Rousseau’s natural men, but neither are they restless and agitated, as we civilized ones are. In modernity, their closest analogues are the Swiss. But the Scythians “were shepherds, and cherished liberty for her own sake,” while the Swiss were “agriculturists, and loved her for the sake of their property,” thus “advanc[ing] a step nearer to civil vices” (256,163). The Greek revolution corrupted the Scythians, for “there is no asylum against the danger of opinions,” which “traverse seas, penetrate into deserts, and agitate nations from one extremity of the earth to another” (258,164-65). The ideas of republican Greece “found their way into the forests of Scythia, and destroyed its happiness,” thanks to the “philosopher” Anacharsis, who journeyed to Athens and brought back the ideas then bruited about there (260,166). With this, “Scythia saw men arise among her inhabitants, who thinking themselves better than their fellow-creatures, moralized at the expense of the latter,” sundering the bonds of untroubled friendship founded upon social equality and a shared way of life. In one of his most Rousseauian moments, Chateaubriand laments, “The Scythians, disgusted with their innocence, drank the poison of civil life” (263,167). Their “simplicity, justice, truth, and happiness all disappeared” (263,168). In exchange, Athens employed their men as military guards, much as French kings “so long surrounded themselves with the brave peasantry of Switzerland” (263,168). 

    Chateaubriand likens ancient Macedonia to modern Prussia; they share the spirit of war and “above all policy,” “changing sides according to times and circumstances, lulling their neighbors into security with treaties, and invading their countries directly afterwards” (270-71,173). In Macedonia, “the politic Alexander” waited until the Greeks and the Persians “exhausted themselves by disastrous wars” before conquering both (271,173). Tyre and Holland represent the opposite, commercial spirit—maritime countries, neglectful of belles lettres (“a mercantile spirit contracts the soul,” as “he who busies himself with a ledger seldom opens a philosophical treatise,” although admittedly Tyre had its Moschus, Holland its Erasmus and Grotius) (279,178). Commercial nations trade in commodities; they are as faithless as devotees of “policy,” but in a different mode. During wars and revolutions alike, Tyre’s “frigid merchants continued to import and export, from one country to another, the superfluities of nations, without embarrassing themselves as to the idle systems by which other nations were tormented” (282,180). The occasional philosopher who arises in such nations may even prove useful to it, as “during revolutions, opinions are the only commodities which find a ready sale” (283,180-81).

    The modern parallel to ancient Persia is “Germany,” the Holy Roman Empire. Both regimes are monarchies whose rulers claim sacerdotal authority and rule over empires “composed of different parts” (292,185). Both held their heterogeneous population together with military force (especially cavalry, which covers long distances rapidly) and measured toleration of diverse religions. The Holy Roman Empire had no slaves but it did have peasants; “the feudal regime oppressed the German laborer nearly in the same way that the slavery of Persia disheartened the subject of the great king” (293,186). The principal difference between these regimes “consists in their morals” (293,186). Unlike the Catholic priests of “Germany,” the priests of the main Persian religion worshipped nature, excelling in astronomy and “the science of magic” or astrology—that is, the attempt to divine the workings of nature, particularly with regard to seeing into the future (312,201). Chateaubriand pauses to remark that “if you wish to predict the future, consider the past. It is a sure datum which will never deceive you, if you proceed upon one principle—morality” (314,202). Historical research that attends primarily to the moral spirit, the ethos, of peoples rather than the stars is the true ‘astrology.’

    In both regimes, longstanding corruption—another means of ruling heterogeneous peoples—left them susceptible to revolutionary fervor, in different ways. “The influence of the republican revolution of Greece upon Persia was direct, prompt, and terrible” (314,201-02). With its very different moral spirit, its Catholic Christianity, the Holy Roman Empire quickly learned principles of military organization, strategy, and tactics from revolutionary France, but eschewed its political system. However, the systematic efforts at secularization undertaken by Emperor Joseph II, a modern ‘enlightened despot’ who attempted to bend Catholicism to imperial purposes by reducing the number of clergy and banning many of the Catholic orders, provoked resistance in the Austrian Netherlands, whose people “offered themselves an easy prey to the French” revolutionaries (318,204).

    The military results of the consequent wars differed because Persia fought a one-front war against revolutionary Greece, whereas the Holy Roman Empire fought France and Turkey at the same time. But there was a moral difference, as well. “The ordinary motive for wars is so despicable, and the account of a battle, in which twenty thousand ferocious monsters mangled each other for the gratification of a single man’s passions, is disgusting and fatiguing; but, when citizens are seen charging a horde of conquerors, with chains or political annihilation by dismemberment on one side, and liberty and a rescued country on the other; if any grand spectacle was ever worthy of attracting the attention of mankind, it is surely this” (357,231). Nonetheless, “the poor and innocent Greeks,” defending “their sons, fathers, gods and country,” fought justly; “the French, destitute of morality, and loaded with revolutionary guilt, by no means supply the same affecting picture” (357,231). Unfortunately, both nations “lost their virtues in the same field that they gained the laurels of victory,” as “from this moment an ambition to make conquests and a love of gain succeeded to the enthusiasm of liberty” (362,235). The Peloponnesian War would ruin Greece; the revolutionary wars would weaken France and turn it away from republicanism. The thrill of victory, even in a just war, can tip the thumotic part of the human soul toward tyranny, away from liberty.

    Geopolitically, the French Revolution occurred in an environment consisting of nations with monarchic regimes. “The more heterogeneous the matter of which bodies are formed that come into collision, the more rapid is the inflammation; hence it is natural to expect that the revolutionary movements of France would, in their effects, infinitely surpass those produced by the disturbances in [ancient] Greece, “where nearly all countries were republics already,” and the revolution consisted of changing them into democracies (368,240). This is why, in the ancient world, “the greatest concussion” occurred in Persia, “because it was there that the republican principles caused the most violent shock” (369,240). This leads Chateaubriand to a different, related but crucial claim. The ancient democratic republics maintained themselves on the backs of slaves; only citizens freed from mundane, banal work by slaves could enjoy the leisure needed for serious public deliberations. “It is indeed impossible to comprehend upon what principle a true democracy can be established without slaves,” and this is why “our modern systems” in Europe, without slaves, serfs, or even the kind of peasantry seen on feudal estates, “exclude all republics among us” (369,241). The United States of his time of course did have slaves, and so, in Chateaubriand’s eyes, might sustain democratic republicanism. “I am astonished that the French, who so closely copied antiquity, did not reduce the nations whom they conquered, to slavery,” the “only method of obtaining what is called civil liberty” (369,241). It should be remarked that both the Americans and the French founded republican regimes on natural rights, which oppose slavery; the Americans, in terms of Chateaubriand’s analysis, had the good sense to make exceptions to their moral foundation, while the French, professing “universal fraternity,” which “was not the sterling coin of high antiquity,” made no exceptions to that foundation and failed as a consequence (370,242). 

    Overall, nonetheless, the underlying result was identical: moral corruption. What a nation “gain[s] in knowledge” it loses “in morals” (372,243). Here again, Chateaubriand shows his Rousseauian side. Morality and knowledge “seem so disposed by nature, that the one is always corrupted in proportion to the increase of the other, as if this balance were destined to prevent perfection among mankind”—making those counsels of perfection that the French revolutionaries whispered to themselves so pernicious (372-73,243). “The question of happiness remains…the same for modern for ancient nations, because it is only to be found in purity of soul” (373,244). Enlightened minds do nothing to enlighten hearts. “Who shall teach us, by words or science, the secret of altering the nature of the soul, and rooting out the vexations which choke it up? If man, in spite of philosophy, be condemned to live with his desires, he will for ever be a slave, forever the man of those adverse times which are the past, of those lamentable days which are present, and those future ages of misery which are coming on” (373,244). The political consequence of this is counter-revolutionary. “If the heart cannot attain perfection, if morality remains corrupt in spite of knowledge, adieu to a universal republic, adieu to the fraternity of nations, a general peace, and the brilliant phantom of durable happiness on earth” (373-74,244). Counsels of perfection make sense only if the Spirit is Holy, and then only under a new Heaven on a new Earth, created by the all-powerful, all-wise God not Man, who is neither all-powerful nor all-wise. Thus even in antiquity the effect of the republican revolution in Greece upon Persia “caused the nations, subjected to that empire, to rise from the impetus of public opinion,” spurring the rulers to react by undertaking “a disastrous war, which caused the lives of millions, without mankind gaining more happiness or more liberty,” as even Greek republican victory in that war corrupted the victors and ultimately left them prey to another emperor, Alexander (377,246). 

    Chateaubriand briefly assesses the effects of the Greek revolution on nations from the Iberians and Celts in the west to Tyre in the East, finding that “this revolution which was all virtue, all true liberty, produced nothing but evil to every country except Rome and Great[er] Greece” (i.e. the Greek colonies in Italy) (380,249). “What! when a nation becomes independent, must it be at the expense of the rest of mankind? Must the reaction of good be evil?” (380,249) Very often so. “If the Greeks, in the time of Aristides, only brought evils on the human race by breaking their chains, what can be reasonably expected (the system of perfection put apart) from the influence of the French revolution? Could anyone possibly believe that the world was thereby to become virtuous and free?” (380,249) Modern Europe, take note.

    Worse, freedom understood as civil liberty probably does not exist, Chateaubriand maintains.  Civil liberty requires rule, politics, but genuine liberty is moral, primarily a matter of the heart. Without a society in which good hearts prevail, civil liberty would be impossible, but in what societies do good hearts prevail? Mostly in pre-civilized societies. Therefore, civil society corrupts hearts, disposes of good, free hearts. Civil society is too rational, too liable to philosophizing, for its own good. And even those very yet-uncorrupted hearts are unreliable. “Did not social man begin by being the child of nature? Is it the latter then to whom we must refer?” (384,250) Consider, then, human nature. Human nature is never at peace. There is “a vague restlessness peculiar to our hearts, which makes us equally tired of happiness or misery.” This “secret reason” or hidden cause of revolutions “will urge us from one revolution to another, even to the end of time” (383-84,250). [1] Where does this natural restlessness of man come from? “Perhaps from the consciousness of another life, perhaps from a secret aspiring towards divinity” (384,250). However that might be, “it exists in all nations,” civilized and uncivilized alike (384,250). “It is increased by bad morals”—worsened by civilizational advance, especially science—and “then overturns empires” (384,250-51). Given France’s “condition as to morality in the year 1789,” “could we escape the most terrible destruction?” (384,251) Add to this France’s political debility—its weak monarch, weak or wicked ministers who were frequently changed, and the Court’s corrupt hangers-on (flatterers, mistresses, intriguers), these ephemerids, these “creatures of he moment [who] hastened to drain the blood of the miserable, and soon ell, to be succeeded by another generation of insects as fugitive and voracious as the first,” and catastrophe was inevitable (385,252). 

    The revolutionaries proceeded to make moral conditions even worse. “Celibacy was become common, even among the lower classes of society. These isolated men, who were in consequence egotists, tried to fill up the chasm in their own lives by disturbing the families of others.” (386,252) Those who headed the families that did exist “adopted ideas at least as destructive to society”: parents “unwilling to sacrifice the comforts of life” produced few children, “and this self-love was clothed with the garb of philosophy” (386,252). Thus “cast out of the law of nature by the moeurs of his age,” the Frenchman “wrapped himself in hardened egotism, which destroyed virtue to its very root” (387,253). And then, “after losing happiness in his world, the philosophic executioners,” the Enlightenment philosophes, “deprived him of the hope of a better life” (387,253). Without family, without God, “devoured by an empty and solitary heart, which had never felt another heart beat against it, can we be astonished that the Frenchman was ready to embrace the first phantom which a new universe opened to him?” (389,253) This phantom was the ghost of antiquity, populated by the shades of Athens and Sparta crying “Liberty!” “The head of the Parisian Clown was covered with the cap of the Lacedaemonian citizen. All corrupted, all vicious as he was, the grand virtues of the Lacedaemonian were forced upon the little Frenchman, and he was constrained to play the character of Pantaloon in the eyes of Europe, attired in this masquerade dress of Harlequin” (389,254). With the illusion of democracy among a people fit only for monarchy, the “famous philosophers, who believed in the existence of civil liberty,” “furiously destroyed” all before them, using the mobs of Parisian rabble as their weapons (389,255). 

    “What is wholesome or one nation, is seldom the same for another” (389,255). “To pretend to establish republics, in spite of every obstacle, is an absurdity in most people, and a wickedness in man” (389-90,255).

    What remedy, then? Paradoxically, the cure for wrongly applied science is science rightly applied. There is no return from civilization, and human nature in its restlessness would not prevent its reestablishment, even if there were. “Let the sciences,” then, “those daughters of heaven, fill up the fatal void” (391,257). “The stillness of the night invites thee…. Search, in the paths of Newton, the secret laws by which these globes of fire proudly pursue their course across the azure sky of if the divinity inspire thy soul, meditate in adoration upon that incomprehensible Being, who fills with his immensity this boundless space” (392,257). [2] Consider the stars not as Persian priests did, vainly attempting to mix science with politics, but as a Newtonian physicist or as a Christian. (Newton himself was both.) And if this is too grand, “equally praise-worthy and less profound occupations” beckon; follow Rousseau, “observe the peaceful genera in the most charming pursuit that nature affords,” “the soft sympathies and loves” in the plant kingdom, where there is no ambition but only a tranquility waiting to be imparted to the restless human souls that study it (392,257). 

    This may be sound advice for exiles who have no hope of quick return to their country, but Chateaubriand has already established the importance of political philosophy, so the advice has its limits. In search of a path forward for citizens, he returns to the “second revolution” of ancient Greece, the regime changes from republics to monarchy, the change begun by Philip of Macedon and consolidated by his son, Alexander (397,258). “The more we advance towards the times of corruption, knowledge and despotism, the more we shall discover our own times and morals,” the society consisting of “great ladies and little men, philosophers and tyrants” (397,258). In this parallel, the regime of the Thirty Tyrants in Athens “strongly resembled the state of France during the reign of the Convention”: “surrounded by spies and traitors, the citizens were afraid of communicating with each other,” as brothers could no longer trust brothers, “the friend was mute in the company of his friend, and the science of terror reigned through the desolated city” (403,262-63). Athenians finally rebelled, calling the general, Alcibiades, back from exile, but when a government has “surrounded itself with the military” it is “a certain sign of ruin and tyranny”; “we almost fancy that we are reading the history of our own time” (407,266). This dilemma, Chateaubriand maintains, issued in both cases from the principle of popular sovereignty.

    “The people is a child; give it a coral hung with bells, and if you do not explain the cause, it will break the plaything to discover how the sound is produced” (409,267). Therefore, ‘in the abstract,’ the people must be enlightened, it must understand the workings of its government. But “must we conclude that what is logically true to its full extent is sure to be salutary in its application?” (409,268) That is, are ‘abstract’ or ‘theoretical’ truths directly applicable in practice? Chateaubriand denies it. “There are abstract truths, which would be absurd if we were to reduce them into practice” (409,268). Popular sovereignty is such an abstract truth; “the people has the power of choosing its own government” and thus of changing its government, by which he means its regime (409-10,268). However, this power “place[s] it at the mercy of factious persons without number, who exist only in confusion,” persons who aim to maneuver the people into self-induced slavery by “persuad[ing] it that its constitution of the moment is the worst of all” (410,268). Unmitigated popular sovereignty, the abstract truth brought into practice without qualification, may make honor, fidelity, “and morality itself” seem to be “mere folly” by assuming that “we have the incontestable right to violate them” (410,269). This makes politics into a sphere in which the moral principles that should rule private behavior have no purchase in the public realm. “Are there then two virtues, the one appertaining to man, the other to nations?” (410,269) Virtue for the one, virtù for the other? “I theoretically believe in the principle of the sovereignty for the people, but to this I add that if it be rigorously put in practice, it would be much better for the human race to return to a savage state, and run naked through the woods” (412,270). Americans will recognize in this the argument of Madison in Federalist 10 and of Lincoln against Douglas.

    In Athens, the head of the Thirty Tyrants regime was Critias, “a philosopher and disciple of Socrates,” an “atheist in principle, bloodthirsty and tyrannical from inclination,” the Marat of Greek antiquity (413,270). If a natural or pre-Socratic philosopher fails to philosophize adequately, a thoroughly politicized ‘philosopher,’ no matter how sensible his teacher, will turn into what later would be called an ideologue—in this case, one armed with dangerous powers. With his colleague, Theramenes, a more talented and supple politician—his French analogue was the Abbé Sieyès—these “monsters” disarmed the citizens and deputized “three thousand brigands” as ‘republican guards,’ thereby consigning “the rest of the people…into terror and nothingness” (413,271). The regime paid its henchmen with wealth confiscated from the rich, whose cries of outraged were silenced by executioners. “Athens was only one vast tomb, inhabited by terror and silence,” as its rulers “studied the countenances of their victims, seeking for virtue and candor in this fine organ of truth, as a judge tries to discover the hidden guilt of a culprit” (414-15,272), just as in Paris during the 1790s and during the twenty-first century in Beijing—its rulers enjoying the supplemental advantage of ‘facial recognition technology.’

    Relative moderates within the regime itself were soon purged. These included Theramenes. “No citizen, Socrates excepted, had the temerity to oppose the measures of the Thirty” (422,278); Chateaubriand retains the distinction between the natural philosopher, the political philosopher, and the political ideologue who claims to philosophize. The many Athenian exiles, like the many French exiles, allied with foreign regimes (Sparta for the Athenians) and expelled the Thirty Tyrants. Yet the French exiles are vilified. True, one group “fought for democracy and the other for monarchy,” but the underlying question is the question of justice, and of what kind of regime will deliver it better in the existing circumstances (428,282-83). The exiled Athenian democrats fought for a regime which, though deeply flawed, was more just than the regime of the Thirty Tyrants; the exiled French monarchists fight for a regime which, though deeply flawed, was more just than the regime of the Jacobins. Further, Chateaubriand insists, exiles should not be lumped together for praise or condemnation as if they were a homogeneous body; like all human groups, there are gradations of virtue among them. To speak otherwise “reminds us of the portrait of the Chinese and negroes, all good or all infamous” in the eyes of prejudiced partisans (429,283).

    How, then, did the Macedonian conquerors enter the picture? To account for this, Chateaubriand must consider yet another polis in which philosophy was misused. Syracuse had a monarchic regime. Its new king, Dionysius the Younger, had recently succeeded his father, a usurper who had “exterminated his enemies” but who “rendered his yoke supportable” for the balance of his subjects, by which means he ruled for nearly four decades (435,288). Unfortunately, the cheerful young prince’s uncle, Dion, was a philosopher who mistakenly supposed that the pleasant but mediocre youth might be turned into a philosopher-king. He “put a thousand ill-digested ideas into the young man’s head,” unhinging Dionysius’ moral gateway, a barrier none too imposing to begin with (438,290). But “a man of superior mind is too much inclined to suppose that others possess the qualities which he feels inherent in himself, and continues to communicate his ideas without perceiving that he is not understood. It is absolutely necessary that a man of genius should make a sacrifice to folly” (439,290-91).

    Compounding his error, Dion induced the monarch to invite Plato to Sicily, and “the court was soon transformed into an academy,” wherein the king “argued about the best and worst species of government,” much to the confusion of His Majesty and to the irritation of the soldiers, who “cared little for the world of ideas” (439,291). While compromising his political authority, Dionysius also found the austerity of “philosophic virtue” a bit much (439,291). Since “the desires of monarchs are absolute wants,” and the desires of this monarch oscillated between the political and the philosophic ways of life, he only reinforced the impression that ‘philosopher-king’ is a contradiction in terms. In one of his moods, he exiled Dion; in another, he recalled him. Dion launched a naval expedition against Syracuse, defeating the tyrant. But “division prevailed in the city” and it all ended in catastrophe, with Dion dead and Dionysius reinstated (444,294).

    Dion had attempted to found a Platonic republic in Sicily, “perhaps the only time [in antiquity] that an attempt was made to frame the government of a nation on principles purely abstract” (447n.,297n.). (“The French wished to do the same in our days; but neither Dion nor the theorists of France succeeded, because the morals of their respective nations were corrupted.”) (447n.,297n.) It was the political philosopher, Plato, the author of the book in which the ‘ideal republic’ is founded by Socrates and his interlocutors in speech, who “understood the nature of his contemporaries better than Dion did, and predicted that he would only produce evil without being eventually successful” (447,297). “The attempt to bestow republican liberty on a people devoid of virtue, is an absurdity. You lead them from misfortune to misfortune, and tyranny to tyranny, without procuring them independence.” (447-48,297) Chateaubriand concurs with the genuinely political philosophers in understanding “that there exists a peculiar government, which is natural, as it were, to each age of a nation; perfect liberty for savages, a royal republic for the pastoral times, democracy in the age of social virtues, aristocracy when morals are relaxed, monarchy in the age of luxury, and despotism in that of corruption” (448 ,297). A founder who misreads the ethos of the people for whom he acts “throws it into agitation with effecting [his] object, and sooner or later it returns to the regime which suits it, by the mere force of circumstances” (448,298). Ideas have consequences—in Chateaubriand’s formulation, “from certain principles ensue certain consequences”—and “from certain morals” certain governments follow. To ignore this is to commit a political crime, whether from misfeasance or from malfeasance. “Tyrants are the punishment of guilty revolutions” (448,298) As for the modern French, “we have been raising ourselves on tiptoe for the purpose of imitating the giants of Greece, but we shall never be otherwise than dwarfs” (451,299-300).

    Once again overthrown, Dionysius fled to Corinth, then to Macedonia, where the monarch, Philip II, treated him kindly. He ended as an impoverished priest, begging alms. His contemporary parallel in Europe is France’s exiled “legitimate sovereign” of the Bourbon line, “now wandering through Europe at the mercy of mankind” (457,304). “Should the day arrive when Europe is converted into a democracy, the last of the dethroned monarchs will be as unfortunate as Dionysius” (458,304). This reflection leads Chateaubriand to consider how exiles should conduct themselves. “An unhappy man is an object of curiosity,” less often compassion (465,309). The “first rule” he should follow “is to conceal his tears,” since “who can be interested by an account of his disasters?” (465,310) Second, he should “isolate[e] himself entirely,” inasmuch as “society lays it down as a maxim, that he who is distressed is culpable” (465-66,310). Third, he should exhibit “unbending pride,” for “pride is the virtue of misfortune” (466,310). [3] When ruling as a king or an aristocrat, “you should undervalue what you are,” cultivate humility; but as an exile “you should be proud of what you have been,” “avail[ing] yourself of it as a buckler against the scorn attached to the unfortunate” and “summoning the dignity of human nature,” lest “others should forget it” when dealing with you (466,310-11). But Stoic self-rule and aristocratic pride are not enough. Read the Gospel, that supreme source of consolation, with its message of “pity, tolerance, sweet indulgence, and still sweeter hope” (467,311). And work, but only in accordance with your nature. Never renounce the faculties of your soul by accepting task that are beneath you. A noble exile “would rather die of hunger, than procure the necessities of life,” although “it is not everyone who will understand this” (469,312-13). Finally, get out of the city from time to time. Visit nature. In the forest the exile “will find peaceful associates, who are, like him, in search of silence and obscurity,” and who will “kindly admit him into their republic,” even if he has been exiled by the republican regime of his homeland’s sovereign people (471,314). “A life with nature for our companion is truly gratifying” (471,314). In exile, Chateaubriand recurs to the nature that was his first interest, his pre-Socratic way of life. Yet he will live that life not as a Socratic but as the political philosopher he has become. “After the loss of our friends, if we do not sink under affliction, the heart has recourse to itself; it forms the project of excluding every other sentiment, and living entirely upon recollection” (471-72,314). Those recollections will include instructive, even self-instructive scenes of public life, and these will give substance to any writings he may care to direct to his former friends and fellow citizens, from exile. In this way he agrees with Rousseau, “recommend[ing] the study of botany as proper to calm the soul, by turning the eyes of the unhappy sufferer from the passions of mankind to the innocent race of plants” (472-73,315). Recalling the Apostle Paul’s admonition, the adjures the exile to avoid “the vanity of philosophy,” although he clearly does not consider philosophy itself vain (476,319). 

    What of Chateaubriand’s own memories? He ties them firmly to political history and to French politics, proving that his exile is no epicurean act of withdrawal into some garden. He begins by recalling the Spartan king, Lysander, who had defeated the Thirty Tyrants and carried off Athenian gold and silver. By so doing, “he introduced the vices” of Athens to his own country: “Simplicity of manners was soon reckoned vulgarity; frugality was deemed folly, and honesty nonsense” (477,319). An oligarchy arose, “and the Spartans, among whom such an equality of rank and fortune had hitherto prevailed, were divided into a vile band of slaves and masters” (477,319). Eventually, a new king, Agis, attempted to “reestablish the laws and morals of ancient Laconia,” but he was betrayed by one of the newly-rich oligarchs and was killed, along with his mother and grandmother (477,319). This reminds Chateaubriand of the death of Louis XVI, who also had attempted to introduce reforms in the years before the French Revolution, with similar results. The memory of Louis in turn recalls the person of his defender, Guillaume-Chrétien Lamoignon de Malesherbes. An accomplished attorney, Malesherbes was a longtime friend of the Chateaubriand family; his granddaughter married into it, cementing the alliance.  “In the midst of courtly corruption,” he “had combined with elevated rank the integrity of heart and courage of a patriot” (495-96n.,333-34n.). So much so, that when the rest of the courtiers had fled Versailles, abandoning the king to his captors, Malesherbes courageously volunteered to serve as his attorney at trial. An advocate of religious and political tolerance (he opposed persecution of Protestants and urged liberalization of censorship of political writings), Malesherbes had also been a friend of Rousseau, the putative inspirer of the revolutionaries. That didn’t stop the revolutionaries from executing the elderly nobleman, along with his daughter, granddaughter, and grandson, “amidst the acclamations of an ungrateful people, whose distresses he had so often commiserated” (495,333). 

    By this he refers to Malesherbes’ efforts on the part of those unjustly imprisoned in the Bastille prison. “He alone refused to adopt the vices of the great,” and remained one of the very few men at the royal court “whom J. J. Rousseau sincerely loved”—a “patriot at court, a naturalist at Malesherbes [his ancestral home], and a philosopher at Paris” (498n.,335n.). 

    Both Agis and Louis “were full of love for their people; both fell from a wish of bringing back their subjects to liberty and virtue; both mistook the morals of their age” (500,338). Their leading vices were “the spirit of system” in Agis, who attempted reforms more thoroughgoing than the corrupted Spartans would tolerate, and “want of decision” in Louis, who belonged in private life, having no natural disposition for the exercise of executive authority (501,338). The long-term results of these upheavals spelled subjection for Greece. As for France, the revolution may have had little lasting influence in its own times, but it will be copied re-attempted, later one, and “will, perhaps, on some future day, overthrow all Europe” (507,343). In this, we know, Chateaubriand proved more nearly correct than he would have wished.

    These important excurses completed, Chateaubriand picks up the thread of the second revolution in ancient Greece, the exploitation of Greek disorder by Macedonia. King Philip II “is the father of that modern policy, which consists in creating disturbances for the purpose of reaping the fruits, and…he equally gave birth to the system, now practiced, of spreading corruption in order to extend dominion” (509,344). In his dealings with the Greeks he “threw away the mask as soon as he felt strong”; “the Greeks then awoke, but it was too late” (509,345). He defeated Athens and Thebes in the Battle of Chaeronea in 338; his assassination elevated his son, Alexander, to the throne. “If the age of Alexander differs from ours in historical respects, they more nearly resemble each other on the side of morality,” as “it was then that there arose, as in our days, a host of philosophers, who called in question God, the universe, and themselves” (510,345). This confluence of despotic empire and intellectual ferment “proves that to arrive at independence it is not sufficient to reason scientifically upon virtue, but necessary to love this virtue; and it proves that all the moralists in the universe cannot impart to us a relish for it once we have lost it” (510-11,346). Indeed, “the enlightened ages have always been the ages of slavery” (511,346). 

    The Greek philosophers of that time, “like ours, were at open war with their own age,” foolishly attempting “to accelerate the course of events” by advancing their own opinions (520,351). “Bodies politic, when left to themselves, have their natural metamorphoses like Chrysalids” (521,351). Their healthy maturation takes time, finally “bursting through the walls of its prison, and displaying two brilliant wings,” on which it “flies to the fields of liberty” (521,351). But “ill-judged artificial warmth” applied in an attempt to hasten their emergence will only kill the organism, leaving “nothing but a dead body of hideous form” (521,351). Of the moderns, Hobbes “maintain[ed] opinions most destructive to society”—that “authority, not truth, constitutes the principle of law,” and that “the state of nature is a state of war, and that happiness consists in a perpetual transition from desire to desire” (533,354). Descartes denied all certain truth but Cogito ergo sum. Other moderns were less pernicious. Locke’s Essay Concerning Human Understanding is “one of the finest monuments of human genius”; Machiavelli, Bodin, and Grotius “revived politics in Europe”—a mixed blessing insofar as “politics” means a policy of what would later be called Realpolitik (534-35,355-56). But “the French concussion did not proceed from this or that man, from this or that book” (537n.,357n.). Rather, it originated in the revival and advance of those twins, “knowledge and corruption” (547n.,357n.). The Encyclopedists or Enlightenment philosophes typified this spirit, a spirit of destruction redeemed by inadequate and at times nonexistent plans for reform. 

    Against the philosophes Chateaubriand places Rousseau, author of the Emile, which he ranks among the “five books in the world which are worthy of perusal” (554,371) Chateaubriand endorses Rousseau’s assertion in the Emile: “Every thing is right when it leaves the hands of the Creator; every thing degenerates in the hands of man” (548,366). The development of reason is the key part of that degeneration and, as Chateaubriand notices, since “it requires all the force of reason to comprehend God,” “God is therefore never mentioned” to the child, Emile, in his early education (548,367). He is rather “immediately exposed to the influence of necessity, the only law of life” (548,367). Even after he reaches the age of reason, Emile hears the teaching—more precisely the “confession”—of the Savoyard Vicar, in which the Vicar “proves the existence of the Great Being not by metaphysical reasonings but by the sentiment he finds in his heart” (552). The sanction for the heart’s sentiments, the only foundation for morality, comes from the most comprehensive sentiment. This teaching comports with the character of Emile: “Emile is man par excellence, for he is the man of nature. His heat knows no prejudices. Free, courageous, beneficent, having all the virtues without pretense, if he has a fault it is being isolated in the world, and in living like a giant in our small societies: (553). His isolation ameliorated by his love of pure-hearted Sophie. The natural man finds himself in experiencing philo-sophia.

    “Such is the famous work which precipitated our Revolution” (553).  What is more, Rousseau predicted that revolution and more, “the horrors with which it would be accomplished” (451n.,369n.). “How could such a republican as Rousseau have formed such an idea, if he had not known what sort of people would effect the revolution in France?” (451n.,369n) It is because the revolutionaries reached for a philosopher’s fine-patterned fabric with clenched fists. The Emile‘s “chief fault is that it is written for only a small number of readers,” readers who perceive its irony: “It would be utterly impossible to educate a young man upon a system, which requires a combination of objects and people that are not to be found”; it is “the sage” who “must regard this production of Rousseau as a treasure,” revealing, as it does “the unsophisticated man of nature” to Rousseau’s “degenerate contemporaries” (554,371). [4] The revolutionaries never noticed any of that, any more than the well-intentioned ladies who took the Emile as a manual for early childhood education.

    Among those degenerate contemporaries, Chateaubriand counts the ones he calls, with irony of his own, “our philosophers” (558,374). Pernicious as their doctrines were, morally pernicious as much of philosophy and especially sophistry can be, the Greeks were “distinguished by the chastity and purity of their morals”—their military courage, contempt for pleasure, and frugality (558,374). Modern philosophers write books about war, about morals, about politics, but they’ve never ventured on to any battlefield, never “taken any part” in government, and “share in all the vices of the world” even as they denounce them (558,374). This has given them one philosophic advantage: “by living more in the world, and according to its customs, than the ancients, [they] have been able better to depict society, and the secret springs of human action” (560,376). The moderns do not unduly ennoble human nature; their very lowness enables them to understand how degenerate men have become. This also gives them “more rapid influence on their contemporaries than the books of Plato and Aristotle”; “we find that a shorter time elapsed between the subversion of principles in France and the reign of the Encyclopedists, than between the same subversion of principles in Greece and the triumph of the sophists” (561,376).

    This leads to a more general question. “How does philosophy act on mankind?” (561,376). The Greek republics changed into tyrannies. The “legislating philosophers of Athens” preferred monarchy to republicanism (563,378). (He is probably thinking of Plato’s philosopher-kings and Aristotle’s listing of kingship among the good regimes, theoretically the best regime, in the Politics.) “Why? Because they had felt the inconveniences of a popular one,” particularly the persecution of philosophers thereby (563,378). Or rather, “they did not possess the monarchical one”; they themselves did not rule as philosopher-kings (563,378). “The state in which we live always appears to us the very worst,” and the innate restlessness of man generates “a thousand little contemptible passions, which we do not dare to confess even to ourselves,” which “continually urge us to hate and blame the institutions of our country” (563,378). Chief among those passions are “interest, pride, and envy.” “This is the secret of revolutions” (564,378). 

    The Greek philosophers were right to praise monarchy, inasmuch as the people “were too far corrupted,” too civilized, “to admit of a democratic constitution” (564,378). By contrast, when Rousseau and others “sounded the republican trumpet, Europe was reposing under monarchical government” (564,379). There it should have remained, given its “corrupt morals,” precluding the possibility that any of “the forms of democracy” might endure (565,379-80). 

    Given the intimate connection of religion and politics, Chateaubriand turns to a consideration of religion, a discussion in which he directs his reader to the often-pernicious effect of philosophy on “the religious ideas of the people.” (592,380). “There is one God,” he begins, “the invisible architect of this universe” (567-68). The polytheism of antiquity derives from “the penchant of human nature for superstition” (572). Philosophy questioned and weakened it; Christianity ended it.

    Christianity advanced rapidly throughout the Roman Empire because it “exalted the humble,” beckoning to “the poor classes,” ‘the many who are poor’ (580). By then, paganism had spawned the vices of such emperors as Nero and Caligula. Most important, Christian evangelists converted the barbarians who brought chaos to the empire. The barbarians were creatures of imagination, not reason, and Christian preachers spoke to them with the vivid and unforgettable imagery of the Cross. Further, as “all civil authority dissolved, the priests alone could protect the peoples,” offering them membership in the Church, the only civil society remaining (587). “Amidst these storms, the priests grew more and more powerful, having succeeded in organizing themselves in an almost unshakable system” (588).    

    “It was after the reign of Charlemagne and the division of his empire that Christianity attained its highest point of grandeur,” with the Crusades and flourish of chivalry (588). This was, not incidentally, the Europe in which aristocrats ruled civil society, and kings were only the first among aristocrats. Christianity began to decline “when the different sects, which it engendered, had the same effect on Christianity that the philosophical schools of Greece had on Polytheism; they weakened the whole sacerdotal system” (592,381). This decline accelerated with the vices of the popes, who began to resemble some of the later emperors, and whose ways were imitated by many of the lesser clergy. Renaissance secularism and Reformation enthusiasm combined to destroy the unified Christendom of western Europe.

    Because it was itself a religious movement, a thing of the heart even more than of the mind, the Reformation capped this moral collapse, this crisis of the heart in European man. It began when “a monk,” Martin Luther, “chose to think it wrong that the Pope had not granted to his order, rather than another, the commission to sell indulgences in Germany. Let us weep for human nature”—torn, as he has observed, between the desire for independence and the desire for tyranny (595,385) Schism followed schism, enabling philosophers to infect citizens and subjects with skepticism. And “when men begin to be skeptics in religion, they begin also to have political doubts,” because “when the soul demands to be free, the body shares its wish” and nature overrides spirituality (592,380).

    The Counter-Reformation allayed “the storms raised by the Reformation,” but by then the Vatican had “lost the grandeur of its walls, and its timberwork was mutilated by its own thunderbolts, which the fury of the tempest had forced back against it” (598,385). Royal and papal violence “only irritated mankind,” shipping up the passion for liberty still further without adequately preparing souls to live at liberty (598,385). Knowledge or science “seconded this disposition to hate what had caused so many evils. In matters of faith there are no bounds; for the moment that we cease to believe anything, we shall soon cease to believe everything,” as seen in the writings of Rabelais and Montaigne, Hobbes and Spinoza (599,386). When, under the reign of Louis XV, the Encyclopedists formed the Société des gens de lettres, “only two great persons refused to become members of it, J. J. Rousseau and Montesquieu,” the only true philosophers of the time (602,388). They saw that “the true spirit of the Encyclopedists was a persecuting fury and intolerance of opinions, which aimed at destroying all other systems than their own, and even preventing the freedom of thought” (602-03,388-89). The Encyclopedists raged “against what they called l’Infame, or the Christian religion, which they had resolved to exterminate” (603,389).

    In the correspondence among these men, including “the despot Frederick” of Prussia, “we see with amazement, philosophers casting off the cloak, in which they had disguised themselves to the eye of the world,” and the monarch “throwing away the royal mask” (603,389). All treated “morality as a fable…talking freely to his brother philosophers of liberty, while he reserved slavery for his stupid people” (603,389). This is astonishing because a monarch undermined “the basis of regal power,” and also because an “atheistic sect were miserable reasoners upon affairs of state,” foolishly exposing their Machiavellianism to public view (604,389). Meanwhile, alone among his philosophic contemporaries, Rousseau defended God, although Chateaubriand does express reservations about the Confessions of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar, which Rousseau carefully folded into the pages of the Emile.  Chateaubriand does not excuse Rousseau or Montesquieu for “unfortunately” having begun “to enlighten the minds of men, who had lost that energy and purity of soul essential towards making a good use of the truth” (604,390). 

    By the end of the Old Regime, the royal court, “blind to the progress of a vast monarchy towards that abyss, in which we have seen it swallowed, plunged deeper than ever into vice and despotism,” its “monarch lulled to repose in the lap of pleasure, corrupt courtiers, weak or wicked ministers, the people losing their morality, the philosophers partly undermining religion and partly the state, the nobles either ignorant or contaminated by the vices of the times, the ecclesiastics a disgrace to their order at Paris, and full of prejudices in the country” (605-06,391-92). The Revolution knocked down the rotten structure, but its protagonists were no less corrupt but utterly lacking in the prudence experience in politics can exercise to prevent the worst excesses of violence. 

    Chateaubriand considers the ancient political philosophers as superior to the moderns in their prudence, that moral virtue which the moderns incline to reduce to mere calculation of self-interest. Plato and Aristotle were more ‘politic’—content “to publish their novel dogmas without directly attacking the religion of that country, whereas Voltaire and d’Alembert, without enunciating other opinions, declaimed against the cult of their fatherlands” (607). “In this, they were much more immoral than the Sectarians of Athens” (607). After summarizing the Encyclopedists’ critique of Biblical religion—the familiar claims of contradictions within the Bible itself, which spawned the many schismatic sects in the early centuries of Church history; the complaints about the hierarchical structure of Catholicism and its discipline; the satires jibing at Christianity’s supposed affinities to paganism—Chateaubriand states his objection to “the unbelievers” (621). He makes no effort to meet them on their own ground, to refute their arguments. Consistent with Rousseau’s teaching, he appeals not to their heads but to their hearts. “You overthrow the religion of your country, you plunge the people into impiety, and you propose no other palladium of morality [to take Christianity’s place]. Cease this cruel philosophy; do not steal from the unfortunate his last hope. What matters if it is an illusion, if this illusion relieves a part of the burden of existence; if it keeps watch during the long nights at his bedside, solitary and soaked with tears; if finally it renders the final service of friendship in closing the eyes of she who, alone and abandoned, vanished into death?” (621).

    As for the priests that bring hope and comfort to the human heart, those of antiquity exhibited “a spirit somewhat different from those of our age” (622). Chateaubriand discusses the spirit of paganism and that of Christianity in both republican and monarchic regimes. In ancient republics “the interest of the priests inclined to the side of liberty” (622). Many modern priests also do. More, in both ancient and modern republics priests were persecuted, in antiquity by the Sophists and in modern France by the philosophes. But in France, unlike in antiquity, “the philosophy of the Bastille” prevailed; atheism had force on its side, and used it.

    In antiquity, also, priests, like all regimes, were not centrally organized. They could pose no danger to liberty, except, at most, in local circumstances. The Roman Catholic Church did pose such a danger because it was centrally organized. As for the priests themselves, those seen in the ancient republics were virtuous, unlike those in the French Republic. This notwithstanding, and “all things considered, priests are necessary for morality, and excellent in a republic; they cause no evil, and can cause much good” (625).

    Monarchies are a different matter. “But if the priestly spirit can be salutary in a republic, it becomes terrible in a despotic state; because it serves as rear-guard for the tyrant, it renders slavery legitimate and sacred in the eyes of the people” (625). In antiquity this effect was conspicuous in Persia and Egypt. “Their spirit was composed equally of fanaticism and intolerance” (625). Unlike modern priests, they held secret doctrines, revealing only exoteric teachings to the people. Also unlike modern priests, they cultivated scientific studies, especially (as he has already noted) astronomy.

    In modern monarchies, “the dominant spirit of the priesthood is egoism”; with no wife or children, the priest is “rarely a good citizen” (627) in those regimes. He shares the spirit of fanaticism with his ancient counterpart, but this takes a more entrepreneurial cast, as, “like merchants in their shops,” modern priests hawk their wares (628).  As an organized body modern priests, like members of other clubs and brotherhood, “put their hatreds in common, and almost never their loves” (628). In France, Chateaubriand allows, the lower clergy, working close to the people, are often beneficial.

    If Christianity continues to decline, what religion will replace it? Chateaubriand outlines two hypothetical futures. The first might be described as Kantian: the nations will unite under one government “in a state of inalterable happiness” (651). Given the previous 650 pages, one may confidently say he thinks this unlikely. (I am not alone in this assessment. On the copy of the book I read, a previous reader had written in the margin next to this passage, “CHIMÈRE!”) On the other hand, le Vicomte continues, it may be that after a long period of revolutions, civil wars, and anarchy the nations will “return by force to barbarism,” leaving minds and hearts ready for a conversion analogous to that experienced by the barbarians evangelized by Christians after the fall of Rome. This would be consistent with the findings presented in his study, which he proceeds to summarize in his final chapter.

    “Most of the circumstances, which are pointed out as new in the French Revolution, are here shown to have almost literally occurred in ancient Greece” (654-55,394). This indicates the limits of human nature. “Man is so feeble in his means and genius, as only to be capable of incessant repetition,” moving “in a cycle,” not progressing morally or politically (655,394). This discovery should have a beneficial moral effect. “Every man, who is persuaded that there is nothing new in history, loses a relish for innovation”—that is, moral and political innovation (656,395). The “enthusiasm” for such innovation “proceeds from ignorance; remove the latter, and the former will be extinguished” (656,395). There being no going back from civilization, and no taking back of the very real scientific progress, the cure for the corruption caused by ‘enlightenment’ is more knowledge, knowledge of a certain kind. It is indispensable to know that the “moral situation of the people” is more important than its “political condition”; that situation provides “the key which opens the secret-book of fate” (657,395). Morals “are the center round which political worlds revolve” (658,396). Morality is a matter of the heart, not the head. “The heart judges of good and evil; the head [judges] of effects, and the connection which exists between one circumstance and another” (658,396). “Virtue, therefore, emanates from the heart, and the sciences proceed from the head,” and “virtue is conscience heard and obeyed” whereas “science is enlightened nature” (658,396-97). The political consequence of this is that “liberty, the daughter of martial Virtue, cannot exist unless nourished at the bosom of Morality” (658,397). Liberty so understood may be seen in Sparta, where the “free man” was in fact ruled by “some hoary-headed leader”—a leader who, if he detected any “soft pity” infecting the soul of any citizen under his command, compelled him “to murder some lowly innocent slave, in the field which this unfortunate creature was laboriously tilling for his master,” a murder required to toughen the soul of the citizen required to commit it (662,397).

    But what of liberty in Athens? it was severely restricted, as well, by modern standards, albeit differently than in Sparta. Athenians could participate in ruling the polis only if he met a property requirement; if he fell into debt “he was sold as a slave” (662,398). And “a good rhetorician could cause Socrates to be poisoned today, and Phocion to be banished tomorrow” (662,398). Chateaubriand tartly remarks, “I should like to know, therefore, how many sorts of political liberty there are,” given not only the differences in the restrictions placed on it not only in Sparta and Athens but in “all the other little cities of Greece” (662,398). 

    He ends with an exhortation. “Let us be men, that is to say, free”—that is, “to despise the prejudices of birth and riches, while we honor virtuous indigence,” “impart[ing] energy to our souls, and elevation to our ideas,” displaying “dignity of character,” “brav[ing] poverty,” “smil[ing] at death like true Christians” (664,398). We can do this only if we “begin by withdrawing our attachment to human institutions, be they of what nature they may” (664,398). No one political regime fits all peoples, and our political choices should learn from ancient and modern history how to match regimes to peoples.

    The divergence of moeurs and of regimes underlines Chateaubriand’s underlying, and quite Rousseauian conviction, that the state of society is not the state of nature. “Oh, man of nature, it is you alone who make me glory in being a man” (667). You alone are dependent neither on a royal court nor a “popular Tiger” (667). You need to obey no person; nature is your temple. True liberty is living in nature. This state, however, can never be recovered by most men, and only occasionally by philosophers. Thanks in part to his exile and the solitude he has gained by it, he has enjoyed glimpses of nature. “One closes [this] book in a disposition of soul calmer and more apt to find the truths and the errors of this work,” a “mixture inevitable in human nature.” “Given the dimness of my lights,” this disposition of soul “makes me more susceptible to another”—another light. Judging from his subsequent book, The Genius of Christianity, this seems to be the light of the Gospel. [5]

    If, as Meier writes, political philosophy is the part of philosophy in which the whole of philosophy is questioned, then Chateaubriand has written a work of political philosophy. And it took an impressive degree of philosophic autarchia or self-sufficiency for a French aristocrat in exile, mourning the murders of family members, to consider the French Revolution philosophically. He does so by taking “a path of philosophy hitherto untrodden,” seeking human nature in historical research into politics while never succumbing to ‘historicism,’ to historical relativism, always remembering to revisit nature as it exists with no human beings in it, except the philosopher himself. He finds human nature not to be malleable, as Rousseau claims, because its spiritedness divides between the thirst for liberty and the thirst for tyranny, a factionalism that brings restlessness both to the human soul and to political life. Man will never be fully satisfied, even in happiness. 

    Because human souls are by nature restless, the course of human events can never result in progress, whether gradual or ‘dialectical.’ Historical research rightly undertaken discovers not overall progress or decline but the moral spirit, the ethos, of peoples, the habits of their hearts, the ways of life human nature has been habituated to follow by its circumstances natural and conventional. As for the course of events, if it has a pattern is it cyclical, as nature yields barbarism, barbarism to civilization, civilization to decadence and back to barbarism. Science, the product of civilization, too often opposes morality, the head against the heart. This happens in antiquity, with the natural philosophers, and in modernity, with its incoherent combination of natural philosophy and politics, yielding ‘ideology’ and then violent revolution. 

    To recover, Chateaubriand advises, modern ‘intellectuals’ must reform both their heads and their hearts. In terms of the life of the mind, they must return to genuinely political philosophy, recovering the virtue of prudence and seeing it for what it is, the indispensable virtue of both citizens and of philosophers, philosophers who must understand their own nature as the ‘epistemological’ starting point of their inquiries into nature tout court. In terms of the heart, of morality, they must bring themselves to see that true compassion for the people they claim to champion against their oppressors must never overturn Christianity, the religion which, along with Judaism, puts both humility and charity at the center of moral life.

     

    Notes

    1. See Alexis de Tocqueville: Democracy in America, Volume II, Part ii, chapter 3.
    2. Pascal finds the vast, empty spaces discovered by modern scientists terrifying because they seem to mean that nothingness overwhelms being, meaninglessness meaning. Chateaubriand sees the vastness but considers it, as it were, metaphysically full.
    3. That admirer of Chateaubriand, Charles de Gaulle, adopted this posture vis-à-vis the English and the French during his exile from France, also on English soil, during World War II. He did not neglect to remain in this posture, even when he returned to French soil, first in North Africa, then in France itself after D-Day, and years later, as the president of the Fifth Republic.
    4. Chateaubriand does not see, or at least does not remark upon, the equally ironic presentation of Plato’s ‘ideal republic’ in the Republic, preferring to call the dialogue an attempt “to spiritualize terrestrial beings”—an act of “philosophic blasphemy,” with its proposal to destroy families by holding women and children in common. He traces this enormity in Plato’s thought to “the delirium of his virtue.” (543,361-62)
    5. Chateaubriand appends a final chapter, an account of a night spent with an Amerindian family in Canada. “These men of nature”—a “nature savage and sublime”—offer him a hospitality characteristic of the men of antiquity. He writes a blessing: “May you live a long time in your precious independence, your beautiful solitude.” That is, the life of natural man is familial and social, not political; his soul is sublime, not beautiful (as it must be, if human beings are by nature divided between the thirst for liberty and the thirst for tyranny), but they live within a larger nature that is beautiful, lending a certain balance to their lives. Chateaubriand would offer a more extensive account of this life in his 1801 novella, Atala.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • 1
    • 2
    • Next Page »