Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for May 2018

    What Is “The Promise of American Life”?

    May 5, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    This is a response to three papers presented at the Southwestern Political Science Convention, New Orleans, Louisiana, March 30, 2002.

    The papers were:
    Lee Ward: “Thomas Jefferson on Natural Rights and Empire.”
    J. David Alvis: “A Plan for Reform: Herbert Croly’s Critique of American Democracy.”
    Patrick J. Bernardo: “Ortega y Gasset on Rights and Self-Government.”

     

    The papers before us raise the question of the American regime in the twenty-first century, although none of them concerns a thinker of this century.

    The American Founders claim that popular self-government best secures our natural rights. Like Great Britain, America too will be an empire, but one of unprecedented character. This will be an empire of liberty, a place to which men and women will want to immigrate, and never again need to exercise their natural right of emigration. That is the original “promise of American life.”

    In so claiming and so promising, the Founders follow Locke in two ways. They are ‘individualists’ in the sense that life, liberty, and property are rights held by individuals. But almost to a man, and also following Locke, the Founders regarded human nature as social. Even in the state of nature, human beings live in families. This natural fact encompasses a moral fact. Jefferson, for example, calls “the natural sense of justice” or “sense of right and wrong” “as much a part of [our] nature” as the senses of hearing, seeing, feeling. Dismissing the spiritual claims of Jesus of Nazareth, Jefferson lauds his moral claims, which contradict the claims of the form of modern individualism stemming from Machiavelli, an individualism tout court which leaves no place for genuine sociality or morality, and therefore with no real place for natural rights.

    The natural sense of justice makes popular self-government possible; reason alone would never suffice to rule l’homme moyen sensuel. This natural sense cuts through the conventional claims of aristocrats and monarchs, enabling the people to see and feel their way to self-government.

    In addition, this new kind of empire can flourish because the principle of representation extends popular self-government across big places. As Jefferson writes, “No constitution was ever before so well-calculated as ours for extensive empire and self-government.” With such institutional backing, and with the kind of commercial ties commended by Hobbes, Locke, and Montesquieu, human sociality makes ‘friendship’ among self-governing regions possible; it makes a non-bureaucratic political whole possible, countering the centrifugal human passions sufficiently to allow reason to rule where it would otherwise be too weak.

    The natural rights of social animals must differ fundamentally from the natural rights of solitary animals. Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Rousseau all deny the sociality of human nature. The Founders depart from their fellow moderns in this. They reconcile individuality and sociality by first seeing that life, liberty, and property are always someones; there can be no life of a community without the lives of the individuals who compose it. Liberty and property, indispensable to life, similarly require individual fulfillment. However, the Founders also see that individuals must defend themselves together; this takes more than calculated contractarianism, although it does take that. The calculating contractarian rescues no one from burning buildings, nor does he give up his life for his friend—much less for his political friend, his fellow citizen, that intimate stranger.

    Whatever else they were, the Founders were hardly Croly’s naïve “pioneer democrats.” The Progressives offered a new promise of American life. Seeing the old one broken, injured by artificial persons called ‘corporations’—unnatural bodies—they turn not only from America’s constitutional foundation but from its natural-rights foundation. They turn instead to the subspecies of utilitarianism called ‘pragmatism’ (Croly) or to instantiated ‘idealism’ (Wilson), or to their unholy and unstable combination, dialectical materialism (Lenin). All these progressivisms endorse forms of the ‘leadership principle,’ a principle admitted by the Founders only in military affairs. Croly’s elevation of ‘History’ over natural right and his consequent replacement of statesmanship with leadership is really neither Hamiltonian nor Jeffersonian, with respect to ‘means’ or ‘ends.’ Eschewing an account of natural rights republicanism, Croly instead tells a story, a tale of American political and social development.

    But absent natural right, why are the economic and social inequalities the progressives deplore wrong? Why should democracy preserve itself, with or without expert ‘leaders’? Does Croly’s misconception of American liberty as “individual self-determination” not simply find a loud echo in the progressives own grander, collectivized triumphalism? Croly’s historicist vitalism, issuing in his call for “a continual process of internal reformation” —what Trotsky later and more forcefully calls permanent revolution—animates much of twentieth-century collectivism, but in this Croly speaks past the American Founders, not to them. As a historicist, he must.

    Croly replies to this ‘why’ question by saying that “the democratic scheme of moral values” is a “religion” of “loving-kindness” (albeit one with technical-administrative efficiency), preparing the American landscape for “the crowning work of some democratic Saint Francis.” “Democracy,” he contends, “cannot be disentangled from an aspiration toward human perfectibility.” Actually, the Founders had rather thoroughly disentangled their democratic republicanism from any such aspiration. Croly takes Jefferson’s Jesus and brings His millenarianism back, this time without a God to back it up. It is the failure of the progressivist promise in all its forms, its lack of sustainable religiosity and statist loving-kindness—the compassion of the cold monster—that brings us to Ortega’s version of the ‘last man.’

    Ortega cites Nietzsche, Hegel, and Comte, but not Tocqueville. Yet his problem is the Tocqueville problem. Democracy, a social condition of long gestation, has been born and it is growing. It releases immense energy, “a fabulous increase of vital possibilities,” strength not decadence. But so far it is rather too much like a college sophomore—long on potential, short on actualization. It doesn’t quite know what to do with itself. It’s all revved up with no place to go.

    Progressivism is not vital but fatal, Ortega argues, because at bottom it is fatalistic. “We are not launched into existence like shot from a gun.” Our potential can issue either in liberty or in the worst despotism, as Tocqueville foresaw and Ortega sees before his eyes. Our democrats begin to care only for anesthetics and motor-cars. With the new tyrannies, “there appears for the first time in Europe a type of man who does not want to give reasons or to be right, but simply shows himself resolved to impose his opinions,” under “the right not to be reasonable.” Genuine liberalism requires the nobility of the aristocrats that democracy inundates. “The great sin of those who directed the nineteenth century” was their “lack of recognition of their responsibilities”—their failure, I should say, to heed Tocqueville. Oddly, Ortega fails to see the threat to philosophy in all this, but he sees the threat to liberty clearly enough. “Modern technicism springs from the union of capitalism and experimental science,” and both capitalists and scientists are mass-men, ignorant of the whole, hermetic and self-satisfied individuals who do not understand the conditions of their own ways of life. Unlike Tocqueville, however, Ortega calls not for an inspiriting recognition of “the natural greatness of man” but for popular recognition of human limitedness.

    Unfortunately, like so many European writers, Ortega has only the weakest understanding of America, which he dismisses as “the paradise of the masses.” “America has not yet suffered; it is an illusion to think that it can possess the virtues of command.” Had Ortega never heard of the American Civil War, of Lincoln? He does see that the bourgeoisie can fight, which is the beginning of wisdom in such matters.

    On the theoretical level, we need an account of natural right understood as characteristic of a social and political animal. I say “natural” because Kant’s categorical imperative doesn’t work, being too deeply embedded in the Rousseauian wing of the Machiavellian fortress. Specifically, what does it mean to wed Lockean natural rights to sociality and not only to political institutions but to politics as a way of life?

    On the practical level, we need a constructive reply to Croly and his allies. The Progressives saw clearly that the American regime faced the challenges of ever-increasing scale and complexity. They failed to show that the American regime as designed by the Founders and amended in the wake of the Civil War could not meet those challenges, but no one has shown that it can, either. The mixture of the original design and the progressives’ design that prevails today has met with challenges from a position more radically to the ‘Left’ than anything the old progressives intended, and the result has been a hash.

    In 1650, Europe, having embarked on the nation-state system, the system of the Peace of Westphalia, could consider fundamental political-philosophic alternatives when understanding that system. One was that of Hobbes’s Leviathan, that vast blueprint for the modern state, home of the mass-man. The other was Grotius’ The Laws of War and Peace, which looks at exactly the same political phenomena through neo-Aristotelian eyes. Europe chose the systematic Machiavellianism of Leviathan. Americans may still have the other choice available to them, the choice of self-government. But we will need to start using the old political science of Aristotle and the new political science of the Founders and of Tocqueville if we are to make that choice in the real world, and keep ‘the promise of American life.’

     

     

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Benardete on the Odyssey

    May 4, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Seth Benardete: The Bow and the Lyre: A Platonic Reading of the Odyssey. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997.

    Originally published in Interpretation: A Journal of Political Philosophy. Winter 2001-2002, Volume 29, Number 2. Republished with permission.

     

    Philosophy asks questions of tradition, then spins traditions of its own. A ‘philosophic tradition’ must be some tradition that builds questions of itself, and of tradition generally, into itself. One such tradition interrogates the Odyssey, seeking philosophy in Homer’s poetry. Few modern philosophers have taken up this tradition, such philosophers having judged the learning needed to do so unnecessary to the philosophic quest as they conceive it. Seth Benardete has acquired that learning, and with it the strength to follow the tradition. He departs from modern philosophers, renewing an old voyage.

    His book, as the phrase goes, resists summary. But it encourages insight, and listing some insights Benardete offers may invite consideration of his argument. He recalls the acknowledged wisdom of poets and philosophers and asks readers to wonder if and how philosophic wisdom differs from poetic. Does the rational dialectic of argument differ fundamentally from the “poetic dialectic” of speech and action, or plot (xiii)?

    1. “Whereas the Iliad begins with the names of Achilles and his father,” the Odyssey begins with a man in whom anonymity is coupled with knowledge, a much-traveled man separated from “father and fatherland” (3). Odysseus defeats the Cyclopes by calling himself “No One,” and by using his mind, the least ‘rooted,’ the most anonymous human characteristic.

    In doing so, and yet also in so doing as part of a voyage back to his fatherland, back to his ‘roots,’ Odysseus radically alters the conditions of his rule of the fatherland, the rule he had won by revolution or “natural right” (4). Before his voyage, he ruled by natural right but had not used his mind to understand natural right. “[W]hat was originally an accidental coincidence of power and wisdom will have to be replaced by the conscious effort to put them together; but the terrible consequences of that effort” (the slaying of the suitors) “would seems to deny the desirability of their coincidence. Homer seems to have reflected on the Platonic possibility of philosopher-kings…” (4). The Olympian gods are the ones who overthrew their fathers, the cosmic gods, and Odysseus imitated them. Associated always with the Olympians (while his men remain pious, worshipping the Sun), Odysseus understands the world as nature not cosmos, understands political rule as founded upon natural right not paternity, and rules accordingly.

    Any monarchy must concern itself with succession. A natural right monarchy, one that sees mere paternity as inadequate, presents its ruler with a problem beyond the usual worry that the legitimate heir to the throne may prove a dunce. The people of Ithaca, are restless, understandably; the brothers and cousins of Penelope’s importunate suitors had been led to violent death by her husband the king. The Olympian gods of natural right instruct Odysseus on how to found a new regime in the “postheroic world” in which son Telemachus must live, an iron age ruled by Athena or mind (13). Telemachus consults Athena but imprudently “blurts out” her “private advice” in front of the suitors (14-15), a failure that puts his own natural right to rule into question. “The Odyssey is remarkable for the light touch with which Athena guides the course of events” (15); for the ancients there is no very tight connection between the rule of reason and the slaughterbench of ‘history’ (that is to say, there is no ‘history’ conceived as a dialectical course of events). This is so, even if Athena occasionally commends the use of the slaughterbench to rulers.

    2. In the Odyssey the person who most closely resembles a historicist is Nestor, who believes human events to be explicable in terms of “a strict theodicy” or moral tale in which everything that happens happens because wise and just gods cause it 919). Those slaughtered are rightly slaughtered; only the good survive. Nestor is no poet; his speeches lack both simile and dialogue. Simile and dialogue bring duality in, and with it moral ambiguity. Poetic dialectic yields no grand synthetic end and raises questions more insistently than it sets down answers. Poetry brings with it “a perspective beyond good and evil,” at least in any narrow or ‘moralizing’ sense of the phrase (21). The Nestorian account leads in the end not to piety but to the disappearance of the gods, who are relativized to certain places and time.

    Duality also inheres in the distinction between appearance and reality, a distinction that would bedevil the thinkers of the Enlightenment, who said they wanted to bring reality to the surface and make it publicly authoritative. But the harshness of reality would make its publicity a source of endless vengeance, or of despairing listlessness; political life, impossible without memory, is only possible if memory is limited by wise forgetfulness, as when Helen drug men, making them “forget their malignant thoughts and sorrows” (27). By selecting some memories and covering others, poetry in its doubleness acts like the drug mixed by the beautiful, Argus-eyed, transpolitical Helen. Founders must plan thoughtfully like gods and the best poets; they must also understand that the plans and even the planning, the work of the mind, also affect (at worst infect) the workings of the heart or spirit (thumos). “Helen seems to have all the traits of the poet, from the coolness with which Homer depicts the most terrible things to his mimetic capacity to make things appear in all their vividness and his insight into the hiddenness of things” (29). But Homer’s Odysseus excels even her; unlike her, he “seems never to have fallen under the spell of Aphrodite” and so exhibits a strong moral character. Why then does he choose mortality instead of godly immortality?

    3. Odysseus’ choice of mortality occurs during his stay with Calypso, a stay that the wise Athena (not Aphodite) arranges so that the natural softening of democratic resentments in Ithaca may take place, and King Odysseus’ potential successor, Telemachus, may mature—both in the course of nature, over time. In choosing mortality, Odysseus rejects the mindlessness of paradise, where “there seems to be no place for man” (35). It is a wise choice, especially given the suspicion that Calypso’s offer was empty, and Odysseus would have been killed, not deified, had he accept it (37).

    This non-choice points to the frustration of life, the anger of thwarted desires that cause minds to ‘double’ by ‘talking to themselves,’ or to the gods. ‘Odysseus’ may be a pun on odussamenos, the anger of someone against someone else. At the founding stage of his new regime, the natural-right rule of the angry but not mindless man will be terror (34). If the gods withdraw, human reliance on mind and force intensifies, but so do human self-opacity and the need for caution and questioning.

    4. After a long stay with Calypso, Odysseus has a short stay with the Phaeacians, who live in a sort of human paradise “without pain or suffering” (47). Having chosen the human, Odysseus will induce the Phaeacians to make the same choice. Odysseus is the humanist evangel. A human life, in its doubleness, longs for the reconciliation of legal right with natural right. This can be done, but only at the expense of eros (59), and therefore it cannot be done satisfactorily, once and for all.

    5. Centrally, Homer goes along with human duality by having Odysseus tell his own story, at the prompting of King Alcinous (“Brain”) of the Phaeacians. In telling his story, Odysseus’ “morally neutral curiosity” is on display, along with his considerable moral virtues. The two come together in Odysseus’ willingness “to run risks for knowledge” (69). Participating in the siege of Troy, an act of dubious justice, Odysseus wants to know more about the conflicting ways of men, and so voyages. “There are forms of the verb ‘to wander’ (alaomai) that are indistinguishable from ‘true’ (alethes)” (72). From the orderly but cannibalistic, insular, and doltish Cyclopes he learns that “law and order can be apart” (72). Odysseus outwits them, using the universal-anonymous mind, which at the crucial moment overmasters Odysseus’ anger. From his disastrous encounters with incestuous Aeolus and the cannibalistic Laestrygonians he begins to see the natural limitations of the rule of the mind, namely, the bodily and the democratic.

    These adventures and misadventures prepare him for the education he received from Hermes, “the peak of the Odyssey” (84). After committing his first act of justice that does not serve himself (embarking on the rescue of his men from Circe) Odysseus sees the revelation of Hermes, who not only tells him about, but shows him the nature of the moly, a plant which protects him against the witch’s spells. Knowledge of nature “lets Odysseus share in the knowledge of the gods without his having to share in their being” (85). “[T]he gods’ power arises from the knowledge” of the nature of things, especially of human beings. The human body is the true home of the human mind: This discovery reconciles the question of the rootless mind with the longing for home, for rootedness. The moly has both flower and root; it is two and it is one. “It now seems that Homer was the first, as far as we know, to have come to an understanding of this philosophic principle, to which he gave the name ‘nature.’ The experiences that had to precede its discovery are the measure of the difficulty of its discovery.” (87)  Odysseus’ odyssey represents the philosophic quest. The philosopher is both human, an embodied mind, and divine, insofar as the knows himself (as an embodied mind). The philosophic life suggests “a humanity that, though it belongs to man as man, is not open to every man, since what he is necessarily he is not necessarily unless he knows that that is what he is necessarily. Without that knowledge he can be enchanted and made subject to perfect rule.” (87)

    How then could a philosopher live (as he must, given human limitations) among fellow men who are not philosophic? Unphilosophic men “must have a version of the knowledge of what constitutes man” (88). That knowledge is the story of Hades, which teaches all men that soul and body are separable, and that mindlessness is to be feared. Hades is “a lawful equivalent of Odysseus’ knowledge of his nature” (88).

    Odysseus’ knowledge requires moral virtue before and after he receives it. Human being, anthopos, is intelligible and invisible; manliness and womanliness are visible, bodily, necessary. Odysseus must resist the temptation of Circe; “there is in man some capacity to resist, a strength of soul or whatever we choose to call it, that can be lost or diminished regardless of knowledge” (89). This thumotic virtue encompasses not only self-control but sympathy for other men, the unphilosophic ones; political life remains necessary for the philosopher, and that life includes a measure of piety. The suitors ignore the wisdom that begins with the fear of Hades, and this is the real reason why they must be so forcefully punished, for the good of both philosopher and city. Ithacans need to be re-minded. The philosopher, for his part, needs to learn that he can know, but not know all, that he can resist but not finally defeat evil, and that he can persuade, but only to a point. Self, gods, and other men “stand in his way” (100). He must in this sense “submit to his fate” (100).

    6. The limited freedom Odysseus enjoys may be seen in his lies. Upon returning home, he would rule, but ruling after the experience of philosophic noēsis differs from ruling before it. Odysseus will soon push off for another voyage, a second sailing. To leave his kingdom safely “in the hands of his son” (104), he must employ both force and fraud. Having employed them, getting out of town will be both the philosophic and the politic move to make. Force and fraud combine in the killing of the suitors, which is not merely a punishment but an exemplary punishment “designed to illustrate the principle, ‘Fear the gods and the future indignation of men'” (106). Liars, including poets, can philosophize and side with the gods.

    7. Once the gods “have completed their withdrawal” (120), eyewitnesses of divinity will give way to prophets who hear the divine choice. Such hearsay, at least in Telemachus, “seems to be nothing but his own thoughts” (117). The noetic experience will become more internalized in the twilight world, the iron age.

    The twilight of the gods and heroes also brings democracy. Telemachus will rule the future Ithaca, but will share power with Eumaeus and even a cowherd.

    As for Odysseus, his political character comes to dominate his philosophic character. Homer takes care to show “how closely anger can pose as reason” (126), distinguishing the bow from the lyre, and both from the liar. The anger built into Odysseus’ name comes to the surface in the end. Philosophy does not always ‘take,’ even after one experiences it. Philosophy is for the rarest natures; perhaps one should not suppose oneself a philosopher.

    8. Penelope’s weaving and unweaving of Laertes’ shroud enchants the suitors, distracting them from their most prudent political course, which would have been to form an oligarchy and ignore the woman. Responsible for the deaths of so many Ithacan men, Odysseus will kill most of the remaining ones who are spirited. The soft-spirited survivors will feel guilty, because one of Odysseus’ allies tells them that the gods favor Odysseus and punish them for failing to oppose the suitors through Odysseus. Guilt enables the gods to withdraw, to become invisible; guilt ‘works’ only with the base. All others must be killed, if they have rejected the gods. It might be noted that in coming generations, new spirited ones will arise. Regimes change, therefore, Men will need Homeric wisdom until there are no men.

    9. The Enlightenment wanted to substitute knowledge for belief. The final episodes of the Odyssey might seem to support that project. Odysseus stands revealed as himself at last, and he rules. The consignment of the souls of the heroic world to Hades also seems consonant with the Enlightenment, with whatever would be the ancient-world equivalent of embourgeoisement. The Enlightenment made much of recognition, and in this Hegel, the philosopher who wanted a political world animated by mutual recognition, is its culmination. The end of the Odyssey seems full of acts of recognition, and of the restoration of authority founded upon recognition.

    Benardete looks more closely, however. He sees that Odysseus grants Penelope little or no recognition for her sagacity, and indeed “from the first book on she is pushed aside in favor of the son she fostered and protected” (150). Odysseus teases his old father, who cannot seriously be expected to recognize his son after twenty year of wear and tear on both of them. In so doing, “Odysseus aims at two things at once, which he believes to be somehow connected: he wants Laertes to know him as he is, but he does not want Laertes to know him if he does not genuinely miss him. Only if his grief is real should he recognize the real Odysseus. These are competing demands unless the standard is doglike devotion; but no human being can be like Argus, and Laertes fails the test of loyalty with knowledge. Loyalty and knowledge are as far apart from one another as the unquestioned is from the result of questioning, or as Odysseus the homeward-bound is from Odysseus the wanderer. The entire Odyssey seems to have strained from the start to assert their togetherness in Odysseus, who first chose memory and then professed to represent the anonymity of mind.” (152)  Odysseus’ “destiny is to establish belief and not knowledge.” (152)  He is poetic-dialectical proof of the impossibility of political enlightenment, of straightforward anti-traditionalism. The rationalist dialectics of Hegel and Marx are taller tales than Homer’s. With a dialectic both rational and poetic, Benardete shows here that one may reject the dialectic of Enlightenment without falling into anti-philosophic obscurantism.

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    Wilson’s Doubleness: A Commentary on “WW”

    May 2, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Paper delivered at the meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco, California, September 1, 2001.

    Chaired by Ronald J. Pestritto of the University of Dallas, the panel was on John Alvis’s play, “WW”: A Play in Two Parts.

     

    Among the letters of our alphabet, “W” is uniquely dual. “WW” means duality times two. “WW” is “A Play in Two Acts,” a twice-told tale of a man with two wives, two friends, two main enemies, and two spiritual but not biological sons. We see one of his daughters twice, once in girlhood, once in womanhood. Wilson in a sense had two lives—the first as a political academic, the second as a professional politician. Like Hawthorne, John Alvis considers men and women between two worlds, the one Christian, the other not. All Christians live in two cities, Godly and human, and all Christians seek to be doubles, actors if you will, standing in for or imitating Christ. the Christ they imitate comes to light in that two-part book, the Bible, with characters in the first or “Old” Testament held to prefigure those in the second. The Bible’s “New” Testament describes a founding presented as a return to old ways. Although they all live in the two cities, not all Christians live in earthly cities in which the ways of God are giving way to some alien but equally systematic body of thought. Modern Christians experience a double duality—living not only in two cities, heavenly and earthly, but in an earthly city divided between what remains of Christendom and not-entirely coherent secularism This duality lends itself especially to drama as conceived in the West, a literary form with duality built into it: dialogue, conflict, parallel. Drama combines thought and action, imitating by bringing out or revealing certain dualities: cant or double-talk, duplicity or double-dealing (two-facedness), and betrayal or double-cross. Doubleness implies authority, the appeal from what is to what should be, the duplication or imitation of the good. (I mean “duplication” and “imitation” in two senses, good and bad, both the good imitation of the good–modeling oneself upon the good–and the bad or counterfeit imitation, a disguise put on to boost oneself into a position of authority.) Whether religious or political, any founding implies a drama or doubling of Old and New, and in “WW” Woodrow Wilson is seen attempting two foundings.

    I am delighted to report that John Alvis is a dramatist, and not just another professor with a hobby. Ezra Pound, his politics less sound than Mr. Alvis’s, did nonetheless write both fine poetry and intelligent literary criticism. He said that a poet must double, intensify, his insight and require the same of his readers by condensing his language—the technique of condensare. Poets should say in a line what lesser writers say in a paragraph, a chapter, even a book. As one who has read Wilson’s many pages of published prose, I can say that Alvis enacts this poetic virtue. His characters speak economically, quite unlike economists, to say nothing of lecturing political scientists and filibustering pols, which Wilson by turns was. Alvis packs lifetimes into his two-hour drama.

    Who is Alvis’s Wilson? The play’s prologue introduces some Wilsonian themes without bringing the man on stage. Oaths fly—oaths Christianly not scatalogically derived, connoting passions and loyalties, punctuating such other theological-political themes as executive authority, guild and responsibility, and the rule of women. This latter theme also brings nature in, by asking, ‘Who rules by nature?’ Much of organic nature is dual, engendering itself by means of gender.

    The first act concerns Wilson’s struggle to found Princeton College anew. The old Princeton served Christianity and America by educating Presbyterians. But God no longer works through the Church, Wilson has decided. God now works through the State. Providence is now History, and so Princeton must shift from educating Presbyterian ministers to educating prime ministers—states’ men, so to speak, men of the state. God once worked through spiritual fatherhood and motherhood, and the Christian college completed that education. The father sent his son to the old alma mater, mostly, in latter-day Princeton’s case, to get him into the right eating club (a fraternity by another name). In Wilson’s estimation, the fraternalism of the eating clubs substituted cliquishness for brotherliness. Wilson demanded that progress, movement toward the future, must replace the ancestral, the ambitions of fathers for their sons. And it shall, because progress is God’s work, and having God on our side apparently obviates the need for compromise with the declining ancestral order. At Princeton, Wilson practiced the high politics of centralization, attempting to destroy the old civil-social institutions and to reconstitute them so that students would not rule themselves in fraternities or imitate their fathers, but be ruled by administrators, faculty, and (God help them) graduate students. Princeton would remain (as it was from its first founding) “in the nation’s service.” But the nation, having changed into a modern nation-state, requires that the new Princeton imitate, become the double of, the nation-state itself as a centralized, tutelary authority.

    At Princeton, Alvis’s Wilson confuses human love and friendship, along with the kind of fidelity they beget, with a shared fidelity to ideals he posits, in the name of God. He overlooks his own emotional infidelity to wife and friend in his ambition to be a lover and friend while being also a founder/creator. He conceives fidelity to his ideal of meritocratic equality, in a regime ruled by unelected local authorities, to be true freedom, opposed to the false freedom of “privilege” and “cronyism”—what his enemies think to be the freedom to associate privately in order to form friendships and to learn without any immediate concern with serving the State. That is, Wilson wants others to be faithful to him by being faithful to ‘progress,’ to the cause they share, but, as a sort of lone founder of a miniature modern state, he cannot partake of the love and friendship that would engender such fidelity. So what? Machiavelli might ask Did Moses have friends? Did Caesar? But Wilson also wants the personality of the Christian God. Professor John Hibben, the friend who deserts his cause, is a Judas, he says. The real Jesus had at least eleven other friends, and they made the difference in the success of His founding. Wilson does not have eleven other friends.

    The Princeton of Wilson’s time remained a civil association, never quite achieving miniature-state status. Wilson failed to make it state-like, or a servant of any real state, and so turned to national and international politics, again as a founder-leader. In Act II, President Wilson, on his speaking tour during his fight for the League of Nations, regards the United States Senate rather as a Princeton eating club writ large, an entity that resists progress or History in the name of a sort of ancestral piety toward the work of the founding fathers—the Constitution, the invocation of which Wilson dismisses as a cloak for the senators’ will to power. Wilson and his new wife imagine that he draws strength from the people at large, that his tour will revive instead of exhausting him. The tour effectively kills him, because the spirit of the crowd may giveth power (or taketh it away) but it cannot give life; when the cheering stops—it must, as it is human, mortal—the democratic leader can only quit. The seduction of popularity, the confusion of vox populi with vox Dei, doubly confused by the ambition to become the leading voice, the prophet of the popular spirit, as a self-conceived servant of the State and instrument of God, leads the leader not to the Cross but back to the White House and to defeat at the hands of the Senate. Stricken with thrombosis, Wilson does not die but loses voice and executive capacity, his body rebelling against too much of the unlively spirit of crowd-swaying. Wilson’s “opinion leadership” is a sort of baptized Baconianism. But it cannot conquer nature. Nor is it clear that holy water turns the soul of Bacon around, or merely rolls off him like water off a duck. It looks as if holy water makes Bacon an idealist without making him a Christian, a point to which I shall recur.

    Wilson’s second-act friend, Colonel Edward House, tries to instruct him in a less confused Machiavellianism. Wilson wants the “New Freedom” for the nation and a new order for the world, both “unselfish” not “self-interested.” He fails to see what Franklin Roosevelt would see: that tangible freedom for the people within a modern state, and in a system of modern states, requires the rule of the executive eagle who can frighten the lesser birds of prey that roost in Senate committees and corporate boardrooms. This eagle will found and direct a bureaucratic state consolidated thanks to the opportunity a world war affords, securing itself by the act of securing the welfare of the sparrows which fear the nearer hawks more than the distant eagle. In Alvis’s epilogue, House steps forward to judge Wilson as Christian-all-too-Christian for such world-historical predation or empire-building. FDR, House says, was not too Christian for the task. Wilson became the John the Baptist in the progressive-American narrative, that reverse gospel which ends with a new Rome, not a new Heaven and a new earth—although some of its imperators are working on that project, too.

    Thus, by John Alvis’s reckoning, Woodrow Wilson was a man who never quite knew if he wanted martyrdom or victory. His modernized or neo-liberal Christianity impelled him to confuse the two. Victory was impossible for him, neglectful of lover of neighbor and of personal God, animated instead by such abstractions as idealism and power. And so was martyrdom, for the same reason. Most political men have no difficulty in choosing between martyrdom and victory. Their rallying cry, ‘Victory or death,’ means ‘We risk martyrdom, but we strive for conquest.’ Martyrdom as a choiceworthy way of dying, rather than as a harsh necessity, makes no sense to most political men. For them, ruling necessitates survival first of all. Martyrdom makes no sense to any but the most extraordinary political men, for whom it might make the regimes they founded immortal in human memory. Alvis has seen what Colonel House saw, that Wilson was not wholeheartedly a political man, even in the extraordinary sense of the victorious martyr. Early in the Great War, House called Wilson “too refined, too civilized, too intellectual, too cultivated not to see the incongruity and absurdity of war.” House said that a nation “needs a man of coarser fibre and one less a philosopher than the President, to conduct a brutal, vigorous, and successful war” (House papers, II. 463-465). House underestimated his friend, there. Wilson as we know did go on to conduct a successful war, did not lack leonine teeth. It was at peacemaking that he failed. To say that Wilson was to some degree a philosopher is not to say that he really was a philosopher. In the opinion of Alvis, and perhaps of House, Wilson did not really know himself, as a philosopher does. He lacked the self-examining duality of Socrates, and Socrates’ dialogic virtues. His classes at Princeton were lectures and, unlike Lincoln, his public ‘debates’ never involved another live person on the other side of the stage. His duality lacked the final degree of thoughtfulness, even as it gestured at rationality. The Wilson I find in his arguments and actions is perhaps even more sharply dual than Alvis’s, both more Machiavellian and more profoundly Christian—even more sharply ambivalent.

    Wilson made himself hard to know. “Opinion leadership” is not transparent; publicity for Wilson often consisted of hiding in plain sight. In 1896 he published a respectful essay on Grover Cleveland, the only Democrat elected to the White House in Wilson’s adult lifetime except himself. He had to profess respect for Cleveland, and he did. He called Cleveland “the sort of President the makers of the Constitution had vaguely in mind,” a man of “robust sagacity,” a practical man, no mere theorist, a “President in ordinary times but after an extraordinary fashion,” a “man without a party” who “carried civil service reform to its completion at last.” This all seems quite stirring, until one reflects on Wilson’s other writings of the period. There he says that partisanship is indispensable to political life, the foundation of leadership (a party being a sort of peaceful army, always in need of a general). Leaders need vision more than prudence, in order to inspire their fellow citizens to advance. The sort of man the Framers wanted, the president who governs rather than leads, is not the sort of man Woodrow Wilson wanted, or the sort of president he became. So Wilson made it hard for others to know him, a lion in lamb’s clothing, a fox posing as the loyal family dog.

    We are looking, then, at a doubly elusive man, concealing himself from others while concealing himself from himself. No wonder that at least two intelligent women, one of them also wise, found him a fascinating, if vexing, companion. The perfect study for a dramatist.

    John Alvis’s Wilson conceals his Machiavellianism from himself by believing himself a Christian—a Christian who never quite gets to church on Sunday, or prays, but seems not to notice that he does not. “I think we fight on behalf of the Prince of Peace,” he tells his daughter, old enough to raise an eyebrow. “It has become my cross and my privilege, unworthy vessel of Providence that I am.” This spiritual warfare for peace, undertaken necessarily by military means and by political activity conceived militarily, as leadership rather than statesmanship, crowds out worship—and with it, humility—precisely while its practitioner calls himself an unworthy vessel.

    I think Wilson’s dilemma may have had less moral and more doctrinal content than we easily understand. In taking Wilson’s Christianity seriously, I distance myself from most political scientists and side with the general run of historians, who tend to take Wilson’s religiosity more on ‘face value.’ Wilson gave lay sermons to churches and to church-affiliated groups even as president of the United States—no Jeffersonian “wall of separation” for him. Of our major presidents, he is the only one, with the exception of Reagan, likely to answer with an honest ‘yes’ to the old sermon chestnut, ‘If you were accused of Christianity, would you be convicted?’ Wilson tried to think through his simultaneous commitments to Christianity, progressivism, and political life.

    A few months before publishing his double-edged tribute to President Cleveland, Wilson spoke to the Philadelphia Society. He gave his talk what is to our ears the odd and rather funny title, “The Expulsive Power of a New Affection.” [1] The original text is lost; we have only a newspaper summary. He discusses many of the same themes in his most celebrated early speech, “Princeton in the Nation’s Service,” delivered in the fall semester of the same year.

    In Philadelphia, Wilson said that “if we wish to get a bad thing out of our soul, we must get a good thing in.” The “good thing” is the “new affection”; only it, and not self-censorship or moderation, has “expulsive power,” the power to purge the soul of evil. “Such a power must be aggressive in its nature,” he said. “There is… great danger in the inoccupancy of the soul, danger that in such a condition small evils may creep in and displace the good.” This closely resembles the Christianity of the Gospels. One turns to the Gospel writers from the ancients struck by the degree to which early Christians regarded the soul as a vulnerable, even weak, entity–almost a passive battleground for good and evil spiritual beings who seek to claim it for themselves. The virtues that seem so sturdy in Cicero seem rather flimsy to Matthew, Mark, Luke, and John. Wilson here acknowledges the Christian stance, although for him the warring armies on the field are forces—virtues and vices—rather than persons–angels and demons. Also, for Wilson the power of a new affection suffices actually to expel sin, not merely to keep it at bay.

    Wilson also endorses the Gospel shield in this warfare: agapic love, the love of God and neighbor, “the one thing that can replace… the very evils of the soul.” To “allow” such love “to fill our whole life and soul” is “not only our duty but our privilege.” Again, this is a ‘liberal’ and ‘abstract’ reading of Christianity, one that emphasizes the virtue of agape rather than the agapic infilling of the soul by that person, the Holy Spirit. It is, if you will, a rather spirited spirituality, very much a Scotsman’s creed. The supreme stubbornness of Wilson, his inclination to sublimate his sins or vices by intensifying his efforts toward some other, better goal (a goal itself saturated by his own spiritedness or ambition), is filtered through and refined by this political theology. Notice how close this progressive Presbyterianism is to the austere willfulness, the discipline commended by the founders of the modern scientific project—Descartes, Bacon.

    Wilson effectually acknowledges this spirited spirituality in his Princeton speech. In those days, Princetonians took their Presbyterianism seriously, or at least said they did. Wilson said so, too: “Your thorough Presbyterian is not subject to the ordinary laws of life,—is of too stubborn a fibre, too unrelaxing a purpose, to suffer mere inconvenience to bring defeat. Difficulty bred effort, rather….” [2]Here is the Wilson who would not compromise, either with his enemies at the college or, later, in Washington. Spirit natural and Christian amalgamate here. Only God could separate and weigh these elements in Wilson.

    Wilson goes on to name three founders, all of whom he would rival. The first is John Witherspoon, the only clergyman to sign the Declaration of Independence, “a man,” Wilson says, “so compounded of statesman and scholar, Calvinist, Scotsman, and orator that it must be a sore puzzle where to place or rank him,—whether among the great divines, the great teachers, or great statesmen.” The Princeton of Wilson’s Witherspoon, Presbyterian and political, a pivot of the Revolutionary War and a school for statesmen, has continued into the 1890s. Wilson’s envisioned new founding at Princeton along lines of English, Christian, and modern ideas, dramatized by Alvis, makes him praise Witherspoon even as he intends to replace him.

    “A commencement day came,” Wilson reminds his audience, “which saw both Washington and Witherspoon on the platform together—the two men, it was said, who could not be matched for striking presence in all the country.” [3] Washington is Wilson’s second founder in this speech. As Alvis and all of us recall, in his own utterly in-Washingtonian way, Wilson too would see, when circumstances allowed him the chance, to be first in war, first in peace, and first in the hearts of his countrymen. But he so sought in part by ending Washington’s foreign policy of American seclusion from permanent political ties with Europe.

    The last founder Wilson names is James Madison, whom he styles “the philosophical statesman.” Madison numbered among the “nine Princeton men [who] sat in the Constitutional Convention of 1787,” six of them former students of Witherspoon. “Princeton men,” Wilson tells his Princeton men, “fathered both the Virginia Plan which was adopted, and the New Jersey Plan which was rejected,” as well as “the compromises without which no plan could have won acceptance.” By Wilson’s reckoning, Princeton men just had the market cornered when it came to constitution-building. And, Wilson suggests, they’re not done, yet. True, “the revolutionary days are gone,” and generations have since entered “a list of the silent men who carry the honorable burdens of business and of social obligation.” Nevertheless: These same silent men “suggest a fertile soil full of the old seed and ready, should the air of the time move shrewdly upon it as in the old days, to spring once more into the old harvest.” [4] A new American founding might occur, and if you wonder how a new founding might come from old dormant seed, shrewd Wilson assures you that “the law of conservation is really the law of progress.” [5]

    Princeton Presbyterianism lends itself both to unrevolutionary and revolutionary politics. “Religion, conceive it but liberally enough, is the true salt wherewith to keep both duty and learning sweet against the taint of time and change; and it is a noble thing to have conceived it thus liberally, as Princeton’s founders did…. The men who founded Princeton were pastors, not ecclesiastics. Their ideal was the service of congregations and communities, not the service of a church. Duty with them was a practical thing, concerned with righteousness in this world, as well as with salvation in the next. There is nothing that gives such pith to public service as religion. A God of truth is no mean prompter of the enlightened service of mankind; and formed, as if in his eye, has always a fibre and sanction such as you shall not easily obtain for the ordinary man from the mild promptings of philosophy.” [6] Washington had said as much is his Farewell Address, but without Wilson’s critique of traditional liberal education or the American Constitution. Wilson has invoked what to his audience was the familiar model of the Presbyterian ‘secular saint,’ now envisioned as a carrier into society not only of the Holy Spirit but the Spirit of the Age valorized by Hegel.

    Turning to Wilson’s critique of traditional liberal education, consider with President Wilson the mild promptings of philosophy. Wilson makes one of the most eloquent defenses of liberal education, classically conceived, that any ‘modern’ has written. But in the end the old liberal education, and the old liberalism of the Founders, are like Grover Cleveland: admirable but superannuated. “Your enlightenment depends on the company you keep,” he says. “There is no sanity comparable with that which is schooled in the thoughts that will keep.” Now here’s the gambit: thoughts that have kept, literature that has survived, hold “a sort of leadership in the aristocracy of natural selection.” [7] Wilson uses reverence for old things to ‘bring in’ the themes of leadership and progress.

    The classics give us “the thinking which depends upon no time but only upon human nature”–no apparent progressivism, there. Yet Wilson also gives this claim one of his characteristic twists. First, those who only read the classics may neglect their “practical duties in the present,” spurning politics for “the peculiarly pleasant and beguiling comradeship” of “authors.” [8] Undergraduate education cannot and should not produce scholars but rather men of affairs who are friends of scholars and of authors, those potential revolutionaries of a new America.

    Second, Wilson deploys literary education against a scientific education that holds out a false progressivism, rival to his own. “Science has bred in us a spirit of experiment and a contempt for the past.” It is materialist. “It has,” he says, “given us agnosticism in the realm of philosophy” and “scientific anarchism in the field of politics” by making “the legislator confident that he can create and the philosopher sure that God cannot.” Science’s conquest of nature “has not freed us from ourselves,” has not “purged us of passion or disposed us to virtue”; instead it “may be suspected of having enhanced our passions by making wealth so quick to come, and so fickle to stay.” Progressivism based on materialism does not work. It does not engage the whole human soul. Only the purgative or “expulsive” and progressive Christianity of Presbyterian Princeton can lead Americans to the new republic of which Woodrow Wilson will serve as the Witherspoonian spiritual-political educator, the Washingtonian executive, and the Madisonian legislator, all in one. If that Wilson bears an unsettling resemblance to the Trinitarian God of the Gospels, and also to Jefferson’s definition of the tyrant, then the question we must ask, with John Alvis, is: How do you know when the chosen vessel of that god, guiding the course of human events, leading his militant party and sect forward, charges into an unholy megalomania? The answer must be that God’s true vessel will be chosen for his humility–as Abraham was. Alvis thinks that Wilson misconceived of himself as that vessel. I am inclined to agree, adding only that Wilson did see these dangers, and tried to avoid them by conceiving a neo-liberal, democratic-progressive, Protestant answer to the theological-political problem of progress and return.

    Filed Under: American Politics

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • 5
    • Next Page »