Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for January 2018

    Adam Smith, Moralist

    January 1, 2018 by Will Morrisey

    Richard F. Teichgraeber, III: ‘Free Trade’ and Moral Philosophy: Rethinking the Sources of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations. Durham: Duke University Press, 1987.

    Originally published in the New York City Tribune, March 30, 1988.

     

    They are not the same thing, the wealth of nations and the power of nations. Wealth is a form of social and political power, not the whole of it. Communist regimes restrict their own potential wealth in the name of redistributing what they have; nonetheless, they compare rather well militarily to the commercial republics. A political morality of discipline can overcome regimes of liberty, as Sparta defeated Athens. Combine Spartan discipline with Athenian ambition in one man and you get Alexander the Great. Combine them in a nation and you get Rome. In this respect the twentieth century differs not at all from the first.

    Adam Smith tried to reconcile commerce with self-defense, liberty with morality. Although remembered as a political economist, he considered himself first of all a moral philosopher. Professor Teichgraeber shows how Smith integrates commerce into a defense of morality, while refusing to sacrifice philosophic realism to ideology.

    Along with his teacher at the University of Glasgow, Francis Hutcheson, and the philosopher, David Hume, Smith did not conceive of moral virtue as the rule of reason or as the deliberate pursuit of virtue. Virtue is rather “the result of the proper orchestration of private passions.” Who or what, then, does the orchestration?

    Hutcheson followed the teachings of the political philosopher Hugo Grotius, who Teichgraeber regards as a cautious opponent of the Christian-Aristotelian natural law tradition. In this interpretation, Grotius inaugurated the modern natural law tradition—modern because it accepted certain profoundly anti-Aristotelian and un-Christian thoughts of Niccolò Machiavelli, including the reorientation of human attention from heavenly salvation to earthly ambition. Hutcheson to some extent ‘re-moralized’ Grotius by positing the existence of a “moral sense,” a secularized version of Christian conscience.

    Moral sense or sentiment governs the virtuous man, orchestrates his passions—not reason or divine law. Morality should not govern political life, however; Hutcheson regards attempt to use political power for moral ends profoundly mischievous. Politics properly gives private life a stable framework. The peaceful spirit of commerce “supersede[s] the formal requirement of religious worship” and the stern, often warlike exigencies of classical politics. The commercial spirit replaces spirituality and spiritedness.

    David Hume takes Hutcheson’s moral sense and de-moralizes it. He wants a modern science of human nature, a psychology. ‘Value-free’ modern science aims not at improvement but predictability, Teichgraeber claims, and the tame passions of commerce are much more predictable than the grand passions aroused by politics and religion. Government should refrain from attempts at ennobling citizens. It should see only to their defense from violence and to the protection of their property.

    Smith seeks to reestablish a Hutchesonian moral dimension to the commercial system, and to “assimilate Hume’s naturalism to the normative and didactic discourse of Hutcheson’s [slightly] more traditional moral philosophy.” In his Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith argues that one can study human passions scientifically, while also providing moral counsel. Such counsel requires some criterion of judgment; Smith finds it in the concept of the “impartial spectator,” who observes the passions of others but also naturally judges them—not with the intellect, with reason, but with ‘his’ own moral sentiments. It is the impartiality of the spectator, not ‘his’ rationality, which proves a sound criterion of judgment. The spectator has no ox to be gored, no skin in the game—indeed, not ox nor skin at all, only moral sentiments. The Impartial Spectator consists of natural human sentiments abstracted from the natural human body. (We are only a step or two away from Kant’s Categorical Imperative, whereby nature is jettisoned altogether.)

    Limited government protecting a commercial economy defends the natural right of property and thus encourages the virtues of frugality and prudence, albeit at the expense not only of many traditional virtues—particularly those of soldiering, classical and Christian—but, to a lesser extent, at the expense of Smith’s favored private virtues, impartiality and sympathy. Smith distinguishes himself from ideologues who came later, by accepting this sacrifice, knowing the risks but insisting that human society can sustain the private virtues he cared for only if public power limited its moralism and provided sufficient ‘space’ for the quieter virtues to survive, even if to a degree most religious men find lamentable.

    The Wealth of Nations was published in a year that turned out to augur well for a great commercial regime: 1776. The final edition of the Theory of Moral Sentiments appeared in another noteworthy year, 1789. Without mentioning events in France, Smith added a warning: If “public spirit” mixes with “the spirit of system”—that is, systematic doctrine sternly enforced—the result will be a fanaticism in scientific garb as uncompromising as any religious passion. The French Revolution would soon offer a glimpse of that. Our century has offered a panorama.

    “Smith remains an eminent companion for those who ponder the limits as well as the achievements of largely free commercial societies, and wonder why there is no better practical arrangement to serve the common public purpose.” Teichgraeber admits that Smith offers “an unheroic and unromantic view of life, and there are of course other nobler visions of our purpose. Smith’s achievement was to see that there is nonetheless a great and difficult project here, one that men will never pursue consistently.” He continues, “In an age when capitalism has facile champions and dogmatic critics in equal abundance”—would that this were true, worldwide—”Adam Smith remains lucid and realistic about a world he only helped to create.”

    In Professor Teichgraeber Adam Smith has found a lucid and realistic interpreter.

    Filed Under: Philosophers

    • « Previous Page
    • 1
    • …
    • 5
    • 6
    • 7