Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for February 2018

    Shklar on American Citizenship: A Dialogue with the Declaration

    February 22, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Judith N. Shklar: American Citizenship: The Quest for Inclusion. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991.

     

    Early modern political philosophers often avail themselves of ‘natural-rights’ theories, in part to counter ‘divine-right’ theories. Divine right was associated with two serious problems: despotism, Catholic and Protestant; bitter religious warfare, civil and international. With modern natural rights theories in hand, along with republican institutional proposals, philosophers such as Locke and Montesquieu sought to tame uncompromising passions and to channel human energies into the peaceful bays of commerce and civility.

    This ’embourgeoisement’ of the world succeeded all too well, in the estimation of some later moderns. From the ‘Left’ came Rousseau’s strictures against this demi-citizen, demi-man, the bourgeois; from the ‘Right’ came Burke’s fulminations against sophisters, bankers, and atheists. A rich variety of Germans—Idealists, Hegelians, Marxists, Nietzscheans—sought to revive the spirited or ‘thumotic’ passions in modern man, much as, centuries earlier, Machiavelli had sought to re-masculinize a world made ‘effeminate’ by Christianity.

    The American Founding displays a fascinating mixture of ‘bourgeois’ and ‘thumotic’ elements. This is modern natural right, all right: equality defined as the unalienable rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness reminds one decidedly of Locke, as do many other phrases in the Declaration of Independence. However, the Declaration’s peroration invokes spiritedness, as the Signers mutually pledge to each other their lives, fortunes, and “sacred honor.” That has an aristocratic ring, not a bourgeois clatter. In its subsequent history, the regime the Founders founded has often deceived its more thumotic enemies—the war-horses of the Confederacy, the fascists and communists of the next century—who supposed that no commercial republic would stand and fight. This bourgeois regime cultivates some unbourgeois passions on the side, and did so, at least in its first century without the aid of the ‘Germans,’ and their thumotic critique of natural right.

    Judith N. Shklar’s succinct and graceful essay well captures this dual character of American citizenship, although at the price of apparent theoretical confusion. [1] She explains American citizenship by turns in Hegelian and natural-rights terms, that is, in terms that are theoretically opposed. A Hegelian will explain citizenship as the outcome of a historical dialectic seen in the master-slave relationship; a natural-rights thinker will explain citizenship in terms of consent and contract founded on certain natural principles—i.e., principles discovered by unaided human reason, not by divine grace or by some illumination or ‘consciousness-raising’ experience issuing from concrete historical situations unavailable to previous thinkers.

    To say this is not to claim that theoretical difficulties necessarily play out directly in practice. A theoretical error may not make a bad citizen. In fact, it better not: we all make so many of them. Publius’ argument in the tenth Federalist shows that even persons intent on being bad citizens can be governed with the help of well-designed institutions. Surely such a regime can survive well-intentioned mistakes of an ‘academic’ sort, as well. As in religion, so in theory, it often matters not if my neighbor believes in one god or twenty, so long as he neither picks my pocket nor breaks my leg. It is true that mistakes in political theory may result in practical catastrophe—as when John C. Calhoun asserts that the phrase “all men are created equal” is “a self-evident lie”—because while one may ‘bracket’ religion from politics it is hard to bracket a theory about politics from politics. But not all such errors are damaging.

    Further, I am not at all sure that Shklar is mistaken. The theoretical contradiction or tension in her essay may be more apparent than real. She may deliberately set it in place. I shall leave the possibility open. In order to highlight both the tension and the question of its deliberateness, I shall pay some attention to the way Shklar unfolds her argument. Her essay seems to me very carefully crafted, deserving every benefit of the doubt when it comes to apparent contradictions.

     

    Shklar on Natural Right

    Slightly more than one-third of the way through her essay on American citizenship, Shklar for the first time explicitly mention the natural-rights foundation of American republicanism, enunciated in the Declaration of Independence. [1] Her earlier references to “the promise of equal political right contained in the Declaration of Independence” (13) to “an unacknowledged ideology of equal political rights” (28) are ambiguous and somewhat misleading. The Declaration does not mention equal political rights at all, much less promise them.

    The only promise made in the Declaration occurs in the final paragraph. The representatives of the United States “pledge to each other”—not to the people they represent or to the “candid World” they address in the name of the people—”our Lives, our Fortunes, and our sacred Honor” for “the support of this Declaration.” This is not an egalitarian promise. Although “lives” and “fortunes” have an egalitarian sound—everyone has one of each—as noted above “sacred Honor” has a decidedly thumotic/spirited, even aristocratic ring. While Hegel may be right to think that everyone seeks ‘recognition,’ it is not to be supposed that every person holds honor sacred.

    The Signers of the Declaration never conjoin the terms “equal” and “equality” with “political.” “Political” first comes to sight in the first sentence: “political bands… have connected” one people with another, Americans with English. It is in dissolving these bands that Americans assume “the separate and equal station to which the Laws of Nature and of Nature’s God entitle them,” among the “Powers of the earth.” Equality exists by nature and by God, not necessarily by politics. Natural right and political arrangements are distinguishable.

    The lapidary sentences immediately following reaffirm this. All men are created equal, that is, they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights. People constitute governments, engage in foundational political activity, in order to secure these unalienable or natural rights; unalienable rights are natural, and precisely because they exist not by grace of consent, assent, or politicking of any kind. Governments derive their just powers, those that secure natural rights, by consent. This can only mean that consent is not mere assent, but rather agreement consistent with unalienable rights—rational agreement, agreement that takes cognizance of the self-evident. [2]  To give an example from everyday life, if some fellow in a bar approaches a woman of republican virtue with the proposition, ‘I want to be your love-slave,’ she is entitled to remind him that his desire is inconsistent with rational or consensual behavior rightly understood. Consenting adults—at least in the chaste and sober language of the Declaration—do not attempt to contradict their very natures by attempting to alienate the unalienable. Such attempt are either slavish or tyrannical, minor or major variant of King George III and his “design to reduce [the People] under absolute Despotism.” Equal political or civil rights may or may not conduce to the security of equal natural or unalienable rights. The former must always be tested in the light of the latter, not confused with them. Such confusion (as in the contemporary phrase, ‘human rights’) may weaken the standard by making it contingent on consent or even mere assent.

    Shklar’s initial imprecise phrasing directly bears on an important point concerning the structure of government, particularly republican government. Several of the charges on which the Americans indict their king (and, sotto voce, their parliament) refer to government by law and representative government: e.g., the attempt to get Americans to “relinquish the right of Representation in the Legislature”; the calling together of legislative bodies “at places unusual, uncomfortable, and distant from the depository of their Public Records”; the repeated dissolving of colonial legislature and foot-dragging on permitting their reelection; and, most famously, “imposing taxes on us without our Consent.” No taxation without direct (rather than ‘virtual’ representation)—indeed, representation itself—is not on the face of it a matter of equal political right. Representation requires the (usually temporary) elevation of certain citizens above others, in order to constitute a government. Representation does not necessarily proceed according to the principle, ‘one person, one vote,’ or even ‘one citizen, one vote.’ Even direct representation can be decidedly inegalitarian. Further, as an instrument of government, representation partakes of the inegalitarianism of all government, which involves telling people what to do. As Publius writes, “In administering a government which is to be administered by men over men, the great difficulty lies in this: you must first enable the government to control the governed; and in the next place oblige it to control itself” (The Federalist, No. 51). Republican or representative government is still government, even if government of, by, and for the people. Lincoln’s formulation is a touch vague with respect to which among the people will be doing the actual governing at any given time, although his actions as president, particularly as Commander in Chief, were anything but vague with respect to the perennial political question, ‘Who’s in charge, here?’ The Signers of the Declaration and the Framers of the Constitution are not at all vague on this point. Both documents clearly identify the governing actor: the Congress versus king and parliament in one instance, and the several branches of government in the other. Once you step out of the ‘state of nature,’ you’ve left behind the situation in which no one has the right to tell you what to do. It will be a rare, indeed hitherto uninvented, political constitution that somehow arranges for thoroughgoing political equality.

    Shklar emphatically rights her careless phrasing, as noted above, and additionally makes a sound observation on the relation of natural rights theory to republican practice. “No historically significant form of government or of citizenship is in principle incompatible with the exclusion of large groups of people, but natural-rights theory makes it very difficult to find good reasons for excluding anyone from full citizenship in a modern regime” (37). She cautions that “only after long and painful struggles, the inherent logic of American representative democracy, based on political equality, did prevail” (38). It is important to see that by “political equality” she means, first and foremost, voting rights, which are civil and not natural rights, but are civil rights designed to secure natural rights. It is moreover eminently arguable that equal voting rights are extremely useful political security for equal natural rights. But not all equal political right are necessarily so conducive, as the tenth Federalist argues, with its well-known strictures on “pure democracy.”

    In this matter Shklar echoes Abraham Lincoln. In the words of his friend and law partner, William Herndon, “Again he said and said often… that, though the Declaration of Independence at that time, 1858, was not just yet a practiced fact here in all circumstances, and yet that it was a grand truth set up as a standard, an ideal standard, it may be, but to be ever worked for, struggled for, and approached….” [3]  According to Herndon, Lincoln was thinking of slavery and its eventual abolition, which also serves as the centerpiece of Shklar’s essay, even more than the civil condition of women, manual workers, and foreign nationals. It is to Shklar’s rhetorical approach that I now turn, picking up her argument from the beginning.

    Slavery, the Acid Test

    Shklar considers a habitual but nonetheless pertinent complaint against the American Founders—that these apostles of natural equality tolerated slavery and a considerable degree of civic exclusion of persons not enslaved. She shows how and why that is and is not a just criticism. In her introduction she points to sociology, history, and law, not to natural right. In one sense this is appropriate and necessary: If natural right is distinct from civil right, then citizenship belongs in the realm not of nature but of “human events” (to use the Declaration’s phrase) and human consent. To be born within a given territory may or may not confer citizenship; obviously, this natural event acquires civil right or privilege only through human legislation. Slaves are born, but they are not born civilly free. Similarly, the right to keep the fruits of one’s labors, a natural right, may or may not enjoy civil protection. Shklar’s rhetoric proceeds effectively by citing, if not stirring, the thumotic or spirited passions; she speaks initially not of natural right but of “civic dignity” (3), the demand for respect—what Charles Taylor, following Hegel, calls “recognition.” Indeed, even her emphasis on “the promise of equal political rights” evokes the thumotic, as anyone who has witnessed the moral indignation of a child (‘But, you promised!) will attest. Consistent with her ‘thumotizing’ strategy, Shklar emphasizes social standing among the four meanings of citizenship (social standing, nationality/membership, participation, and “ideal republican citizenship” (3). She goes so far as to agree unqualifiedly with Aristotle that a change of regime changes you as a citizen without changing your nature, at least your physical nature; the same person could live through the Third, Fourth, and Fifth French republics, as well as the Vichy regime, with no physical change beyond the wear and tear of years (8). This claim overlooks the problem that a Jewish citizen of the Third Republic might not physically survive into the Fourth; regime changes can kill you. Thus in her introduction Shkalr abstracts from or downplays the natural consequences of politics. By so ‘abstracting,’ she wants to avoid another sort of abstraction the theoretical abstraction from the ‘historical,’ that is, from economic, social, and political conditions (see p. 9). American citizenship has changed since 1787, at least in the sense that a far wider portion of the population enjoys citizenship rights. Shklar wants to show how this happened, but she does not make her position clear at the beginning. It is not at first clear whether she means to argue that “democratic ideology”—which can exclude from citizenship as well as include—is somehow at tension with itself, that the Founders’ principles were therefore inadequate, or whether she simply means that there was a mismatch between theory and practice, that “a profoundly democratic society… was actively and purposely false to its own vaunted principles” (14).

    Her first glance at this question is not encouraging. She claims that “the value of citizenship was derived primarily from its denial to slaves, to some white men, and to all women” (16, emphasis added). The most authoritative statement on the value of citizenship, the Declaration of Independence, disproves this. The value of citizenship was primarily derived from the assertion of self-evident natural rights, and secondarily from the denial of those rights by means of seriously compromising the civil rights of the American people as a whole, among whose numbers the freeborn white men who signed the Declaration were conspicuous examples. The Declaration makes no mention of slavery; as is well known, Jefferson wanted to charge the king with imposing the institution of chattel slavery on the colonies, but even his proposed language did not compare the conditions of slaves to the condition of subjects. This is not to deny that such comparisons were made—George Washington made one [4]—but it is to deny that the ‘negative’ derivation was primary.

    “What gave citizenship as [social] standing its historical significance is not that it was denied for so long to so many, but that this exclusion occurred in a republic that was so overtly committed to political equality”—not exactly so, as discussed above—”and whose citizens believed that theirs was a free and fair society” (17)—again not so, else Lincoln would not have won the presidency, nor would anti-slavery arguments have gained sympathetic hearing from the beginning, as seen in the writings of Washington, Jefferson, and other prominent members of the founding generation. Nor would arguments for voting rights for manual workers, women, and freemen have obtained any purchase in the nineteenth century, had Americans who enjoyed full citizenship believed that theirs was a free and fair society, simply. Nor would slave manumission have occurred throughout the northern states. These objections notwithstanding, Shklar’s rhetorical approach has the great merit of bringing early Americans into the reader’s imagination as real men and women in real circumstances: “The word slavery used to express fears of oppression in a country where slaves were constantly before one’s eyes or at least are a living presence has a different meaning from its use as merely a figure of speech” (22-23)—as in the writings of many English Whigs.

    Self-Government, Political and Economic

    After the introduction, Shklar divides the remainder of the essay into two sections, “Voting” and “Earning.” That is, she discusses citizenship in the modern commercial republic first in accordance with its republicanism, then in accordance with its commercialism. (If you prefer ‘liberal democracy’ to ‘commercial republicanism,’ she may be said to discuss citizenship first in terms of democracy, then in terms of liberalism—the latter first in the older and then in the newer sense of the word.) She continues her ‘historicizing’ strategy at the beginning of “Voting,” where she claims that Americans fought hard to get the right to vote and then often failed to exercise that right because citizenship was a matter of social standing defined negatively as ‘I-am-not-a-slave.’ Once won, voting rights are not seen primarily as a positive means of asserting rights, she argues; consequently, the right often rests in peace, unexercised. This explanation depends upon her not-quite-just dismissal of Aristotelian citizenship (ruling and being ruled) as “citizenship for members of a master class” (29) or “participatory aristocracy” (30). In fact, Aristotle advocates the expansion of the middle class as ballast for the typical ancient regime of many poor and few rich. Her dismissal of citizenship as ruling and being ruled is also not quite just to the Americans. With her equation (following the formulation of a North Carolina judge) of U. S. citizenship law and English common law (33-34), she misses the interplay between representative government and popular sovereignty—the American equivalent of ruling and being ruled. As James Monroe, following Madison, discusses at length in his book The People the Sovereigns, the American regime is not constructed along any (ancient) Greek, Roman, or (modern) English or Dutch model. Only the people, not the government, are sovereign, constrained only by natural right—i.e., by their own nature, as distinct from their passions-of-the-moment. The people are self-governing, in the sense that they are sovereign. they rule directly when they vote, serve on juries, run a business or organize a labor union. They are in turn governed by their law-making, law-enforcing, law-applying representatives, who come from them and must abide by the same laws they, as governors, make, enforce, and interpret. If the people are sovereign, ultimately limited in their action only by natural right, and if human beings are free to act against natural right, this means that majority tyranny is a serious possibility, as the Founders, Lincoln, and Tocqueville all recognized. These statesmen also agreed on the basic features of the solution to this potential problem: republican institutions that work to slow down popular passions, refining and enlarging the public views; a complex civil society providing ‘mediating institutions’ between the individual citizens and the government; a virtuous citizenry. (This last item is prominent in the much-misrepresented Madison, whose ‘institutionalism’ is intended as an —auxiliary precaution. [5]  The Americans may be said to use non-Aristotelian means to achieve at least one Aristotelian end: moderation. They need such means because their circumstance differs from Aristotle’s. They live in a modern state, not an ancient polis.

    It is now—not a moment too soon—that Shklar corrects her course and cites the American regime’s natural right foundations. She proceeds through a good account of voting rights as civil protectors of natural rights, although she occasionally slips and confuses the two. (For example, “It is only citizenship perceived as a natural right that bears a promise of equal political standing in a democracy” (57). Not exactly: it is the equal political standing in terms of voting rights that mightily helps to secure the natural rights that citizenship, membership in a civic order, is intended to secure.) Perhaps the polemical highlight of her account is her criticism of nineteenth-century feminists for abandoning natural rights arguments in favor of such “notably undemocratic paths to progress” as Social Darwinism, health and hygiene-oriented reform, and the Social Gospel (60-61). This “evolutionary historicism” (88), ‘Left’ or ‘Right,’ typically requires a revolutionary or at least evolutionary vanguard, supremely ambitious personalities who do not merely refine and enlarge the public views but redefine and transform them. Such individuals have tended to appeal not to prudential reason (how can we best secure natural rights?) but to the thumotic passions that the American constitution is designed to moderate.

    In “Earning,” Shklar describes the way independent work has embodied a (tamed) spiritedness. This account, with its sharp refutation of Weber (91), deserves praise, although it should be noted that the Jacksonians were only elaborating the labor theory of value propounded much earlier by John Locke. [6]  She must mean that the work ethic was “forged” in practice in Jacksonian America (65). She also errs (again because she is thinking in sociological terms) in claiming that the economic portion of the public sphere, unlike the political portion, is “entirely unequal” (64). This is not even exactly true in terms of income levels; about two-thirds of American families fall into the ‘middle class’ range of household incomes, although the increases at the lower and upper ends of the income scale in the past fifty years are significant—especially the increases at the upper end. On the legal as distinguished from the socioeconomic level, the natural right to keep what you earn is in fact equally protected by civil laws, except of course that the incomes of the wealthy are taxed (with representation) at rates higher than others. (Lest one shed an idle tear for the wealthy, it may be noted that they also enjoy more exemptions and better accountants; more pertinently, they also enjoy more money at the end of the day.) This means that, overall, the American intention to break with European society, “for centuries separated into three orders: those who pray, those who fight, and those who labor” (69), has been largely successful in practice and in theory. America is successfully bourgeois. As always, practice doesn’t measure up to theory, but if Americans don’t always enjoy the economic independence of the Jeffersonian yeoman, they often act as if they do. Shklar’s proposed “right to work” not as a “primary human right” but as a civil right “derived from the requirements of local citizenship” (100)—defended on the grounds that one must earn in order to be a full citizen in terms of social standing—is an important attempt to re-yeomanize contemporary workers to the greatest extent possible. Like any such proposal, this one will be subject to the exigencies of politics, inasmuch as civil rights are alienable, tradeable, compromisable, and generally subject (as the Declaration states) to prudence, to be deliberated on by legislators, executives, judges, and other citizens.

    The Ambiguity of Modern Liberal Theory

    On the level of ‘pure’ political theory, modern liberalism often involves not-quite-plausible attempts to reconstruct natural right or, rather, to gain the benefits of natural right without actually endorsing it. These attempts often amount to elaborations of the Kantian project, exemplified recently in the writings of John Rawls. Rawls’s “original position” argument, which assumes that no one operating behind the “veil of ignorance” will have the guts to roll the dice and say, ‘Give me tyranny or give me slavery, because to my soul equality is worst of all,’ requires a rational will with no rational object or subject (older writers would say ‘soul,), and hence leaves itself vulnerable to Allan Bloom’s joke, that Rawls has given us a first philosophy for the Last Man. Shklar, no less liberal than Rawls, proceeds more concretely and probably more wisely, calling attention to the real conditions of citizenship and to the natural rights to be secured by citizens for themselves and for one another.

    The difficulties with proceeding as Shklar does—perhaps for reasonable rhetorical purposes—have been canvassed. In sum, they involve a failure to recognize the subtlety of the interplay between theory and practice. Specifically, Shklar does not clearly account for the way in which practical reasoning or prudence must guard the discovery of theoretical reasoning, natural right. The Declaration states this matter explicitly and The Federalist shows the operation of prudential reasoning for that purpose on every page. Shklar often seems to assume that equal natural rights will best be guarded by equal civil rights, at least with respect to voting and earning. This comes, first, from her ‘Hegelian’ contention that recognition, rather than natural right, opens the door to understanding human equality and, second, from the (democratic, not Hegelian) corollary, that equal recognition, embodied in equal political rights, is the antidote for the tensions generated by unequal recognition. If it were true that equal natural rights are best guarded by equal civil rights, there could be no natural rights argument for civil inequality. But there is, and it is an argument concerning one of the most extreme cases of the denial of natural rights, slavery—the centerpiece of Shklar’s argument.

    Jefferson often receives a polemical bruising over the apparent contradiction between slaveholding and natural equality. Jefferson himself was of course fully aware of the problem, and attempted to devise various schemes for slavery’s gradual abolition. This was not simply a matter of finding a practical formula; any practical formula also raised a serious theoretical issue. Government that guards natural rights is government by consent, that is, rational assent. Government by consent in practice entails popular sovereignty. Popular sovereignty, while often consistent with consent, is not always consistent with consent; the majority may vote to oppress the minority in an exercise of passion or prejudice. Theoretically, there is no problem; a majority vote to violate the natural rights of the minority is not genuinely consensual, not consistent with the self-evidence of natural rights. But what if the majority vote to violate the natural rights of the minority does have a serious rational element? That is, what if the attempt to vindicate the natural rights of the minority would involve a serious threat to the natural rights of the majority?

    This might seem impossible, but Jefferson did not think so. In his Notes on the State of Virginia, Jefferson discusses a proposal for emancipating slaves born after a certain time, after they have reached their majority and have been educated at public expense. These young ex-slaves would be emancipated, but they would not be made citizens of Virginia; they would be sent out as colonists to settle elsewhere. “It will probably be asked,” Jefferson writes, “Why not retain and incorporate the blacks into the State, and thus save the expense of supplying by importation of white settlers, the vacancies they will leave? Deep-seated prejudices entertained by the whites; ten thousand recollections, by the blacks, of the injuries they have sustained; new provocations; the real distinctions which nature has made; and many other circumstances, will divide us into parties, and produce convulsions, which will probably never end but in the extermination of the one or the other race.” [7]  Citizenship exists to secure natural rights. But if the expansion of citizenship is likely to endanger natural rights even more than the refusal of such expansion will do, citizenship should not be expanded. Such predictions are a matter of prudential judgment. (In fact, the emancipation of slaves did not lead to the extermination of any race in America, although deep-rooted prejudices of whites and bitter recollections by blacks have indeed divided us into parties and produced convulsions). Not only does natural equality not translate easily into civic equality in practice, as Shklar knows, but it need not invariably translate justly into civic equality, either. The quest for inclusion can run afoul of the quest for justice, although, as Shklar cautions, you need a very good argument to offer proof ‘how so.’ Such an argument requires practical reasoning and the test of experience, and will in the end be probabilistic not demonstrative, undogmatic not ‘thumotic.’ It is both the merit and the problem of liberalism that it tames but also democratizes the thumotic—a point, however, which takes us away from Shklar, toward Francis Fukuyama and Perry Anderson. The tension seen in Shklar’s argument instances the difficulties in attempting to synthesize the American Founders’ understanding of natural right with the Hegelian ‘politics of recognition.’

    Conclusion

    Liberalism is a species of political rationalism. Liberalism’s viability depends crucially upon the kind of reason that the rationalist employs when thinking about politics. Political rationalism can involve deductive/demonstrative reason, practical or prudential reason, dialectical reason, or all of these in a variety of combinations.

    For example, Hobbesian political rationalism gives heavy emphasis to deductive/demonstrative reasoning, following from Hobbes famous ‘discover’ of Euclidean geometry in middle age. Hobbes uses demonstrative reasoning not only to establish the first principles of natural right but for constructive purposes. His monarch is a ‘first principle’ or ‘prince’ from whom all subsidiary powers are derived. Hegel and Marx, by contrast, emphasize the use of dialectical reasoning for purposes of political and social deconstruction and reconstruction. The result oddly resembles that of Hobbes, at least in the sense that the practical result of each theory has been monarchy.

    The American Founders use demonstrative reason in order to establish the first principles and theoretical corollaries of natural right. John Marshall also uses it for legal purposes, to deduce implied powers from stated constitutional principles (McCullough v. Maryland). They use dialectical reasoning for its classical purpose of persuasion, but never in an attempt to establish ‘laws of history.’ (They do not even use the term ‘history’ to refer to what they call in the Declaration “the course of human events.) They use neither demonstrative nor dialectical reason primarily for the purpose of political construction or deliberation. For that, they use prudential reason.

    It may be that Shklar, too, finally uses the dialectical reasoning of the Hegelian ‘politics of recognition’ for persuasive purposes. It may be that the foundation for her, too, is natural right and the prudential defense thereof. But this is not clear. The rhetorical advantage in not making it clear is to get a fair hearing for natural right from scholars who eschew it, to introduce what to them is a bitter food in a palatable, if mushy, mixture. The disadvantage is that she elides a serious schism in American political history and in political philosophy itself, a schism that confuses politicians and ordinary citizens to this day, and has civic consequences, immediate and potential.

    On the one hand, Shklar’s tendency to conflate equal natural right and equal political right misapplies deductive reason to a practical problem. This is likely to lead to a doctrinaire approach to politics, and to a consequent disillusionment when recalcitrant reality fails to bend obediently to the results of the rational deduction. This, it seems to me, is most likely in Shklar’s approach to political economy, where any locally-enforced ‘right to work’ might tend to inhibit the social mobility needed in a large-scale commercial economy. If I have a civil right to a job in the town I live in, will not local labor surpluses be perpetuated, and the labor needs of other localities be starved thereby? Such prudential questions must be raised and answered before a new civil right is established. If not, economic dislocation and political frustration will likely result.

    On the other hand, Shklar’s evocation of a democratized Hegelianism or ‘politics of recognition,’ with its use of dialectical reason for purposes of political construction, resembles, albeit in a very mild form, the moves made by well-known American progressives in the late nineteenth century, moves that issued in the characteristic political themes of the twentieth century: the call for ‘leadership,’ the denial that the Constitution provides an adequate framework for government in the modern world, the establishment of large bureaucracies on the state and national levels, and so on. These themes have had important civic consequences, particularly with respect to the matter of self-government in the sense of civic participation, as many writers ‘Left’ and ‘Right’ have observed. It could not have been Shklar’s judgment to dig into these matters too deeply, in this brief essay. She is surely aware of them, which is why I’ve been so insistent in leaving open the possibility that she evokes the democratized version of Hegelian dialectic for reasons having to do with the original, persuasive, use of dialectic.

     

    Endnotes

    1. Judith N. Shklar: American Citizenship: The Quest for Inclusion (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 13. All subsequent page references to the text.
    2. For a fine use of the distinction between consent and assent, see the statement by the labor union leader, p. 21.
    3. Emanuel Hertz, ed.: The Hidden Lincoln: From the Letters and Papers of William Herndon (New York: Blue Ribbon Books, 1940), p. 407.
    4. On the Boston Tea Party, Washington wrote, “We must assert our rights, or submit to every imposition, that can be heaped upon us, till custom and use shall make us tame and abject slaves, as the blacks we rule over with such arbitrary sway” (Letter to Bryan Fairfax, August 24, 1774, in John C. Kirkpatrick, ed.: The Writings of George Washington from the Original Manuscript Sources (Washington: United States Government Printing Office, 1931), Volume III, p. 242.
    5. See James Monroe: The People the Sovereigns, Being a Comparison of the Government of the United States with Those of the Republics Which Have Existed Before, with the Causes of their Decadence and Fall (Cumberland: James River Press, 1987). See, for example, pages 5, 12-13, 31-36 (on the contrast with the first French Republic); 41-55 (on ancient Greek ‘city-states,’ generally); 68-69 (on modern Britain); 80-102 (ancient Athens). For Madison’s ‘comparative regime’ analysis, see The Federalist #63. For Madison on “auxiliary precautions,” see The Federalist #51.
    6. See John Locke: An Essay Concerning the True Original, State, and End of Civil Government, sections 32-51.
    7. Thomas Jefferson: Notes on the State of Virginia, Question XIII (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), pp. 131-132.

     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    The Goodness of Banality

    February 20, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    “Who would have imagined that these sons of a materialistic generation would have greeted death with such ardor?”
    —Ernst Jünger

    “Our writers used to do their utmost to expose the humbug, deceitfulness, fraudulence, and even the secret crimes of outwardly decent, genteel, and smiling people, but it is a lucky society in which despicable behavior at least has to be disguised.”
    —Nadezhda Mandelstam

     

    A few years before Jünger’s essay appeared, Winston Churchill described the Great War as a combination of pre-Christian ruthlessness with modern national and technological power. “When it was all over, Torture and Cannibalism were the only two expedients that the civilized, scientific Christian States had been unable to deny themselves: and these were of doubtful utility” (The World Crisis). The nineteenth century culminated in something unforeseen: thumotic utilitarianism. The Great Society produced the Great War, as progress in education, science, and the political economies of the nations provided the riches possible materials for conflagration: “When all the trumpets sounded, every class and rank had something to give to the need of the State.” “Far more than their vices, the virtues of nations ill-directed or misdirected by their rulers, became the cause of their own undoing and of the general catastrophe.” But such misrule calls into question the character of the Machiavellian/Baconian enterprise, the conquest of Fortuna: “One rises from the study of the causes of the Great War with a prevailing sense of the defective control of individuals”—even the most powerful individuals—”upon world fortunes.” Or, as John Keegan puts it, the generals were gripped in “a spirit not of providing for eventualities, but rather of attempting to preordain the future,” a spirit that led the old regimes to military and political self-destruction.

    Churchill diagnosed the debacle as the result of the substitution of “national passions” for religious ones. “Almost one might think the world wished to suffer. Certainly men were everywhere eager to dare.” Having hectored themselves for more than a century concerning their insipid materialism and narrow individualism, segments of the bourgeoisie tried heroism. The war may be partly ascribed to moral uplift gone mad. Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche—along with such lesser lights as Carlyle, Ruskin, Barrès, and Wagner—all attempted in various ways either to elevate the bourgeois lump or to explode it. They nearly succeeded.

    Most commercial republicans learned the lesson, and spent subsequent years attempting to promote peace, however ineptly. Wilson had seen the Kantian apocalypse, and readied the Kantian solution—the League of Nations. Lloyd George and Clemenceau were not ready, but their mild-mannered successors were. The Germans—those poets, philosophers, and musicians had played more lovingly with thumotic fires—needed more convincing. So did the Russians, who had never been bourgeois in the first place, and were now in the ideological grasp of a ‘German.’

    America won the Great War, Ernst Jünger claims. In a triumph of the only real commercial-republican art form, advertising, Americans cloaked self-interest in the regnant ideology of constitutionalism and humanitarianism. But—what might have been! Had Germans not been European-all-too-European, had they been uninhibited by vestigial ‘old-regime’ habits, that “mixture of false romanticism and inadequate liberalism”—habits “at heart… not Prussian”: then the youth of Germany, “glowing, enraptured, hungering after death,” nobly despising bourgeois self-preservation, joyfully would have made themselves instruments of the most glorious triumph. Had there only been leaders ready to give German youth “direction, awareness, and form,” then the spirit of the nation would have fused with the spirit of the age, “heroic spirit” with “severe necessity.”

    Jünger senses that the ‘dialectically’ progressivist historicism of the nineteenth century amounts to a thumotic appeal to the human soul, and a critique of the commercial-republican solution to religious strife. ‘Germanism’ (so to speak) has “cultic” dimensions, “the force of faith”;  “the great popular church” of the nineteenth century combines utilitarian ‘realism’ with the absolutism utilitarians dislike. As the near-culmination of this synthesis, the Great War destroyed the old monarchies, the last regimes that respected limits, by means of “Total Mobilization,” i.e., democracy plus bureaucracy, the disciplined participation of all elements in society for a single unifying purpose. The bourgeois social contract is demolished by the revival of the Hobbesian war of all against all—with the crucial difference that “all” now means societies, not weak individuals who are ready to fall into each others’ arms in a new ‘contract.’ Wilson was betting that the national societies, too, would do exactly that, but Jünger matches that bet and raises it.

    The social bonds of these new societies will be far more powerful than the rational calculations of individuals. The ‘inner logic’ of ‘History’ may be seen in the unintended participation even of the soi-disant critics of the State: pacifists on the battlefield; Marxian socialists abandoning their economic determinism for the trenches; nihilists cheering for the Fatherland. The victory of Americanism can be reversed, the true end of ‘History’ achieved, if Germans will only listen to their Prussian soul, realize themselves, bring out “the new race” of the “deep Germany,” author of “a new form of domination.” Even now, bourgeois esteem for equality—prosperity and votes—gives way to the thumotic passions of national socialism. “Behind every exit, marked with the symbols of happiness, lurk pain and death. Happy is he alone who steps armed into these spaces.”

    Walter Benjamin sees that historical materialism is surreptitious theology, a way of reviving many of the passions commercial republicanism sought to redirect, but with the added danger of asserting that in this world might makes right. “[P]oliticians’ stubborn faith in progress, their confidence in their ‘mass basis,’ and, finally, their servile integration into an uncontrollable apparatus [cf. Churchill] have been three aspects of the same thing,” and it is sobering to see that Benjamin here criticizes the relatively benign social democrats, not the Stalins or Hitlers. “Nothing has corrupted the German working class so much as the notion that it was moving with the current.” This Whiggish tale of corruption, which John Adams rightly insisted could be told of classes high and low, recurs with added vehemence when ‘History’ inflates material ambitions with unstable ‘spiritual’ gases.

    Once victorious, modern tyranny reconstitutes the original version of the Hobbesian state of nature, as may be seen (in different ways) in Mandelstam and Jean Améry. In Mandelstam’s telling, “self-government” under Stalin meant control by mutual surveillance—gossip armed with a truncheon. The real Absolute Spirit turns out to be the Terror democratized, made pervasive, atomizing all social relations by making them impossible to rely on. (It took Stalin for twentieth-century intellectuals to relearn what Tocqueville had to say about despotism.) Mandelstam shows that social relations require taking things for granted—such things as decent habits and hypocrisies, reasonable expectations, ordinariness. The inclination to lay bare social relations, subjecting them to unsparing analysis, destroying bourgeois decadence in preparation for some vast, envisioned new creation: all of this unfailingly results in thumos turning in on itself, making life in the anti-society solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and (often decidedly) short.

    Améry unforgettably describes the ultimate anti-society, the concentration camp. He missteps in arguing that Hitlerism was even worse than Stalinism; Nazism most assuredly did have an “idea of man,” namely, the Aryan conqueror, and it likely would have suffered the same welcome ossification as its proletarian counterpart on the ‘Left,’ had it survived. But if this is an error, it is an understandable one; to each his own Hell. Amery’s testimony concerning the impotence of intellect in Auschwitz illustrates not only the obvious point—you can’t think your way out of a well-organized death camp—but also the not-at-all obvious point that in late modernity intellect has lost its primary object, a point well made by Benda, years before the Second World War.

    To say that, in Auschwitz, “intellect had to capitulate unconditionally in the face of reality” means that there was no intellectually respectable ‘court of appeal’ from this concentration of social antimatter. Améry courageously rejects the claim that unassisted human intellect can discover God or ‘History,’ even when the prospect of torture and death concentrate the mind wonderfully. Contra religious and secular-historicist prophecy, the intellect cannot grasp the future, much less shape it. There is a terrible dilemma here: Because the late-modern intellectual’s own intellectual moorings are predominantly social, with a special emphasis on “respect for power”—a mild form of historicism—he cannot adapt even in a limited, ‘merely intellectual’ way to the supreme, ‘totalizing’ historicism, the supreme power-worship, of the death camp. The philosopher’s unassisted intellect, unhinged from its object, nature, by historicist doctrines or secularist ‘religions,’ short-circuits’ in the camp, which, being socially ‘total,’ seems the most real of realities to him. Had Augustine been sent to a death camp, he would have been as miserable physically as anyone else, but he would have faced the brutal fact without intellectual or spiritual disorientation.

    This anti-society has its “antiman,” the torturer, a would-be anti-god who would transform his enemy into nothing but body, then into nothing at all. More, the torturer wants to torture the whole world, “realize his own total sovereignty,” become “master over flesh and spirit, life and death.” This is much more than “the total inversion of the social world,” as Amery calls it. It is the inversion of natural right, that supposedly naïve and superficial doctrine that profound ‘historical thinkers’ rejected. Amery’s experience is the most powerful ‘negative’ argument in support of the existence of natural right. “Amazed,” the tortured person “experiences that in this world there can be the other as absolute sovereign, and sovereignty revealed itself as the power to inflict suffering and to destroy. The dominion of the torturer over his victim has nothing in common with the power of social contracts.” Precisely: it is the purpose of social contracts to prevent such dominion. Those boring, bourgeois, Lockean impediments to tyranny have their modest place, after all.

    In Homer, the heroism on which Jünger and his epigoni keen has its limit: death, the response to which is the fraternity of enemies, Achilles and Priam breaking bread. In Plato, the apparently irreconcilable conflict between thumos and eros is limited by logos and the nature it discovers. The tragic demi-gods of the epics and tragedies and the comic demi-god, the philosophe, of the Platonic dialogues are just that: demi-gods, part god, part mortal human. In Christianity, there is again the man-God who finds—indeed sets—limits. Machiavelli’s centaur, who counsels princes to conquer Fortuna, is the half-man, half-beast who will rule all ‘gods’ and (in the Baconian version) nature too. His limits are only circumstantial; in principle they can be overcome. Nietzsche radicalizes Machiavelli: The philosopher now is neither man-god nor beast-man, but a beast-god, a being of unlimited appetite or eros an unlimited power, the apotheosis of libido dominandi. Nietzsche prudently sees that only the few should aspire to such being, but his vulgarizers, ‘Left’ and ‘Right,” are predictably less cautious and additionally possessed of Wagnerian—no, more, Jüngerian—hubris.

    The course of Western thought since Rousseau has shown how the thumotic critique of the ‘bourgeois’ or self-limiting, self-governing form of modernity became progressively wilder and self-entrapped: a concentration camp in theory leading to concentration camps in practice. Rousseau’s critique retains the limit of nature, although human nature conceived as more or less infinitely malleable provides modest limits, indeed. Hegel’s critique eschews natural right altogether, but sets itself the limit of the ‘end of history,’ which, immodestly but safely, happens to occur in the mind of the sane bureaucrat, Hegel. But in Marx the end of history is material, and in the future; there are no limits or conceptual constraints on how to get there, only an infinitely malleable ‘dialectic.’ In Nietzsche there is not even the vague limit of the end of history; the limit is rather in the conflict of wills, the most powerful and (so he hopes) refined subordinating all the others. ‘Postmodernism’ merely exaggerates the defects of all these later systems.

    The task for political theory is to discover or rediscover conceptual constraints that can be translated into practice. In the meantime, the ‘bourgeois’ solution is the best available—to be criticized, but with equanimity and an occasional dose of modesty. There is some substantial good in much-despised ‘banality.’

    Filed Under: Manners & Morals

    Vaunting Guardians of the Marxist Revolution

    February 19, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    If Fortuna is a woman, what then? Beat her into submission, Machiavelli urges. Sweep aside all effeminacy (that is, Christianity), and conquer.

    Machiavellian spiritedness did not so much conquer the Christian spirit as amalgamate with it, yielding the wars that wracked Europe in the 17th century. Then a saner modernism emerged, one that channeled manly spiritedness into the peaceful bays of commerce and republicanism.

    There was a problem with the commercial republican solution. It could not satisfy the most spirited men and women, whom such glory as parliamentarism conferred could never satisfy, for whom business was a bore. Beginning with Rousseau, who revives Machiavelli’s founder in the person of the Legislator, moderns seek a vaster scope for their ambitions than bourgeois waters afford.

    The tribe of the lion and the eagle: Stalin was such a predator. The Foundations of Leninism introduces readers to a distinctly modern tyrant, one who justifies his actions according to a comprehensive doctrine reducible to a partisan ‘platform.’ The Party, like the Machiavellian prophet, must not go forth “completely unarmed” (102). The Party must be both “bold” and “flexible,” leonine and vulpine (102-103). The Party’s very doctrine is a weapon; “the Party must be armed with revolutionary doctrine” (103). The Party determines the content of its prophecy in accordance with “a knowledge of the laws of revolution”—laws of kinesis, unlike the laws of yesterday, which do not stabilize human societies but heat and reshape them. The Party does not merely govern; it guides. The head of the Party is no statesman; he is the leader of the Party even as the Party “must lead the proletariat” (103-104), which leads all humanity. The Americans had compared Washington to the leader, Moses, during war, then to Cincinnatus in peacetime. So long as there is the Party, there will be no peace. The Party consists of “the General Staff” (104) of the proletarian army, conquering Fortune—the fluctuating, circulating, up-and-down stock market life of the bourgeoisie. Like Machiavelli’s army in The Art of War, the Party replaces virtue with virtù, piety with discipline. ‘Civic life’ be damned; the proletarian dictatorship has a world to win, and no time for the chattering slackers of parliament buildings and newspaper offices.

    “The Party is the embodiment of unity of will, unity incompatible with the existence of factions” (113). James Madison need not enlist; his are the devices of the commercial-republican halfway-house, a drafty structure of rickety architecture, to be demolished by a new, more scientific Corps of Engineers adept at gaining the masses’ “conscious and voluntary submission,” which Stalin (ever the ex-seminarian) rightly sees as the only “truly iron discipline” (114). These incorruptible disciplinarians shall purge their ranks of petty-bourgeois opportunistic polluters, whose dispirited “spirit of demoralization and uncertainty” accords ill with the new spiritedness, the new scientific faith or dialectical prophecy of the bringers of the new order. And what could be more certain than death? Charles de Gaulle told André Malraux that “Stalin said only one serious thing to me: ‘In the end, death is the only winner.'” Genocidal terror gets ‘History’ on your side, with no back-talk. What could be more unifying than a mass grave”

    Stalin, straightforwardly a tyrant, needs smart sycophants willing to trick himout in attractive finery. Georg Luckács does the honors, doing himself no honor thereby. His apologia for Stalin is a contemptible performance, and one of the most valuable any young ‘intellectual’—to say nothing of “the young generation of the Communist Party”—could read. It shows how not to be an intellectual, how an intelligent person can ‘dialecticize’ his way into a sacrificio d’intellectio that excuses mass murder, emitting polysyllabic sonorities and gesturing nobly all the while.

    Lukács correctly sees that Marx transforms transcendence into immanence, divinizing the course of human events and above—no, wrong metaphor: beyond—all else exalts the Party and its Leader. There are no conceptual constraints on the Leader’s tactics; they are, in Lukács’s fine phrase, “conceptually indeterminable.” They sure are—with a vengeance. “The sense of world history” (which is no rigid concept) alone determines the Leader’s tactics.

    This yields a new super-imperative, ‘super’ because it is no longer categorical but supremely spirited: Act as if your action or inaction will change the destiny of the world, All is partisan; the only right consciousness is class-consciousness; you are either with us or against us.

    So far, this is standard Marxist fare. But the special Lukácsian signature comes at the end. Ardent but sensitive young comrades, our consciences must not be allowed to make cowards of us all. Prince-of-Denmark vacillation can never be allowed to persist in a young captain of the world-historical revolution. Virtue must become a noble tragic sacrifice of the priests of virtù, inspirited by the historical Law—rather as Christians are adjured to allow the Holy Spirit to think and act through them, martyrs if they must be. So, as I advance upon my class enemy, truncheon in hand, intending to break his kidneys, I shall assure him, ‘This is going to hurt me even more than it will hurt you. I am no Sadist, taking pleasure in your pain. I do more than feel your pain; I feel my own far more exquisite and tragical agony.’

    By contrast, Rosa Luxemburg shows distinct signs of sanity and decency. She does not lack a certain old-Whig charm, with her insistence that the proletarian democratic-dictatorship replacing the bourgeois democratic-dictatorship retain the proven forms of republican civic life. She truly sees that rule by terror ultimately will demoralize and not re-inspirit the too-spirited terrorizers. In partly excusing the Leninists by arguing C’est la guerre, she exhibits (calculatedly, perhaps) that winning if foolish generosity her enemies despised.

    Her mistake is obvious and comes early. In 1917 Russia, “The democratic republic was the complete, internally ripened product of the first onset of the revolution.” Wrong metaphor: in Russia the democratic republic was the weak infant of the revolution. It needed the most patient nurture, this child of a people who, unlike the Americans of 1776, had little if any experience in self-government. She compounds her error by endorsing the vast project of nationalizing agriculture under large, state-run farms. If done Leninistically, this will bring bureaucratic centralism, injuring civic involvement. If done democratically (as Luxemburg wishes it were) it will load the backs of infant democrats with adult complications unsolved by the most mature republicans. Never fear, she assures us, predicting that “living history,” especially in its scientific-socialist phase, “has the fine habit of always producing with any real social need the means to its satisfaction, along with the task simultaneously the solution.” Caught you, you Emersonian. Would that it were so.

    Like his countryman Machiavelli, Filippo Tomasso Marinetti is a founder. Like Machiavelli’s founders, Marinetti’s are men alone. (Even Machiavelli’s Centaur makes an appearance in The Futurist Manifesto, Machiavelli’s educator of founders.) Marinetti’s founders, like Machiavelli’s, distrust the deceiving senses of sight (classical philosophy) and hearing (Biblical prophecy), but while the politic Machiavelli commends the sense of touch—caressing or annihilating, as circumstances dictate—the artist Marinetti cries, “The scent, the scent alone is enough for our beasts,” our “young lions.” Surely taste will not be the sense preferred, smacking as it does of bourgeois proprieties and genteel refinement.

    As in Machiavelli, the castles-in-the-air of old philosophies and faiths must be brought to earth. Away, pachyderms of “pensive immobility”: “There is no more beauty.” Masterpieces must be spirited, “aggressive.” Sing, goddess, of “the man at the wheel”—not on the wheel—of Fortune. “Time and Space died yesterday,” conquered by the speeding vanguard. Like modernity itself up to his time, Marinetti begins with Machiavelli and ends with Nietzsche. Pitliess, ‘unjust’ action and creativity constitute the only real art, which is the best of life, which is superior to truth.

    André Breton shares this ‘life-over-conscience’ view, which he associates with freedom, “the only word that still excites me.” His freedom is freedom of imagination, which “alone offers me some intimation of what can be.” In The Surrealist Manifesto, he does not explain why imagination does not equally and perhaps more likely offer me intimations of what cannot be, except in dreams. Realism be damned; it is mediocre, hateful, boring, the stuff of novels.

    Breton criticizes logic, meaning analytical logic; he wants do delimit analysis not by noēsis but by imagination. Looking for noēsis, he finds fantasia. The dream is an isle of unlimited, self-satisfying spiritedness or thumos in a vast sea of bourgeois/analytical-rational banality. Like any thumotic personality, he longs for certainty. In this sense he is a Cartesian who rejects Cartesian method, Cartesian rationalism. He drams of a synthesis of dream and reality, surreality, which alone will have the absolute properties of Hegel’s end-of-history with none of the latter’s constricting finality. Surreality is reminiscent of the thumotic Carlyle’s “Natural Supernaturalism.” Surrealism is the dream of Machiavelli’s lion untampered by the shrewdness of Machiavelli’s fox: “Isn’t what matters that we be masters of ourselves, the masters of women and of love too”? To love is to love some thing or some one; love implies the noetic limits imposed by the nature of the object or person loved. but the thumotic man wants to master love, experience pure freedom. Surrealism will make praxis poetic, in acts of Nietzschean fortitude and endurance: having borne, camel-like, the burdens of bourgeois life, having rebelled leoninely, the new artist will be as a dreaming child.

    It turns out that Breton too has a method. Thumos must be freed, but only indirectly (and paradoxically) by an act of passivity. This act is ‘automatic writing’ or ‘stream-of-consciousness,’ whereby ‘Freudian’ subconscious forces are tapped without the unfree, scientistic, analytical trappings of Herr Doktor’s couch. This exercise could happen no more in the ancient world, with its sense of limits and balance, than in Christendom, with its fears that such spiritual exercises could call up real demons. (Surrealism is a modest curlicue on the line of Satanists and mock-Satanists of Romanticism and the later ‘Decadence,’ the line that runs, in different ways, from Sade and Blake through Les Fleurs du Mal and such ‘spiritualist’ doctrines as Theosophy. Hence Breton: “We cross what the occultists call dangerous territory.”

    Surrealist freedom does necessarily not end in anarchy. Breton quotes Baudelaire on the spontaneous and despotic coming of Surrealist images. ‘Sovereignal freedom’ is the result of unlimited freedom. It is as if Rousseau’s solitary walker also wanted to be Rousseau’s Legislator. A “new morality” will be imposed, but, like many a founder, Surrealist man writes books and denies authorship of them. Like Machiavelli’s and Marinetti’s founders, he too will be a man alone with a godlike power or “invisible ray” that will enable him to triumph. (Tristan Tzara rehearses these and other Nietzschean tropes more playfully; his attack on the characteristic question of philosophy—What is?—is especially amusing, albeit sophistical.)

    In art and in politics, the type of soul Plato calls the guardian no longer wants to guard but to rule. In order to rule thumotically, however, it cannot stand still. It must endlessly assert and reassert its freedom. In politics, the triumph over the limits of nature, of the human body, ends in tyranny and death: a stack of dead bodies. In art, the triumph over life—the free, undefinable future of Futurism, the above-it-all freedom of Sur-realism, the comic freedom of the undefinable (thus free, beyond the whatness of nature Dada—all end in another sort of nothingness, the walls of museums and office builders and rich collectors.

    Filed Under: Manners & Morals

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
    • 4
    • …
    • 11
    • Next Page »