Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for April 2019

    “Moby-Dick”: End of the Yarn

    April 19, 2019 by Will Morrisey

    This is the thirteenth in a series of essays on Melville’s novel.

     

    As Ahab drew nearer the Whale, two gams followed in quick succession. New England’s Puritan founders had modeled their regimes on the laws of Israel; the name of the first ship recalls the early generations of Israel. The captain of the Rachel had not only seen Moby-Dick, he had chased him, losing a boat and its crew to him. The captain’s twelve-year-old son was on that boat. The Manxman now took the cries of the seals on the rocks to have been the cries of those drowned sailors. As in the Bible, the Rachel mourned her lost sons. Rachel’s husband was Jacob; Starbuck just failed to be a ‘Jacob.’ Now, he sought no ally in the visiting captain, nor does Ishmael suggest that he so much as thought of doing so. Starbuck was no founder, lacking the strength to follow his God.

    The captain of the Rachel  knew Ahab from Nantucket, knew that Ahab himself had a young son. He implored Ahab to join him in the search, offering to pay for time lost. Ahab refused, with one of his most striking utterances: “May I forgive myself.” Ahab treated himself as God; after all, according to his gospel, he had personality, the ability to judge and forgive, whereas his ‘god’ had none.

    Ishmael explicitly likens the Rachel to the Biblical Rachel, the mother of the Jewish people. In the Book of Jeremiah, Rachel weeps for her future descendants, exiled to Babylon by God; God promises to end that exile, in His own time, showing mercy for His chosen people. In the Book of Matthew Rachel’s story is said to have foreshadowed the murder of innocent children by Herod in his attempt to kill Jesus, prophesied to be a threat to his rule; the life and redemptive crucifixion of Jesus reveals God’s mercy not only toward Israelites but to all peoples. Even as he treats himself as God, Ahab put himself on the side of Herod.

    Nonetheless, Ahab continued to have his humanities. Having sent the grieving captain on his way, he returned to his cabin and to Pip, his adopted ‘son.’ “Lad, lad, I tell thee thou must not follow Ahab now”—not, to be sure, to save Pip from harm but because Pip, like the captain and his son, could distract him from his mission. “There is in thee, poor lad, which I feel too curing to my malady. Like cures like; and for this hunt, my malady becomes my most desired health.” Compassion, agape, would impede that hunt. Ahab’s sympathy for Pip based itself on the assumption that Pip’s imbecility both came from and symbolized the cold indifference of the chaos-cosmos. But Ahab was now proved mistaken. Pip retained a core not only of sanity but of gratitude and compassion in his own soul: “No, no, no! ye have not a whole body sir; do ye but use poor me for your one lost leg; only tread upon me, sir; I ask no more, so I remain a part of ye,” the one who had adopted him. Pip wept and pleaded, but as with Starbuck so with Pip: Ahab replied, “Weep so, and I will murder thee!” Ahab then recalled a shred of his Quaker Christianity, relenting only so much as to say, “God for ever bless thee; and if it come to that,—God for ever save thee, let what will befall.” That won’t happen; by rejecting his many opportunities to change his course, his regime or ‘way,’ Ahab doomed Pip along with himself. Ishmael comments, “All his successive meetings with various ships contrastingly concurred to show the demoniac indifference with which the white whale tore his hunters, whether sinning or sinned against,” but the telos of the Ahab regime “domineered above” the “gloomy crew.” “The old man’s despot eye was upon them.” [1]

    Ahab himself remained in a bondage of his own choosing. “Even as Ahab’s eyes so awed the crew’s, the inscrutable Parsee’s glance awed his; or somehow, at least in some wild way, at times affected it.” Both men stood on deck, day and night, awaiting the appearance of the Whale while gazing at each other, “as if in the Parsee Ahab saw his forethrown shadow, in Ahab the Parsee his abandoned substance”; “both seemed yoked together, and an unseen tyrant driving them.” Distrusting the dispirited crew, suspecting that they might deliberately pretend not to sight the Whale, Ahab commanded that he be hoisted to the top of a mast to serve as lookout. He shrewdly trusted Starbuck to hold the rope that pulled him up, rightly convinced that the First Mate would not allow an ‘accident’ to befall him. It would have been easy for Starbuck to arrange such a thing, but his God remains as silent as Ahab (or Machiavelli) would expect.

    If God does not speak in words, does He nonetheless speak in actions? As Ahab perched on the mast, a “sea-eagle” seized his hat and carried it away, dropping it into the sea. Ishmael recalls an omen associated with another intruder-usurper, Tarquin, the fifth king of ancient Rome.”An eagle flew thrice round Tarquin’s head, removing his cap to replace it, and thereupon Tanaquil, his wife”—reputed a prophetess—”declared that Tarquin would be king of Rome.” “But only by the replacing of the cap,” Ishmael recalls, “was that omen counted good. Ahab’s hat was never restored.”

    In ancient philosophy, Roman or Greek, the right telos of man and regimes was eudaimonia or the happiness attendant to the full development of human nature. Fedallah was no good daimon, Machiavelli no good philosopher, Ahab no good man. In its final gam the Pequod met the teleologically-named and, given its circumstances “most miserably named” Delight. Moby-Dick had shattered one of its boats, killing five men; captain and crew were burying with prayer the only body they had recovered. After hearing this, Ahab “like lightning” ordered his ship to sail on; his crew must not be permitted to dwell upon death, or God, lest fear of either overcome their fear of their ruler. Ahab imitated the god he has adopted, the electric fire which had caused his harpoon to burn with the fire of a serpent’s tongue.

    The tyrant himself had nearly reached the end of the rope of his will. If thoughts of his moral and political responsibilities, his family, and the Biblical God had not deterred him, could natural sentiments reach him? Ishmael describes the “symphony” of nature on the Pacific, as the “feminine” air, “transparently pure and soft,” and the “masculine” sea, with its “strong, troubled, murderous thinkings” blended into an “all-pervading azure” of “a clear steel-blue day.” For a while, “those two seemed one,” as the sun “seemed giving his gentle air to this bold and rolling sea; even as bride to groom”—a natural parallel of the spiritual doctrine of ‘one flesh.’ Ahab responded. “The step-mother world, so long cruel—forbidding—now threw affectionate arms around his stubborn neck, and did seem to joyously sob over him, as if over one, that however willful and erring, she could yet find it in her heart to save and to bless.” Nature might ‘save’ the man the Biblical God does not save—save him at least from tyrannical ambition and folly. “Ahab dropped a tear into the sea; nor did all the Pacific contain such wealth as that one wee drop.” Starbuck approached him, and Ahab offered the most pious man on his ship what amounts to a confession, calling himself a fool, an “Adam, staggering beneath the piled centuries since Paradise.” “Starbuck, let me look into a human eye; it is better than to gaze into sea or sky; better than to gaze upon God. By the green land; by the bright hearth-stone! this is the magic glass, man; I see my wife and my child in thine eye.” He told Starbuck to stay on board the ship when next the whale boats lower for Moby-Dick.

    At this one moment, Starbuck’s decision not to kill his captain seemed good. Better than dying a tyrant, Ahab might have returned if not to Christianity then at least to natural moral sentiment, to filial devotion to hearth and home—what Aristotle considered the foundation of political life. Starbuck urged Ahab to change course. “I think, sir, they have some such mild blue days, even as this, in Nantucket.” “But Ahab’s glance was averted” from his First Mate’s human eye; “like a blighted fruit tree,” Eden’s Tree of Knowledge, “he shook, and cast his last, cindered apple to the soil,” rejecting what he acknowledged as “all natural lovings and longings” of “my own natural heart,” recurring to the “handspike” of “Fate.” Not the natural-right philosophy of Aristotle but the fatalism of the Greek tragedians (and of Nietzsche, after Melville) remained Ahab’s North Star to the last. Starbuck left in despair; Ahab caught Fedallah’s eyes, reflected on the water. When Moby-Dick reappeared the next day, captain and crew returned to the hunt.

    The Whale “divinely swam” with “a gentle joyousness,” like a Jupiter or Jove of the sea. Nature turns hostile, but need not always be so. Knowing his own fate, Fedallah watched Moby-Dick with “a pale, death-glimmer” in “his sunken eyes; a hideous motion gnawed his mouth,” anticipating the same motion taken by the Whale’s jaw, which soon crushed Ahab’s boat with Fedallah and his ‘tigers’ in it. The ship rescued Ahab and crew, and here Ishmael pays tribute to the Captain’s greatness. Battered and exhausted, “nameless wails came from him, as desolate sounds from out ravines.” “In an instant’s compass, great hearts sometimes condense into one deep pang, the sum total of those shallow pains kindly diffused through feebler men’s whole lives.” “Such hearts” might “in their life-time aggregate a whole age of woe, wholly made up on instantaneous intensities; for even in their pointless centres, those noble natures contain the entire circumferences of inferior souls.” Ishmael’s language recalls the virtue he saw in Jesus, that He was a man of sorrows; if Ahab amounted to an anti-Christ, he was at least an anti-Christ, no Starbuck and very far from a Stubb.

    Recovering quickly, Ahab ascertained that no men had been lost and ordered the boat to be repaired. Materialist Stubb joked at the ruined boat (garbling an Aesop fable as he did), earning the Captain’s rebuke, “What soulless thing is this that laughs before a wreck?” For his part, pious Starbuck saw an ill omen in it, drawing a still sharper scolding: “Omen? omen?—the dictionary! If the gods think to speak outright to man, they will honorably speak outright; not shake their heads, and give an old wives’ darkling hint.” His riposte must have hit Starbuck harder than Ahab knew, as God had indeed failed to answer Starbuck’s plea for guidance when he considered committing tyrannicide. “Begone! Ye two are opposite poles of one thing…and ye two are all mankind; and Ahab stands alone among the millions of the peopled earth, nor gods nor men his neighbors!” He would be the greatest isolato of all, the supreme, all-ruling tyrant. As such, he moved again to secure his rule, announcing that the doubloon will go to the man who sights the Whale on the day it’s killed, then assuring his men that if he is the one to see him first, he’ll pay each man ten times the value of the doubloon. This lifted the gloom that had threatened to undermine his rule.

    On the second day of the hunt, newly-motivated Stubb exuberantly predicted that Ahab would kill Moby-Dick; he “did but speak out for well nigh all that crew.” “The hand of Fate had snatched all their souls; and by the stirring perils of the previous day; the rack of the past night’s suspense; the fixed, unfearing, blind, reckless way in which their wild craft went plunging towards its flying mark; by all these things, their hearts were bowled along” by the no-longer gentle wind, which “seemed the symbol of that unseen agency which so enslaved them to the race.” They had become fast-fish, not loose-fish. They had achieved perfect unity: “All varieties were welded into oneness, and were all directed to that fatal goal which Ahab their one lord and keel did point to,” striving “through that infinite blueness to seek out the thing that might destroy them.” Like Ahab’s harpoon, the tyrant-forged unity of the regime cut through the evanescent but natural unity of peaceful air, sea, and sun. Indeed, the wind itself picked up, “rushi[ing] the vessel on by arms invisible as irresistible.” Unlike the American regime, intended to keep the many varieties of citizens checked from their worst passions by setting ambition against ambition, interest against interest, thereby achieving a dynamic balance, Ahab’s crew now fused themselves to Ahab’s will, to one fate.”

    At the next lowering, Moby-Dick smashed two of the boats, not before entangling them in their own harpoon lines, like the weaver-god, Fate. He then attacked Ahab’s boat from below, and Ahab’s ivory leg splintered off. Rescued a second time, Ahab remained defiant: “Nor white whale nor man, nor fiend, can so much as graze old Ahab in his own proper and inaccessible being.” But Fedallah had disappeared, dragged under by Ahab’s line; given the prophecy Fedallah had issued and Ahab had believed, this gave the Captain pause. Starbuck took the event for one final chance at dissuasion: “Thy evil shadow gone—all good angels mobbing thee with warnings:—what more wouldst thou have?… Oh, oh,—Impiety and blasphemy to hunt him more!” But to him who denies the personal God, there can be no blasphemy except in the failure to resist, while contradictorily claiming fidelity to the chaos-cosmos: “Fool! I am the Fates’ lieutenant; I act under orders.” Turning to the superstitious sailors, he took care to sever any connection between Starbuck’s appeal and their beliefs. “Believe ye, men, in the things called omens? Then laugh aloud, and cry encore! For ere they drown, drowning things will twice rise to the surface; then rise again, to sink for evermore. So with Moby Dick….” But of course the same ‘omen’ might as well apply to the Captain himself. Speaking to himself, Ahab saw one of his contradictions, a different and deeper one: “Oh! how valiantly I seek to drive out of others’ hearts what’s clinched so fast in mine!”—namely, the Parsee’s omen or prophecy that he would “go before” Ahab in death, yet must be “seen again ere I could perish.” He vowed to solve this “riddle,” as he would do, on the third day of the hunt.

    His ivory leg replaced by the carpenter’s latest, last efforts, Ahab observed the beauty of the third day, calling it “food for thought, had Ahab time to think; but Ahab never thinks, he only feels, feels, feels; that’s tingling enough for mortal man!” “God only has that right and privilege,” the right and privilege to think. Willfully thoughtless Ahab then thought, speaking a monologue on the wind. It is “a coward wind that strikes stark naked men, but will not stand to receive a single blow. Even Ahab is a braver thing—a nobler thing than that. Would now the wind but had a body; but all the things that most exasperate and outrage mortal man, all these things are bodiless, but only bodiless as objects, not as agent. There’s a most special, a most cunning, oh, a most malicious difference!” The wind can strike but not be struck in retaliation. The wind is like God, exasperating but at times “glorious and gracious,” a spirit. For the moment Ahab’s mind swayed, so to speak, in the wind. But Moby-Dick’s reappearance tore him out of his thoughtful, willed thoughtlessness. This time, not only Ahab but the men on the three mastheads sighted the Whale simultaneously. “Three shrieks went up” from the sailors “as if tongues of fire had voiced it.” Fedallah’s spirit was now in the crew, talking in tongues inspired by an unholy spirit.

    As for the Whale, the spirit of fire had risen in him, as well. “Maddened by yesterday’s fresh irons that corroded in him, Moby Dick seemed combinedly possessed by all the angels that fell from heaven.” Upon sighting him, Ahab had bravely denied that Fedallah’s prophecy of doom could come true—that Ahab would die after seeing Fedallah one last time. How could a drowned man be seen again? “Aye, aye, like many more thou told’st direful truth as touching thyself, O Parsee; but, Ahab, there thy shot fell short.” “What is more, he exulted, “no coffin and no hearse can be mine—only hemp can kill me!”

    Moby-Dick surfaced, breaching the waves once again with a majestic, warning leap into the air. Pinioned to the Whale’s body by harpoon ropes, Fedallah’s body reappeared with the monster, the Parsee’s “distended eyes turned full upon old Ahab.” The Captain dropped his harpoon, seeing the prophecy fulfilled: Moby-Dick himself was the hearse. But “where is the second hearse?” Ahab demanded, threatening his boat-mates with harpooning if they jumped off their craft. “Ye are not other men, but my arms and my legs; and so obey me.” As the Whale began to swim off, Starbuck watched from the deck of the Pequod: “See! Moby Dick seeks thee not. It is thou, thou, that madly seekest him!”

    True enough, but when Ahab ordered Starbuck to set the Pequod‘s sails to follow his whale-boat, Starbuck again obeyed. The three harpooneers mounted the masts; while Ahab had chased the Whale, a sea-eagle had carried off the ship’s red flag, which Ahab, seeing it was no longer on the mainmast, ordered Tashtego to replace. Ahab’s boat caught up with Moby-Dick, and when Ahab’s re-seized harpoon struck the Whale, Moby-Dick charged not the boat but the now-nearby ship itself, “smiting his jaws amid fiery showers of foam.” Fiery showers: fire and water, Ahab’s worshiped “Father” and “Step-Mother,” combine in one image. “Is this the end of all my bursting prayers? all my lifelong fidelities?” panicked Starbuck wondered. The answer was yes, as Moby-Dick, “retribution, swift vengeance, eternal malice…in his whole aspect,” “smote the ship’s starboard bow,” breaching it with “his predestinating head.” Ahab saw and understood: The ship was the second hearse, the one made of American wood.

    Ahab made one last throw with the harpoon of the satanic baptism. This time the snaking hemp rope caught him, pulling him from the boat into the sea. The ship sank, sucking the last boat into its whirlpool. Tashtego, representative of the ‘first’ Americans, at the top of the mainmast, was the last to go down on the American-made hearse. Just before he did, he pinned the swooping sea-eagle to the mast, as it attempted to fly off with replacement flag. The ship, Ishmael thinks, was like Satan, who took a part of Heaven to Hell along with him. “The great shroud of the sea rolled on as it rolled five thousand years ago”—the time of the Flood.

    “And I only am escaped alone to tell thee.” The Epilogue’s epigram is from Job 1: 14-19, the coda of each of the four messengers who reported a flood of disasters to Job. Ishmael means to be the bringer of bad news to Americans, but why? He is, after all, an Ishmael—a perpetual exile.

    He had been thrown overboard from Ahab’s whale-boat during the fight. He ascribes his presence in Ahab’s boat to “the Fates,” who caused him to take the place of Fedallah there. Thrown from the boat, “floating on the margin of the ensuing scene, and in full sight of it”—exiled by Moby-Dick, Fate’s agent—he found himself slowly drawn “towards the closing vortex” as the Pequod sank. “Like another Ixion I did revolve.” Ixion is the Ishmael-figure of classical mythology, equally an exile, although for the crime of having pushed his father into a fire. The gods take him up, much to their regret, and eventually he provoked punishment by Jupiter for committing adultery with Hera, attached to a wheel of fire for eternity. The physical wheel of water has its counterpart in the ideational or mythological wheel of fire, both these contradictory elements serving as objects of Ahabian worship. Unlike Ahab, Ishmael escaped the wheel. Queequeg’s “coffin life buoy” reached the center of the vortex before Ishmael could be sucked into it, then shot up as the ship went under, propelled by the resulting jet of water. Ishmael clung to it and survived overnight. He was picked up by the Rachel, the following day. “In her retracing search after her missing children, [she] only found another orphan.”

    Queequeg, the man of nature, in effect saved his friend by volunteering his coffin for use as a life-buoy, crafted and recrafted by the carpenter or mindless Christ. Ishmael was saved also by the captain of the Rachel, a man of familial moral sentiment and Biblical agape. Biblically-oriented readers will find in these and so many remarkable events prior to it the hand of Providence. Ishmael does not. Does Melville? Perhaps not, since after all his is the ruling intelligence behind the novel, and we have no way of knowing that he ascribed that gift to God.

     

    Note

    1. For a comparison of Ahab and Pip with King Lear and his Fool, see Olson, op. cit., 58-63.

     

     

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    The ‘Progressive’ Critique of the Declaration of Independence

    April 11, 2019 by Will Morrisey

    Lecture first delivered at the Center for Teaching Excellence, Hillsdale College, July 2006.

     

    The challenge of teaching the American Founding is that their political theory was simple—indeed, self-evident—but understanding their actions, their practice, is hard. The notion that no one has the right to murder you, enslave you, or otherwise ruin your life isn’t hard to understand. It’s the way that the Founders acted to secure the unalienable rights of American citizens, and the reasons for their failure fully to secure them that requires intensive study.

    The challenge of teaching the Progressives’ re-founding of the American regime is fairly easy to understand in practice. We see their successes all around us in such institutions as the administrative state, in such Constitutional measures as the income tax and the popular election of U. S. Senators, and in our expectation that politicians serve as leaders of their American people. But the political theory animating Progressivism is anything but self-evident. Progressivism breaks radically with previous American political principles. To see this, consider a question I asked students many times, without ever hearing the right answer.

    The Declaration of Independence begins: “When in the course of human events.”

    Why not, “When in history….”?

    Because for the Founders the word ‘history’ did not mean the course of human events. At their time, ‘history’ meant the historia rerum gestarum —the story or account of things that are born and pass away, the story of the course of human events. A ‘history’ was a narrative, a literary genre, and a mode of inquiry.

    Philosophy and poetry are also modes of inquiry. Following the well-known imagery of Plato’s Republic philosophy was considered the rational ascent from the cave of conventional opinions, into the daylight of truth. Plato’s Socrates engaged in ‘dialectic’—argumentation governed by logic, which is thought governed by the principle of non-contradiction. The first statement of that principle in Western thought is enunciated by Socrates in that dialogue: The same thing will not do, or have done to it, opposites, at the same time, with respect to the same part, or in relation to the same thing. So, for example, an object might be black and white, or gray, but it cannot be ‘blackwhite.’ You can inscribe a circle in a square or a square in a circle, but you can’t draw a square circle. Philosophic inquiry governed by that principle eliminates false or self-contradictory arguments.

    Poetry was understood as an imitation or ‘imaging’ of true things—holding the mirror up to nature, as Dr. Samuel Johnson said, around the same time the Declaration was written. The equivalent of dialectic in poetry is drama, a sort of argument in action: Achilles against Hector, God against Satan, Hamlet against himself.

    History, however, put into words what had been seen, in the course of human events. Only then can those events last, be remembered, continue to be inquired into. By writing a ‘history,’ the historian fixes events, holds them in place, making the comprehensible to the intellect, which can understand only that which ‘stays put.’ Like philosophic dialectic and poetic drama, a history also presents conflict. Thus Thucydides tells us that he writes a work “for all time,” after having seen “the greatest war of all time.” He chose a course of events—a massive, violent change—which revealed something great and permanent in human nature, which does not change.

    Poetic drama, philosophic dialectic, and political history all aim at inquiring about the permanent things by an ascent from the human-all-too-human conflicts or contradictions we see all around us. All of these genres of writing and of thought comport with the doctrine of natural right familiar to us in the Declaration of Independence, because natural right is a permanent thing. In the American regime, the Founders sought to secure the natural rights of citizens by means of a well-defined, limited constitutional government.

    But around the same time the Founders lived, ‘history’ began to be redefined not as the story of the course of human events but as the res gestae —the course of events itself. What is more, philosophers soon began to turn to the course of human events not merely as a source of what human nature is, but as something that constituted human nature. That is, they began to think of human nature—and of all nature—as something not fixed but evolving. According to historicism, man is fundamentally a historical being, not a natural being. Nature itself is historical, constantly changing or evolving; nature has no permanent ‘nature,’ so to speak.

    Still further, the early nineteenth century philosophers—the greatest of them was the German, G. W. F. Hegel—looked to ‘history’ or the course of events as the source of moral and political authority. Why? European philosophy had already abandoned religion as a source of moral and political authority. The Enlightenment tended toward atheism. The French Revolutionaries’ appeal to moral authority issued in “The Rights of Man and of the Citizen.” that is to say, by the time the United States Constitution had been ratified, ‘enlightened’ Europeans had rejected divine right as a monarchic myth and substituted for it the natural rights of man.

    The problem with deriving moral and political authority or rights from nature, for these European philosophers, was simple. They were materialists. And they conceived of matter ‘atomistically.’ If all nature, including human nature, is nothing but matter in motion, how do you get morality out of that? If human beings are nothing but bodies composed of vibrating atoms, if that’s what human nature is, then there is no ‘ought’ to be extracted from it, no right to be derived from it. for human life to have moral significance it needs a purpose, a telos. But if human nature has no built-in purpose, because it’s nothing but matter in motion, and if there is no God to give Creation a purpose, both natural teleology and religious teleology make no sense Enlightenment seems to result in nihilism, in darkness rather than light.

    Further, even as the Enlightenment rejected God and began to reject nature as sources of moral and political authority, it also rejected human laws and other conventions. The Enlighteners were, after all, revolutionaries, dissatisfied with the status quo of existing laws and other conventions. Where would human beings turn for guidance, with all the existing sources of authority now discarded?

    Here is where the German philosophers stepped in. Hegel contended that the only possible source of moral and political authority remaining to ‘enlightened’ human beings was history itself. Human history, he said, has been working toward an end, a telos, a purpose, all along, although until Hegel’s time no one had been able to see what that purpose is. According to Hegel, human history is the course of events by which human beings have conquered nature, subjecting it more and more to the human will. The story of the conquest of nature is thus the story of human progress toward ever greater freedom of the exercise of the human will over nature or brute matter. The meaning of ‘history’ or the course of events, its purpose, is that progressively unfolding freedom over nature, through time. Doctrines centered on divine revelation and doctrines centered on nature right now must give way to doctrines we may call, as a group, historicist or progressive. The ‘progressive’ person is, to use the word deployed by both Hegel and Marx, conscious of his place in history’s movement; a leader is conscious of how to hasten history’s forward movement toward the end of history.

    To see how radical this philosophic turn to historicism was, consider it in contrast to the teaching of the Bible. the Bible also tells us that the course of events has meaning. God guides the course of events. Theologians call this ‘providence.’ How does providentialism differ from historicism?

    The God of the Bible creates the heavens and the earth out of nothing. He then forms an out of part of that creation, earth, and breathes His Spirit into that clay, thus creating man as an image of Himself. Thus God differs radically from all of His creation; He did not make the heavens and the earth out of Himself, extruding them in the manner of an amoeba. Again to use theological language, the God of the Bible is not ‘immanent’ in His creation. The created being closest to God, man, derives his authority over the rest of God’s creation from the breath of divine Spirit that constitutes part of him. But this creature quickly learns that he is not God, whatever the Serpent may whisper in his wife’s ear. More, his Creator issues increasingly elaborate sets of commands which serve as standards for his conduct, standards that do not change until the Creator Himself changes them. Both laws and Lawgiver are ‘above’ man.

    Hegel’s historicism is entirely different. Hegel argues that the course of human events or history is not guided by a radically separate Creator-God. Hegel teaches that history is infused with rationality, with what Hegel calls the Absolute Spirit. The Absolute Spirit has nothing to do with God, the Holy Spirit. Holiness implies purity, separation from matter; the Absolute Spirit dwells within matter. Indeed, matter is nothing but a congealed form of the Absolute Spirit. Matter evolves in accordance with a logical pattern. Instead of “Laws of Nature and of Nature’s God,” historicism posits laws of history, laws of the unfolding of the Absolute Spirit.

    Each historical epoch has its own spirit. The “spirit of the age” or Zeitgeist is the Absolute Spirit in its current stage of evolution or development. As in a logical syllogism, all contradictions will finally disappear. History behaves logically; the clash of opposites—whether opposing ideas, opposing social classes, opposing races, opposing armies—eventually resolves itself into the end of all historical conflict, namely, a world state that results in peace. History consists, therefore, of a logical dialectic, a set of knowable laws of progress. The dialectic previously understood as man’s rational inquiry into the nature of things—in poetry, philosophy, and history—now came to be conceived as the process whereby human beings, over time, mastered nature while disposing of previous systems of thought (including the Bible) as retrograde mythology.

    The scholar Eric Voegelin rightly said that historicism “immanentizes the eschaton.” It puts ‘god’ into creation, into the course of events caused by matter in motion. It fuses the ‘is’ with the ‘ought,’ might with right—on this earth, not in Heaven. What happens is also what should happen, because progress, moral rightness, is built into the historical process itself. In Christianity, a religion of the Creator-God, the eschaton has only been ‘immantized’ on one occasion, so far: in the life and person of Jesus Christ. And that life, on this earth, ended with a return to the separation of Creator from created—with the Crucifixion and the Resurrection, that is, with the return of Jesus to His Father in Heaven. Jesus left behind His assembly or church, but, a Paul shows in his epistles, God’s assembly proves eminently fallible. The Kingdom of God on earth will only begin when Jesus rules a new heaven and a new earth—a new creation. And even that new creation won’t be infused with God, who will rule it as the holy God.

    Speaking of ruling, I turn from the moral to the political dimension of historicism. Hegel and his philosophic followers understood moral and political authority to consist of this ever-widening sphere of human freedom or human conquest of nature. Intellectually, the saw the locus of the conquest of nature in modern science, and the powerful technologies that already had begun to bring space and time under ever-increasing human control or mastery. They saw the political locus of the conquest of nature in the modern state. The modern state, which crucially centralizes human control of persons and territories in one location, one capital city, and which then extends its administrative power to its borders by means of a rule-governed bureaucracy, struck historicists as the very embodiment of the modern project of freedom or rule over nature.

    This means that the highest form of human freedom is located not in the individual or the family, or in the free enterprise of the people, or in the governmental institutions to which the people elect their representatives, but in the state, especially in its ‘technocratic’ element, the bureaucracy, not elected and at best ‘overseen’ by the people’s elected representatives. So constituted, the state masters nature more effectively than any individual or family can ever do.

    Historicism also means that the most ‘authoritative’ things will happen in the future. In taking his moral bearings, a historicist does not ‘look back to “In the beginning,” to the Creator-God. Nor does a historicist ‘look around’ to the nature created by that God. Nor does he look within himself, at human nature. A historicist must rather look forward, forward to the ‘end of history’—to the World State, as in Hegel, to communism, as in Marx, or to the supreme Aryan world empire, as in Nazism. To put it another way men are not by nature angels now, but as mankind evolves, becoming more and more masterful, we will become much more like angels. The Absolute Spirit is working itself out in us.

    Politically, this means that historicism requires of politicians not governance in accordance with stable principles but leadership. The leader leads his people into the morally authoritative future. The leader is the secular prophet of a promised land to be built entirely with human hands and brains. Human hands and brains are the Absolute Spirit at work.

    The leader himself does not suffice to get us there, however. The prophets of God in the Bible know what to do and where to go because God tells them. God knows what to tell them because he is all-knowing: He knows not only the overall goal but He also knows every step of the way, the number of hairs on every head, every sparrow that will fall. A human leader, by contrast, may know the goal but he cannot know every detail that needs tending. For rule over the details, for effective human providence, he needs bureaucracy—a systematic and centralized administrative state.

    Here’s where the American Progressives come in. Historicist ideas entered the United States in the early decades of the nineteenth century through a variety of what might be described as ‘cultural middlemen’—intellectuals who studied German philosophy, translating its ideas to the American context. One of the most famous of these figures was Ralph Waldo Emerson. Later on, an important figure in the American historicist movement was the educator William Torrey Harris, among the most prominent of the Saint Louis Hegelians, who served as President Grant’s Education Commissioner in the 1870s; other historicists settled into positions at major universities.

    But the ontological historicism of these disparate figures did not yet advocate statism in America. One of Emerson’s most famous essays celebrated American individualism, and Harris was a Social Darwinist. The movement toward an American statism centered in academia, beginning in the decades after the Civil War. Historicism linked itself to statism earlier in Europe because in Europe statism preceded historicism.

    Throughout Europe, universities initially had been instituted by the Roman Catholic Church, an eminently international, not statist, institution. When Niccolo Machiavelli conceived of the modern, centralized state in the early sixteenth century, he intended it as the key institutional weapon against the rule of the Church, and therewith the influence of Christianity. But after Machiavelli’s young, and Christian, contemporary Martin Luther broke with the Church, his followers discovered that states could serve as guardians of Protestant Christianity; only states were politically strong enough, because sufficiently centralized, to resist the international Papacy and its military and political allies. This circumstance in turn made the Protestant universities in the German countries ally themselves with their respective states. That is, by the time the Peace of Westphalia solemnized the modern international system of states in 1648, norther German universities had adapted themselves to statism. And when Bismarck and the Hohenzollern monarchy consolidated most of the many German states into one large nation-state in the middle of the nineteenth century the German universities were structured as appendages of that state. The study of political life consisted primarily not of the study of natural rights and regimes but the study of administration or bureaucracy as the authoritative instantiation of historical and dialectical progress.

    German academics set themselves the task of finding scientific methods by which the state might rule more efficiently and thus, in the words of University of Nevada Professor John Marini, to “establish the rational structures whereby organized intelligence, or knowledge derived from the scientific method, would begin the process of solving, progressively, the political, social, economic, and cultural problems of the nation.”  As Marini also observes, the young scholars who established political science as a separate discipline within the American universities typically attended graduate school in Germany in the late nineteenth century, thus absorbing the principles of German social science, the handmaiden of German statism. It is important to understand that the German unification of the states via the institutional structures of the administrative state must have looked especially attractive to young Americans who grew up during the Civil War, not only because such a state promised to end the political corruption associated with political parties and the party ‘bosses’ but because rule by professional bureaucrats looked like an efficient way to bind small and medium-sized states into one big national state—precisely the problem the federal republic of the American Founders had solved only at the cost of a catastrophic war. With this institutional reform came the vast reconstruction of philosophic doctrine mentioned earlier, the move from natural right to historical right. By 1895, John J. Lalor’s Cyclopedia of the Social Sciences classified “Natural Law” under “Fictions”—this, in an article assuring readers that “the sphere of fiction must steadily diminish as that of inductive and positive science advances and as man’s mind becomes stronger, clearer, and more discerning.”

    The best known of these young American scholars studied politics and administration as a graduate student at the Johns Hopkins University—the first American university modeled after the German research universities, staffed with professors who had done their own graduate studies at those universities. His name was Woodrow Wilson. He of course went on to the presidency of Princeton University, the governorship of New Jersey, and the presidency of the United States.

    As a twenty-year-old undergraduate, one who spent ten years of his boyhood and early adolescence in Augusta, Georgia during the Civil War and the hated Reconstruction, Wilson confided to his diary serious reservations about the American regime of 1876: “The American Republic will in my opinion never celebrate another Centennial. At least under its present Constitution and laws.” The United States is only “a miserable delusion of a republic…founded upon the notion of abstract liberty!”—that is, natural right. As had several of his most prominent Southern intellectual forebears, particularly John C. Calhoun, Wilson admired England’s mixed regime; “the English form of government is the only true one.

    Any Ivy League education and subsequent graduate training turned this Burkean Southern conservative into a devotee of ‘Germany.’ In a book written for college students, Wilson engaged in that sub-discipline of political science that would come to be called ‘comparative regimes.’ ‘Comparative’ politics as the Germans conceived it compared the supposedly inherent characteristics of different nations or races. Which ones are the strongest, the most vital, the most likely to win the struggle for survival and domination? Nations and states are organisms which interact dialectically. He distinguished political systems that are “defeated or dead” from “those which are alive and triumphant”—a point any American southerner would find compelling. Because peoples of German origin dominated the world at the time, “it is Aryan practice we principally wish to know.” England remained Wilson’s favorite among the Aryan nations, for its gradualism of development. The United States, insofar as it had any political merit at all, derived it from its adaptation of English institutions. Wilson tried to account for the Civil War not at all in terms of unalienable right or of American republicanism but entirely in terms of “national feeling”—nationalism—itself based primarily upon social and economic differences between the North and the South.

    Wilson thus took German historicism and democratized it for American use. The esteem for democracy is the distinguishing feature of American Progressivism. Wilson claimed that democracy, not monarchy, was the final stage of human development. Its “true concept…is inseparable from the organic theory of the state.” Wilsonian ‘democracy’ bears as close a resemblance to Hegelian monarchy as it can, without ceasing to be democratic. “Properly organized democracy is the best government of the few,” representative government. But—and here the Hegelian surfaces—bureaucracy or “civil service” is “but another process of representation.” The science of administration is “the latest fruit of [the] science of politics,” a science “developed by French and German professors.” It “must inhale free American air,” but it nonetheless embodies the Hegelian “spirit of the time,” that is, the current stage of the dialectical development of the Absolute Spirit.”

    Thus Wilson presented an extraordinary and revolutionary political agendum as an act of incremental conservatism. He cautiously assayed the political difficulties of his project. Convinced that “the democratic state” as yet lacked the means for carrying “those enormous burdens of administration which the needs of this industrial and trading age are so fast accumulating,” yet mindful that “it is harder for democracy to organize administration than [it is] for monarchy” to do so because public opinion rules democracy, often in a “meddlesome” way, Wilson sought to exercise a new kind of statesmanship to found a new kind of regime.

    The new, historicist statesmanship would not so much defend the existing regime as lead the people to new modes and orders of life. “Society is not a crowd, but an organism, and, like every organism, it just grow as a whole or else be deformed.” “Leaders of men” precipitate the “evolution of [society’s institutions” with “creative power”—the most recent example of these having been Otto von Bismarck. The leader is a sort of secular prophet: “He must read the common thought: he must calculate very circumspectly the preparation of the nation for the next move in the progress of politics…. the nice point is to distinguish the firm and progressive popular thought from the momentary and whimsical popular mood, the transitory or mistaken popular passion.” The leader is the good shepherd of the spirit of the age.

    Thus the new historicist leadership of progress requires a new kind of prudence. The new prudence foresees the course of events; it is literally promethean. Jane Addams, the prominent Progressive reformer whom Wilson cultivated as a political ally, described herself as “a little uneasy in regard to [Wilson’s] theory of self-government.” He seemed “as if he were not so eager for a mandate to carry out the will of the people as for an opportunity to lead the people whither in his judgment their best interest lay.” There has been no more sensible insight.

    This also means that the United States Constitution as written and amended simply won’t do. It is ‘Newtonian,’ not ‘Darwinian,’ aimed at balance instead of growth. It is, as Wilson titled an important essay, “The Elastic Constitution.” A more recent jurist called it “the Living Constitution.”

    Ultimately, Wilson contended, the best interest of the people lies in socialism, the logical result of ‘democratic’ Hegelianism. If society is an organism, then “the community” has “the absolute right…to determine its own destiny and that of its members,” for “men as communities are supreme over men as individuals.” While “wisdom and convenience” may require the limitation of public control over economic activity, “limits of principle” upon that control “there are, upon strict analysis, none.” Democracy finally requires socialism. To achieve it, an existing political democracy needs a modern bureaucracy founded by a “leader of men”—a new kind aristocracy, eventually calling itself ‘meritocracy,’ claiming to rule not on the basis of warrior and civic virtues or social and intellectual refinement but on technical expertise.

    That is to say, political progressivism appropriates two pieces of the modern scientific project. The dramatic and bold part of that project, the conquest of nature, may be seen in the person of the leader. The mundane, routine, precise, and detailed part of the project may be seen in administration. The popular support for the statist project comes not from natural right form the sentiment of nationalism (eventually to be replaced by an international world state), which registers the vitality of the national organism. In contrast to the Declaration of Independence, progressivism substitutes historical progress for natural right, taking the task of government not to be limited to securing the natural rights of individuals and nations but rather as the much more ambitious task of guiding humanity toward the end of history, the unlimited universal state.

    In making these changes, in making a mantra of ‘change’ itself, did American Progressivism actually cost Americans anything valuable? Did it cause us to abandon any of the individual and national rights we secured under the Founders’ regime? Consider the first establishment of a solid structure of Progressive institutions during the New Deal, an establishment prepared by the passage of the Constitutional amendments to legalize the income tax and to require popular votes for United States senators, accomplished a generation earlier. The best description of the administrative state Franklin Roosevelt and his allies bequeathed us was published exactly 100 years before his landslide re-election in 1936. It was Alexis de Tocqueville who coined the term “administrative despotism,” which he described in a famous passage near the end of the first volume of Democracy in America:

    “I want to imagine with what new features despotism could be produced in the world: I see an innumerable crowd of like and equal men who revolve on themselves without repose, procuring the small and vulgar pleasures with which they fill their souls. Each of them, withdrawn and apart, is like a stranger to the destiny of all others: his children and his particular friends form the whole human species for him; as for dwelling with his fellow citizens, he is beside them, but he does not see them…he exists only in himself and for himself alone….

    “Above these an immense tutelary power is elevated, which alone takes charge of assuring their enjoyments and watching over their fate. It is absolute, detailed, regular, far-seeing, and mild. It would resemble paternal power if, like that, it had for its object to prepare men for manhood; but on the contrary, it seeks only to keep them fixed irrevocably in childhood; it likes citizens to enjoy themselves provided that they think only of enjoying themselves. It willingly works for their happiness; but it wants to be the unique agent and sole arbiter of that; it provides for their security, foresees and secures their needs, facilitates their pleasures, conducts their principal affairs, directs their industry, regulates their estates, divides their inheritances; can it not take away from them entirely the trouble of thinking and the pain of living”

    “So it is that every day it renders the employment of free will less useful and more rare; it confines the action of the will in a smaller space and little by little steals the very use of it from each citizens. Equality has prepared men for all these things: it has disposed them to tolerate them and often even to regard them as a benefit.

    “Thus, after taking each individual by turns in its powerful hands and kneading him as it likes, the sovereign extends its arms over society as a whole; it covers its surface with a network of small, complicated, painstaking, uniform rules through which the  most original minds and the most vigorous souls cannot clear a way to surpass the crowd; it does not break wills, but it softens them, bends them, and directs them; it rarely forces one to act, but it constantly opposes itself to one’s acting; it does not destroy, it prevents things from being born; it does not tyrannize, it hinders, compromises, enervates, extinguishes, dazes, and finally reduces each nation to being nothing more than a herd of timid and industrious animals of which the government is the shepherd.

    “Our contemporaries are incessantly racked by two inimical passions: they feel the need to be led and the wish to remain free. Not being able to destroy either one of these contrary instincts, they strive to satisfy both at the same time. They imagine a unique power, tutelary, all powerful, but elected by citizens. They combine centralization and the sovereignty of the people. That gives them some respite. They consoled themselves for being in tutelage by thinking that they themselves have chosen their schoolmasters….

    “In our day there are many people who accommodate themselves very easily to this kind of compromise between administrative despotism and the sovereignty of the people, and who think they have guaranteed the freedom of individuals well enough when they deliver it to the national power. That does not suffice for me. The nature of the master is much less important to me than the obedience.”

    Many of us here today teach civics. To rebuild an active, civic spirit of self-government—as against the passivity of the administrative state—is what we do. We can only do it effectively if we recall the principles and practices of the American Founders, notice the contrast between them and those of the Progressives, then teach that contrast to our students.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    “Moby-Dick”: Storm

    April 11, 2019 by Will Morrisey

    This is the twelfth of a series of essays on Melville’s novel.

     

    The Pequod caught a forward breeze. A few days after its gam with the Bachelor the crew killed four whales, one harpooned by Ahab himself, evidently practicing for the anticipated encounter with his nemesis. He considered the way a Sperm Whale dies, turning its head toward the sun: “He too worships fire; most faithful, broad, baronial vassal of the sun!” The seas, “where to traditions no rocks furnish tablets,” “life dies sunwards full of faith,” only to be spun around “some other way” after death, toward the “dark Hindoo half of nature.” “In vain, oh whale, dost thou seek intercedings with yon all-quickening sun, that only calls forth life, but gives it not again. Yet dost thou, darker half, rock me with a prouder, if a darker faith.” Ahab wants nothing of the solid rock of Christ, the Son, turning instead to the larger, darker sea, whose billows “are my foster-brothers.” He seeks a rock in something vast and fluid, a chaos-rock.

    One of the whales couldn’t be hauled in immediately, so Ahab and his boat-crew stayed with it. Fedallah watched his fellow-predators, the sharks; Ahab told him of a recurring dream, a dream of hearses. It is time for prophecy. Fedallah reminded him that “neither hearse nor coffin can be thine”; at sea, there are no hearses, but before Ahab can die he must see two hearses at sea, “the first not made by mortal hands,” the second made with wood grown in America. What is more, Fedallah must die before Ahab; he must be Ahab’s “pilot,” his guide into death, if he is to die. In exchange, Fedallah has made two promises: that Ahab shall kill Moby-Dick and survive the killing. Fedallah adds another promise—that “hemp only can kill thee.” Ahab assumed that means the gallows, but should recall that the dangerous, snake-like ropes in the boat he sits in whip dangerously after the harpooneer lances a whale. Does Fedallah lie, or deceive?

    In the Sea of Japan, the land of the rising sun, the summer sea under that sun shimmers with an “unrelieved radiance” like “the insufferable splendors of God’s throne,” the white throne of judgment. Fire-worshipping Fedallah gazed at the sun, which Ahab (now changing symbols, so to speak), called “my Pilot.” He asked the sun, “Where is Moby Dick?” Indeed the sun ‘sees’ half the world at a time. But the sun, silent as always, told him nothing. In fury he destroyed the ship’s quadrant, cursing “Science,” the “foolish toy”; “no longer will I guide my earthly way by thee” not because the quadrant is a human instrument but because it “feebly pointest on high,” toward heavenly bodies like the sun, whereas the ship’s other instruments, the compass and the log-and-line, point him along the surface of the sea, his fluid rock. Overhearing the Captain’s tirade, bluff Stubb concurs. “Damn me, Ahab, but thou actest right; live in the game, and die in it!” Ishmael isn’t the Captain’s only secret sharer.

    The sea’s potential chaos overtook the Pequod, struck by a sudden typhoon. Dutiful Starbuck wished they would ride with the gale, towards home, instead of against it, towards Moby-Dick. Ahab had other plans. As lightning sets fire to the three masts, he shrieks to the crew, “The white flame but lights the way to the White Whale!” Ishmael compares the lightning to “God’s burning fingers” as He wrote the words of judgment against Belshazzar as recounted in the Book of Daniel: “MENE, MENE, TEKEL, UPHARSIN.” The king calls upon the Chaldeans—Fedallah’s ancestors—to interpret these words, but they fail. They prove poor prophets. Only Daniel can understand truly: That God has numbered the days of Belshazzar’s kingdom; that the king has been weighed in the balance and founding wanting; that his kingdom will be divided and given to the Medes and the Persians. Belshazzar is killed the following night. As the “H” in “UPHARSIN” implies, the sundering of Ahab’s regime will take breath away.

    Nonetheless, Ahab follows the Parsee. He prayed to the “trinity of flames,” worshiping them in a reversal of the way a Christian would pray to the Divine Trinity: “O! thou clear spirit of clear fire, whom on these seas I as Persian once did worship, till in the sacramental act so burned by thee, that to this hour I bear the scar; I now know thee, thou clear spirit, and I now know that thy right worship is defiance.” There is no kindness in chaos-nature, only “speechless, placeless power.” Therefore, “To the last gasp of my earthquake life will dispute its unconditional, unintegral mastery in me. In the midst of the personified impersonal, a personality stands here.” “A true child of fire, I breathe it back to thee.” Stubb had whispered about Ahab’s scar, months before, comparing it to the crack in a tree struck by lightning. If Ahab were an ordinarily evil man, he would lack this nobility, the character of the tragic hero which Ishmael suggests by his periodic allusions to Lear—here, to Ahab’s “beaten brain,” both comparable to and contrasting with the live, “beating” brain of Shakespeare’s king. Ahab’s brain has been beaten, finally, not by Fate or Fedallah but by itself, by its own inner flaw. He had that flaw before he met Fedallah. did Fate give it to him, or did he give it to himself? Having it, did he need to succumb to it?

    Ahab regards the Creator-God as mindless. “Thou knowest not how came ye, hence callest thyself unbegotten; certainly knowest not thy beginning, hence callest thyself unbegun…. I know that of me, which thou knowest not of thyself, oh, thou omnipotent. There is some unsuffusing thing beyond thee, thou clear spirit, to whom all thy eternity is but time, all thy creativeness mechanical.” As humans are to the God of the Bible, so the Biblical God is to—call it Fate. As a personality confronting an impersonal foolishly supposed personal by mythologizing prophets and priests, and their dupes, Ahab worshipped the truly impersonal Fire by defying it. Prudence dictates otherwise, but why would a noble man not defy such a being?

    Poor Starbuck read matters differently. When lightning struck Ahab’s steel harpoon with “forked fire” like “a serpent’s tongue,” he told the Captain that “God, God is against thee.” Turn home “while we may,” on “a better voyage than this.” This panicked the crew, who “raised a half mutinous cry.” Immediately recognizing a nascent revolutionary moment, Ahab seized his burning harpoon and “waved it like a torch among them; swearing to transfix with it the first sailor that but cast loose a rope’s end.” The threat of force stopped them, giving him a chance to reinforce his rule with speech, reminding them of their oath to hunt the White Whale, an oath “as binding as mine”—’totalitarian,’ encompassing “heart, soul, and body, lungs and life.” To these words he added a final action, blowing out the fire on the harpoon and roaring, “Thus I blow out the last fear!” The last fear of God, but not the last fear in the souls of the men. Quite the contrary: Instead of overpowering the tyrant, the men, so threatened and so reminded, fled in terror. Starbuck’s attempt to rally ‘the many’ to his side thus failed. “Oh, none but cowards send down their brain trucks in tempest time,” Ahab said to himself, even as he reminded himself, Lear-like, to “take medicine.” But while Lear takes “physic” in order to expose himself “to feel what wretches feel” and thus dispose himself to charity toward them, Ahab remains a tyrant, not a king, knowing what wretches feel only to rule them for his own purpose, not their succour. As for the officers and the harpooneers, they do not share in the sailors’ panic but neither do their souls have the strength to rebel; Stubb could only say to Flask, “This is a nasty night, lad,” and Tashtego wished for a glass of rum. At this moment, was anyone on the Pequod better than a would-be drunken Indian?

    The typhoon passed, the crew cheered and began repairing the ship, as ordered by the officers. The ‘many’ respond to immediate success and failure and except for Starbuck, the ‘few’—officers and harpooneers—were little better. Only the First Mate clearly foresaw the ultimate disaster to which Ahab directed the ship. Only he could act to stop it, and chance now gave him the opportunity.

    Starbuck went below deck to report to his Captain on the new conditions on deck. He saw the muskets on the gun rack, including the musket Ahab had aimed at him. “An evil thought” occurred to him, which he found hard to suppress. Should he kill Ahab, as Ahab had been ready to kill him? The gun was already loaded.

    How evil is that thought? “Shall this crazed old man be tamely suffered to drag a whole ship’s company down to doom with him?”—effectively murdering more than thirty men. He found Ahab asleep, incapable of resisting. Neither reasoning, nor remonstrance, nor entreaty had swayed the tyrant; Starbuck had tried them all. Alogos, immoralist, and un-agapic, the tyrant demanded only “flat obedience to [his] own flat commands.” As for the vow, the contract Ahab had cited, “Great God forbid!” that we make ourselves lesser Ahabs. Ahab’s real underlying ‘contract,’ the one with Fedallah, ignores the good of ship and crew; a king would rule for the good of his people but the tyrant rules for himself, for an illusory self-interest. Assenting to the contract with Ahab, officers, harpooneers, and crew assented to the contract with Fedallah, a soul reminiscent of the Prince of Liars.

    Was there no “lawful way” to proceed? No: restrained, Ahab “would be more hideous than a caged tiger, then, I could not endure the sigh; could not possibly fly his howlings; all comfort, sleep itself, inestimable reason would leave me on the long intolerable voyage.” Ahab would murder sleep, as Macbeth’s conscience did; an anti-conscience, Ahab was the monster that would put reason to sleep. There was no law for Starbuck to fear, here on the open sea. “Is heaven a murderer when its lightning strikes a would-be murderer, tindering sheets and skin together?” Surely not: Starbuck might kill with impunity and also without moral hazard. With Ahab dead, Starbuck might see his wife—named Mary, for the mother of Jesus—and child again. Without Ahab dead, he would not. Personal, political, and familial morality alike command tyrannicide.

    Starbuck then appealed to the final authority. “Great God, where art thou? Shall I? shall I?” Nowhere in this yarn does God speak to anyone. Events occur, which may or may not be interpreted as providential, but God is always silent. Here, only Ahab spoke, in his unreasoning sleep. After Starbuck made his brief report to the Captain, Ahab in his dream replied, characteristically, with a command: “Stern all! Oh Moby Dick, I clutch thy heart at last!” It was “as if Starbuck’s voice,” as he softly dialogued with himself and his God, and then to Ahab, “had caused the long dumb dream to speak.” “Starbuck seemed wrestling with an angel.” But unlike Jacob, he let go. “He placed the death-tube in its rack, and left the place.” He went back on deck and told Stubb to wake Ahab and make the report, prevaricating that “I must see to the deck here.” His conscience had made a coward of him. There would be no just coup d’état, no revolution against tyranny on the Pequod. The ship’s ruler pursued defiant rebellion against the personified impersonal; its potential ruler could not bring himself to rebel against that ruler. These two extremes spell catastrophe as surely as MENE, MENE, TEKEL, UPHARSIN.

    In the aftermath of the natural storm and the political near-storm, the waves still billowed, the sunlight gleaming on the ocean, making it seem “a crucible of molten gold.” Awake and secure in his power, Ahab exclaimed in megalomaniacal exultation, “All ye nations before my prow, I bring the sun to ye!” As Melville’s symbolism would have it, the ship’s compass needle had been deranged by the lightning strike, so Ahab takes charge of adjusting the ship’s course. Officers and men obey; “though some of [the sailors] lowly rumbled, their fear of Ahab was greater than their fear of Fate”—likely not the wiser fear. As for the “pagan harpooneers,” they remained imperturbable; “if impressed, it was only with a certain magnetism shot into their congenial hearts from inflexible Ahab’s.” As for the tyrant himself, he proclaimed himself “lord of the level loadstone,” overawing “the superstitious sailors” by making a new compass and gesticulating mysteriously over it, as if commanding it to come to life. Having regretfully rejected the human home, the earth, the sands of Nantucket; having defiantly rejected the heavenly God, dashing the quadrant, Ahab claimed mastery over men by controlling power of navigation over the chaos-sea. “In his fiery eyes of scorn and triumph, you then saw Ahab in all his fatal pride.”

    The compass became the first of three new instruments Ahab commanded to be made. The second was a log-and-line. As the compass registers direction, the log-and-line registers the velocity of the ship: The line winds around a reel; a piece of wood, the “log,” is tied to the end of the line and is thrown overboard; sailors can then measure the speed at which the ship moves by the length of line pulled from the reel in a given segment of time. The old log-and-line had been damaged by long exposure to the elements; deployed, it snapped. The old Manxman remarked, “To me, the skewer seems loosening out of the middle of the world,” but Ahab simply commanded that a new device be made, having concluded from conversing with “the man from Man” that he had no wisdom to offer Ahab, that “the dead, blind wall butts all inquiring heads at last.” When Pip appeared, seeing in the loss of the “log” a picture of his own casting-away, the Manxman would dismiss him, but Ahab intervened and put him under his protection. To Ahab, deranged Pip fell from the “frozen heavens” and therefore “touchest my inmost centre.” Not the sagacious old man but Pip tells the true tale, the tale told by an idiot. “Lo! ye believers in gods all goodness, and in man all ill, lo you! see the omniscient gods oblivious of suffering man; and man, though idiotic, and knowing not what he does, yet full of the sweet things of love and gratitude. Come! I feel prouder leading thee by thy black hand, than though I grasped an Emperor’s!” The Manxman judged them “One daft with strength, the other daft with weakness”—true enough, but not comprehensive. Nor do recent scholars who find in this a stinging critique of American slavery quite see the point. The tyrant has his humanities, but they rule his conduct only when considering a soul that seems to him to mirror his own soul, with its own obsessions. Ahab made Pip his missing leg because Pip was crushed by unknowing, unspeaking ‘gods.’

    Steering the ship by the new compass and measuring its speed by the new log-and-line, Ahab set his course toward the equator, the surface-center of the world. At night the sailors heard a cry sounding “like the half-articulated wailings of the ghosts of all Herod’s murdered Innocents.” Only the Captain knew what it was: the cries of seals when the mothers lose their cubs. In the New Testament, Herod’s mass murder, a futile attempt to kill the infant Jesus, recalls Jeremiah’s story of Rachel, weeping for her exiled ‘children’—her descendants, to be banished to Babylon by God in punishment for their idolatry. As God promises to redeem the guilty Israelites from their exile, so will His Son redeem guilty humanity, which sins repeatedly against Him. The next gam will be a ship called the Rachel.

    The sailors, however, superstitiously took the seal-cries to signify the cries of lost, drowned sailors. Confirming their forebodings, the next day a man fell from the mast-head and drowned in the sea: “Thus the first man of the Pequod that mounted the mast to look out for the White Whale, on the White Whale’s own peculiar ground; that man was swallowed in the deep.” The sailors dropped the life-buoy for him, but it too, like the log-and-line, proved too weathered to work; it sank, following the man. Queequeg offered his coffin as a replacement. Starbuck fretted over the symbolism of substituting a coffin for a life-buoy; Flask considers the matter materially; Ahab turns again to the carpenter to re-shape the coffin for the new use.

    The carpenter again revealed himself as a Jesus according to Ahab, fashioning a means of salvation without knowing what he is doing. To Ahab’s accusation, “Thou art as unprincipled as the gods, and as much a jack-of-all-trades,” the carpenter can only reply, “But I do not mean anything, sir. I do as I do.” If the Creator-God of the Bible is what He is, willingly shall be what He shall be, the carpenter-god here only does, humbly but mindlessly and will-lessly. Against such a being, Ahab asserts personality—mind and will. “What things real are there, but imponderable thoughts?” “A life-buoy of a coffin!” The coffin, symbol of death, “by a mere hap, made the expressive sign of the help and hope of most endangered life.” Could this have “some spiritual sense” as “an immortality-preserver”? But as soon as Ahab promises himself to “think on that” he exercises his will to deny it. “So far gone am I in the dark side of earth, that its other side, the theoretic bright one, seems but uncertain twilight to me.” He turns not to Christ but to Pip: “We’ll talk this over; I do suck most wondrous philosophies from thee!” His dialogue will be not with Christ, nor even with Socrates, but with a supposed mirror of himself, self-willed agent of will-less alogos. 

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    • 1
    • 2
    • Next Page »