Will Morrisey Reviews

Book reviews and articles on political philosophy and literature.

  • Home
  • Reviews
    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
  • Contents
  • About
  • Books

Recent Posts

  • Orthodox Christianity: Manifestations of God
  • Orthodox Christianity: Is Mysticism a Higher Form of Rationality?
  • The French Malaise
  • Chateaubriand in Jerusalem
  • Chateaubriand’s Voyage toward Jerusalem

Recent Comments

    Archives

    • June 2025
    • May 2025
    • April 2025
    • March 2025
    • February 2025
    • January 2025
    • December 2024
    • November 2024
    • October 2024
    • September 2024
    • August 2024
    • July 2024
    • June 2024
    • May 2024
    • April 2024
    • March 2024
    • February 2024
    • January 2024
    • December 2023
    • November 2023
    • October 2023
    • September 2023
    • August 2023
    • July 2023
    • June 2023
    • May 2023
    • April 2023
    • March 2023
    • February 2023
    • January 2023
    • December 2022
    • November 2022
    • October 2022
    • September 2022
    • August 2022
    • July 2022
    • June 2022
    • May 2022
    • April 2022
    • March 2022
    • February 2022
    • January 2022
    • December 2021
    • November 2021
    • October 2021
    • September 2021
    • August 2021
    • July 2021
    • June 2021
    • May 2021
    • April 2021
    • March 2021
    • February 2021
    • January 2021
    • December 2020
    • November 2020
    • October 2020
    • September 2020
    • August 2020
    • July 2020
    • June 2020
    • May 2020
    • April 2020
    • March 2020
    • February 2020
    • January 2020
    • December 2019
    • November 2019
    • October 2019
    • September 2019
    • August 2019
    • July 2019
    • June 2019
    • May 2019
    • April 2019
    • March 2019
    • February 2019
    • January 2019
    • December 2018
    • November 2018
    • October 2018
    • September 2018
    • August 2018
    • July 2018
    • June 2018
    • May 2018
    • April 2018
    • March 2018
    • February 2018
    • January 2018
    • December 2017
    • November 2017
    • September 2017
    • August 2017
    • July 2017
    • June 2017
    • May 2017
    • April 2017
    • March 2017
    • February 2017
    • January 2017
    • December 2016
    • November 2016
    • September 2016
    • August 2016
    • July 2016
    • June 2016
    • April 2016
    • March 2016
    • February 2016
    • January 2016

    Categories

    • American Politics
    • Bible Notes
    • Manners & Morals
    • Nations
    • Philosophers
    • Remembrances
    • Uncategorized

    Meta

    • Log in
    • Entries feed
    • Comments feed
    • WordPress.org

    Powered by Genesis

    Archives for September 2016

    Muslims and the Modern State

    September 30, 2016 by Will Morrisey

    Pierre Manent: Beyond Radical Secularism: How France and the Christian West Should Respond to the Islamic Challenge. Ralph Hancock translation with an introduction by Daniel J. Mahoney. South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2016.

     

    After the founding of the American federal state, with its democratic and commercial republican regime, George Washington did not need to address Muslim-American citizens, as there were none. The more immediate question for Americans was whether the several denominations of Christians could live together. And could any of them live with Jews?

    Before the First Amendment guaranteeing freedom of religion, President Washington answered this question in letters he wrote to each of the major religious congregations in the United States. In his First Inaugural Address he had already reminded Americans that the peaceful ratification of the Constitution owed something to God’s providence, that their self-government was not (to use a word not in his vocabulary) a matter of `autonomy’ but of staying within the limits set by the laws of nature and of nature’s God. To the United Baptist Churches in Virginia, the Presbyterian Churches, the Roman Catholics in America, the Annual Meeting of Quakers, and, perhaps most significantly, to the Hebrew Congregation of Newport, Rhode Island, Washington enunciated the American view of peaceful religious practice as a right not a privilege. “It is now no more that toleration is spoken of as if it were the indulgence of one class of people that another enjoyed the exercise of their inherent natural rights, for, happily, the Government of the United States, which gives to bigotry no factions, to persecution no assistance, requires only that they who live under its protection to demean themselves as good citizens in giving it on all occasions their effectual support.” It is noteworthy that Washington in settling the question of religious liberty Washington addressed religious believers not primarily as rights-bearing individuals but as members of congregations, as voluntary associations within American civil society.

    Knowingly or not, in this letter to his countrymen, the French political philosopher Pierre Manent follows Washington’s example. He addresses the French first of all as fellow citizens, not as human beings abstracted from the political circumstance in which they now find themselves. The book consists of a preface followed by 20 succinct chapters. These are structured in a series of three six-chapter waves, cresting in the sixth, twelfth, and eighteenth chapters, followed by two chapters of summary, conclusion, and exhortation. In his fine introduction, Daniel J. Mahoney provides a clear overview of Manent’s argument; here I will follow that argument as it unfolds.

    He begins with one the most familiar and perhaps distinctive features of modern politics: the state and civil society. While modern, centralized states are “large, over-burdened,” and “slow-moving,” the citizens in the societies governed by them “work, reflect, decide, invest, whether in their families, their associations or their enterprises” (3). Despite these energies, citizens seldom “manage perceptibly to modify the course or the physiognomy of the big animal,” except in times of crisis (3). “In fear or in hope, each person is now confronted with what is held in common and what war threatens to ruin or revolution to overturn” (3). The thoughts and actions of hitherto ‘individualistic’ or narrowly ‘groupish’ semi-citizens widen, as “each in deciding for himself decides for the whole, and in deciding for the whole decides for himself” (3). For France, the most recent such moment was June 1940, when the Nazis attacked and conquered. “The defeat was the extrinsic accident that revealed the sickness of the nation’s soul”—a disease Charles de Gaulle diagnosed as the renunciation of moral and political responsibility of the French for France. De Gaulle’s founding of a new republic aimed above all at restoring civic responsibility to the French, but the New-Left uprising of May 1968 shook that regime. Without overthrowing the Fifth Republic, the French Left wounded it; their cherished communitarian illusions defeated, the Left whipsawed from activism to comfortable career advancement within the apparatus of the state that had sought to overthrow: “The citizen of action was followed by the individual of enjoyment” (5). This happened not only in France but throughout the Western republics. But (as usual?) the French took this one step farther. “What is specific to France is the political victory of an essentially apolitical movement” (5), by which Manent means that the utopianism of the Sixties Left and the careerism of French leftists ever since both stemmed from a rejection of the Gaullist call to responsibility, to politics.

    This apolitical utopianism found both its expression and its camouflage in the project of European integration. De Gaulle too wanted a European federation—even to the point of saying to the astonished Soviet premier Alexei Kosygin, “Come, let us build Europe together.” But de Gaulle’s Europe was “L’Europe des patries,” the Europe of the Fatherlands: a federation in which each nation and its state remained self-governing, responsible. But in the Europeanist project that actually developed, “the people, unhappy with government, and the government, unhappy with the people, both turned their faces towards the promised land of Europe where each would finally be rid of the other” (6). Manent remarks, “These sweet hopes are no longer with us” (6), as neither states nor peoples can consummate the grand divorce settlement for which they had hoped in pursuing the European Union.

    This failure has had a serious consequence. “Neither the institutions of Europe, nor the government of the nation, nor what is called civil society [for if apolitical, how civil can it be?] have enough strength or credibility to claim the attention or fix the hopes of citizens. As rich as we still are in material and intellectual resources, we are politically without strength” (6). And those without political strength leave themselves vulnerable to those who are: when Muslims in France “take up arms against us in such a brazen and implacable way, this means that, not only our state, our government, our political body, but we ourselves have lost the capacity to gather and direct our powers, to give our common life form and force” (6-7). The failure of moral responsibility has resulted in intellectual confusion and conflicted feelings, as “our irritated and vacant souls” revolve on themselves, incapable of understanding what is happening to us because we no longer understand ourselves (7). Manent seeks to bring his reader a measure of self-knowledge—”to know better his own soul as a citizen” (7).

    Manent’s book appeared in France in 2015, in the aftermath of terrorist attacks by Muslim Frenchmen. In his first chapter he identifies these attacks not as crimes but as “acts of war” (8). This identification (which would have been obvious to such early modern philosophers as Hobbes, Locke, and Montesquieu) had become difficult for the French of Manent’s time; “we do not know what to think because we do not know how to think” (8), and we do not know how to think because we no longer think of religion “as a social or political fact, as a collective reality, as a human association” (9). Manent assures his readers that he isn’t about to urge them into the confessional but to urge them to think, and to think politically. The liberal regime of the modern French state inclines citizens to regard “public institutions [as] responsible for guaranteeing the rights of the individual,” including the right to one’s opinion on religion (9). More, the education established by that state “discourages all effort to take religion at least a little seriously as a social and political fact” because that education propounds a notion of historical progress which consigns religiosity to the past. Supposedly, “Humanity his irresistibly carried along by the movement of modernization,, and modern humanity, humanity understood as having finally reached adulthood [as per Immanuel Kant’s formulation], is a humanity that has left religion behind” (10). But, as Gilles Kepel argued more than two decades ago in his book The Revenge of God, no one told this to God. The complacent assumption that Muslims would `progress’ towards secularism has proven false. Both Arab nationalism and Arab socialism have staggered and fallen, beginning with the 1979 collapse of the Shah’s regime in Iran—”the beginning of an unseen detour from the great narrative shared by liberals and socialists” (10). Manent eschews the grander debate over whether the great modernist story will resume, although he evidently doubts that the supposed historical laws of historical progress are really laws at all; “it would be better to try to focus on the present, and to take up the task of seeing more clearly what it is we see” (12).

    What we see at present is a “disagreement between the average Western and the average Muslim views” respecting the right “way of life”—the right moeurs. For the West, “society is first of all the organization and the guarantee of individual rights,” whereas for Islam society “is first of all the whole set of morals and customs that provides the concrete rule of a good life” (13). The modern, liberal state that so organizes and so guarantees individual rights failed in both its imperial form with the decline and disintegration of the Ottoman Empire, and then with the several secular nation-states that succeeded it, including those founded by Mustafa Kemal in Turkey, Gamal Nasser in Egypt, and the Pahlavi family in Iran. Crucially, even as in the West the state has strengthened while moeurs have weakened, in the Muslim East states have weakened as moeurs have strengthened. “While we for our part strive to live with no law and no moral rule other than the validation of the validation of the ever-expanding rights of the individual, they hope to find in divine law a just order that political law has too rarely or too sparingly provided” (14). In the West, we see “social dissolution and the loss of the common good” even as “still more rights” proliferate; in the Muslim East, even “those who are offended by the brutality and sometimes the cruelty of Islamism already share the rule of life which the Islamists would like also to make the exclusive political law” (15). In view of this, how could `moderate’ Muslims “oppose very vigorously the imposition of a law whose fundamental goodness they accept? (15). They are more or less in the same moral position as the left wing of the American New Dealers of the 1930s, who jocularly called the Communists “New Dealers in a hurry.” Manent observes that both of these assumptions disregard the “political approach to common life” (16), by which he means what Aristotle means, namely, the practice of ruling and being ruled, shared rule, reciprocity, the way of life that practices reasonable discussion in common of the common good. “Both sides are committed to a process of depoliticization” (16). In France, where both the West meets the Muslim East in the schools and on the sidewalks, there is little foundation for any such shared rule, because neither side understands or wants it and because they would not know how to begin practicing it if they did.

    Concretely (as the Marxists used to say), the French and the West generally face the problem of “how to accept the Muslim way of life as the way of our Muslim fellow citizens, and yet avoid this way finally being confused with the law or taking the place of the law” (17)—precisely the aspiration of so many Muslims. The fact that Muslims freely adhere to Islam does not commit them to the way of life of civil liberty any more than the free adherence of some on the Left to the Communist Party committed Communists to civil liberty. In so arguing, Manent disputes the claim of Western secularists, who suppose that any way of life that does not limit the ways of life of other citizens can find safety within the modern state. He begins by distinguishing between “secularity” and “secularism.” Secularity means what the  George Washington and the other American founders meant by the separation of church and state, whereby government guarantees freedom of worship so long as the practices of a given religion do not impair the natural and civil rights of other citizens. But secularism means something else; it means the attempt by the state to promote religious indifference within civil society. Secularism extends secularity’s religious neutrality of the state to the society the state governs. As Hancock and Mahoney remind us in a footnote, the 1905 French law establishing laïcité resulted in closing Catholic schools and religious orders, a move halted only by the need for national unity during the First World War. Since then, however, secularism has moved less forcefully but more effectively. However, Manent insists, this increased secularism or social areligiosity has actually resulted in a sort of “interpenetration between secular State and a Christian society profoundly marked by Catholicism” (20)—not quite what contemporary Voltaireans have in mind. Instead of a thoroughly secularized state and society, France sees “the neutral or `secular’ state, a morally Christian society, and the sacred nation” (20)—the latter raised up by the French revolutionaries of 1789, reinvigorated in the union sacrée of the First World War, and revived once again by de Gaulle in the aftermath of the Second World War.

    Yet many French persist in envisioning “an imaginary city,” the “secular Republic” wherein historical `progress’ has brought them far beyond religiosity as a matter of civic concern. In religion-free utopia, the current troubles with Islam can be overcome as readily as Catholicism supposedly was. “Yet, in the real Republic, which has been declared henceforth altogether secular, we find nothing to suggest the slightest perceptible progress on this path that we imagine we will follow tomorrow at a vigorous pace” (23). This “secular faith” depends upon an exalted notion of “the State”—a notion some readers may recognize as Hegelian in origin and aspiration. The State has indeed been, “for four centuries, the great instrument of modern politics” (24). But how has it actually worked in France? Has it produced the secular society its proponents long for?

    In actuality, the French state “is much weaker than would be necessary for event slight success in this task” (25)—weaker, indeed, than the state at the disposal of the Third Republic, which itself reached only a compromise (though a beneficial one) with the Church and the nation. “The big difference is that the State of the Third Republic had authority. It represented a nation that all held sacred,” a nation committed to the modern project of social democratization, as Tocqueville had described it. Animated by the philosophic principles of Kant and Comte, the Third Republic had confidence in historical progress and, toward this end, unhesitatingly conscripted young men into military service and, above all, “laid down the content of education very precisely, putting the French language and French history at its center” (25). The state fostered democratic nationalism within the framework of an ideology that combined German idealism with  French positivism. If the idealism gave it moral elevation, the positivism gave it at least the sense, the hope, of hard-headed practicality. Today, however, “our life is much more pleasant” than it was at the turn of the last century but “our State is much weaker” (25). It has “abandoned its representative ambition and pride, thus losing a good part of its legitimacy in the eyes of citizens” as the indeterminate internationalism of pan-Europeanism has partially replaced democratic nationalism (25). A de-nationalized citizenry cannot sustain any real citizenship, so the nation’s ability to `push back’ against the weakened French state languishes. It no longer dares to conscript its citizens and it no longer cares to educate them civically, to provide them with “a truly common education designed to produce a common mind” (26). Even the secularism that remains amounts to little more than moral and cultural relativism: “Under the name of secularism we dream of a teaching without content that would effectively prepare children to be members of a formless society in which religions would be dissolved along with everything else” (27). The strong and decisive modern state has become an imbecile, having “gradually but methodically stripped itself of the resources that once made it the characteristic instrument of modern politics” (27). This is what the much-touted ‘post-modernism’ of French intellectuals has produced. Although utopians dream of ‘globalization,’ in reality the weak state leaves itself vulnerable to another form of internationalism, the Muslim ummah. “How would such a weak State suddenly find the strength to give the law to religion”—as the Third Republic did—”especially when the religion in question has no doubt concerning the legitimacy of its collective rule and when its believers have no particular reason to respect the State in question?” (28).

    But in fact, and quite apart from the grand compromise of the union sacrée, even the French state under the Third Republic experienced “an enormous political and spiritual failure,” “a religious obstacle that no one had anticipated” (28). This was the Dreyfus Affair, which highlighted the dilemma of the place of Jews in the democratic-nationalist French state. If the Third Republic collapsed in 1940 because factions had weakened it far too much to withstand the Nazi attack, and if these political divisions were symptoms of as well as aggravations of moral irresponsibility (as de Gaulle argued, with Manent concurring), the rise of anti-Semitism in the period between the middle of the nineteenth century and the Second World War “signals the first great failure of the liberal State” (29)—specifically, the failure of that state to protect Jews in the society governed by that state. The state’s failure in this task—a task that George Washington saw as indispensable to a regime of civil liberty—its failure to convince its own citizens why Jewish citizens must be respected by their fellow citizens, enabled enemies of the liberal state in France and elsewhere in Europe to use an ever-strengthening anti-Semitism as a weapon against the regime of liberal and democratic republicanism. Monarchists and fascists alike, in opposition but also in symbiosis with the communists (who were not anti-Semitic but who of course detested liberal and democratic republicanism), fatally weakened the Third Republic and the network of republics throughout the Continent.

    French republicanism hadn’t started out that way. In the formulation of a prominent liberal aristocrat, the Comte de Clermont-Tonnerre—like so many of his political friends, a victim of the extremist Jacobins a few years after he made his speech in December 1789—the Republic intended “to refuse everything to Jews as a nation, and to grant everything to Jews as individuals” (quoted p. 29). The problem with this, as Washington implicitly saw when he wrote to a Jewish-American congregation, is that Jews are both individuals and a nation, in fact a nation with a unique mission and regime or way of life. In the years subsequent to the First and then the Second Republics, and especially in the Third Republic, “the European liberal State… failed to bring about the transformation of the Jewish way of life into the guarantee of rights to Jewish individuals as citizens” (30). This failure had two opposing consequences: the Holocaust or Shoah and the subsequent founding of the state of Israel as a homeland and refuge for the Jewish nation which had been persecuted and left to die by the European liberal state. At the same time, Manent observes, the founding of Israel does not solve the so-called Jewish problem not only because that state has no shortage of virulent enemies but because the Jewish nation has a meaning for humanity beyond the borders of any state, whether that state is secure or threatened.

    Given these facts, what now is the status of Jews in France, in the wake of terrorist attacks by Muslims in France? The formulation of Clermont-Tonnerre no longer suffices. One suspects that the nineteenth conflation of the notion of nation with the biological notion of race—seen in the very word ‘anti-Semitism‘ as distinguished from anti-Judaism—inclined Europeans (who supposed ‘race science’ actually to be scientific, a thing on the very cutting edge of scientific progress) to deny the natural-rights individualism that allowed men like Washington to uphold the rights of human groups who had covenanted with themselves or even with God to pursue aims consistent with the laws of nature and of nature’s God, the Creator Who endowed human beings with rights as individuals, including the liberty to enter contracts and covenants. Be this as it may, the regime of the Third Republic, animated by the principles of Kantian idealism and Comtean positivism which had replaced unstably the more coherent natural-rights principles of the First Republic, never adequately addressed the question of Jews’ status in French society, and today’s much-weakened French republican state has failed to protect not so much their civil status as their natural right to life itself. This failure has yet to approach the failure of the last years of the Third Republic, leading to the crisis of 1940, but it “manages less and less to give meaning to the association” of “force and justice” upon which the legitimacy of any decent modern state must rest (31).

    This requires both Jewish French citizens and non-Jewish French citizens to “outline the contours of a new association that will no longer be simply contained in the political regime [of republicanism], indispensable as that regime remains” (32). French citizens of Christian inflection (including those who have abandoned Christian theology and Church membership) are “heirs of Israel” (32) by way of Jesus’s Judaic witness, His insistence on the validity of the Law of God. “If the Jews were set apart from the ‘nations,’ this was to reveal God as a friend to mankind among the nations, and to make Him present among them”; the Jewish nation, the light unto those nations, has thus “assur[ed] the mediation between God and humanity,” whether in the original Israelite regime or in the renewed spiritual regime that centers on the worship of Jesus as Christ  (32). In Europe, “this mediating role was appropriated and claimed by the Catholic church, reducing the Jews to the role of passive witnesses who transmitting the Books without understanding them”—a nation supposedly superseded by the Church (32).

    The searing memory of the Shoah remains one side of Europeans’ horribly late recognition that the doctrine of supersession cannot withstand rational scrutiny. But more is needed. The term ‘anti-Semitism,’ with its overtones of race theory, made sense in the intellectual atmosphere of the Dreyfus Affair, but it only obscures the circumstances France and the West generally face today. Islamists target not some supposed ‘race’ but religions and their adherents, including but by no means limited to Judaism and Jews. “The word that fits the new reality is the word war” (33). This war targets Jews, Christians, blasphemers, Muslim ‘apostates,’ and also “the authorities and institutions of Western nations” (33). For non-Islamists, this war is a “defensive war” (34), but a war it is. And in fighting it, every Western nation-state will need to find “the contours of a new friendship for which the political means are not available” (34), given the morally and intellectually disoriented character of the modern state (34). “Within this friendship”—which can only begin in civil society, not the state—”Jews as Jews and as a people are an essential element. The part they will now play in the world will demand of them a mediating role that might be said to correspond to the deepest vocation of Judaism” (34). For France this would mean a reconstituted and improved union sacrée. What the French state of the Third, Fourth, and Fifth Republics all failed to solve ‘from above,’ the French themselves must move decisively to solve ‘from below.’ If they can do so, ‘2015’ will prove to have been another ‘1940,’ another ‘1871,’ another ‘1789.’

    Thus the first ‘wave’ of Manent’s essay begins with a consideration of modern political regimes and the modern state, especially as seen in France. It culminates in a consideration of the failure of that state fully to solve the religio-political question with regard to the Jewish citizens of France and a call for a renewed effort to re-found the liberal state through a civil-social coming-together of all French citizens threatened by Islamist violence in the service of a profoundly illiberal projected regime. The next ‘wave,’ which gathers strength in chapters 7 through 11 and crests in chapter 12, addresses the question of Islam in the civil society that must take over the task the State has failed to perform.

    Insofar as the modern republican state weakens, “we return to the pre-modern situation”—feudalism—but without the now-vanished features of the original feudal societies in Europe (35). The Catholic Church remains, but in much-chastened form, while the aristocrats and dynasts have disappeared almost entirely. Nonetheless, like feudalism, the post-modern, post-statist Europe features societies without clear borders, wherein ‘interior’ and ‘exterior’ mingle transnationally. Globalization is the new feudalism. “What is often neglected… is that this effacing of political borders leaves religious or more generally spiritual borders largely intact”; their borders “tend to become the main borders” (36). These too are somewhat porous, at least in Europe, given the influx of Muslim immigrants. Europe’s problems “will prove insoluble if we do not succeed in developing a coherent and stable disposition that defines our relation to Islam as such socially, politically and spiritually” (37). Republicanism in France aims at the common good, at “civic friendship” (38). How shall the French establish such friendship with Muslims, admitting the failure of secularism to transform Islam or to transform a critical mass of Muslims? The fact is that “Islam fulfills and brings together the three dimensions of human time, giving stability, compactness and completion to the umma” (39); Islam gives its adherence a purpose secularism simply cannot offer. Why would Muslims, especially young Muslims, abandon the one for the other? “Thus the world in which we must live and act is a world marked by the effort, the movement, the forward thrust of Islam”(39) even as “Europe is disarming itself in its core” (40) precisely by eschewing common goals and common efforts in the name of individualism in the Tocquevillian sense of a refusal of political activity, of political and civil-social organization, in favor of an ever-narrowing circle of friends and family—all valorized in the name of ‘rights.’

    Islam “advance[es] into Europe” by immigration, by investment, and by the use of terror (41). Although these three means of advancement (or to put it more dramatically than Manent does, conquest) are analytically separable, they are related in practice. Immigration provides a demographic base; money provides mosques and publishing houses. As for terrorism, it “would not be what it is, it would not have the same reach nor the same significance, if the terrorists did not belong to this population and were not our fellow citizens” (42). In view of this, the “coherent and stable disposition” the French must develop “must be essentially defensive” (43); emotionally satisfying as it may be to (as Americans say) ‘go on offense,’ that will not work as a means of achieving a peaceful conclusion to this war.

    Manent regards French and indeed Western disorientation in the face of the “forward thrust of Islam” as entirely understandable: “This is the first time for quite a long time that something new in the West did not come from within Western life, from the internal development of Western society and politics” (44). So much so that the West even generated an ideology, historicist progressivism, to valorize and to explain this development. In formulating a strategy of self-defense, such complacency will only continue us in our illusions. Given the demographic and spiritual strength of Islam in Europe, Manent calls for intellectual and spiritual regrouping; “our regime must concede, and frankly accept their ways, since the Muslims are our fellow citizens. We did not impose conditions upon their settling here”—why would we, if we believed in the inevitability of historical progress toward secularism?—”and so they have not violated them” (45). Even the new, nationalist French Right of Le Pen père and Le Pen fille will find, if they eventually win office, that control of a vitiated State will not enable them to do the things they want to do. A defensive strategy will begin with French self-knowledge—a consciousness resulting from the forced acknowledgment of the differences between ‘Frenchness’ and Islam brought on by the Muslims’ advances—a knowledge of the “great moral and spiritual resources that can be renewed, activated, and mobilized in order to contain this inevitable change within certain limits, and to preserve a country whose physiognomy remains recognizable” (46). The French must therefore, first, accept Muslims “as they are,” “renounc[ing] the vain and somewhat condescending idea of an authoritarian ‘modernizing’ of their way of life,” and, second, “preserve and defend, as an inviolable sanctuary, certain fundamental features of our regime and certain aspects of France’s physiognomy” (46-47).

    Specifically, with regard to prudent renunciations by the French, Manent finds requirements that public schools serve uniform menus (including pork) to all students a policy of “meanness”, and the refusal to allow different swimming pool hours for girls and boys an instance of civil discourtesy that deserves prudent abandonment (48). But Manent devotes much more attention to the features in need of defense, perhaps because the French are so confused about them.  As the fundamental unit of political life, the one in which children first learn what political relations are by observing the reciprocal rule of husband and wife, the family is another matter; “it is our right to prohibit polygamy and this we do, [he adds with Gallic irony] at least in principle” (49). In the public square, moreover, “the burqa is inadmissible,” inasmuch as the social “physiognomy” of the West cannot survive the concealment of the human face (49); “it is by the face that each of us reveals himself or herself at once as a human being and as this particular human being”—a “mutual awareness that is prior to and conditions any declaration of rights” (49).

    Beyond the family and civil society, the political realm too has elements deserving “intransigent preservation” (49). Principal among these are “complete freedom of thought and expression” (51) and the French “way of life” (55). With regard to civil liberty, the French should reject the use of the term ‘Islamophobia’ to repress any and all critical discussion of Islam, thereby preserving “the capacity to treat Islam in the same way all political, philosophic, and religious elements of our society have been treated for at least two centuries” (51). To (as it were) privilege Islam would amount to “the worst service we could render to Islam at a time when demands for its reform are heard on all hands,” first and foremost Islamic hands (51). While respecting Islamic persons (and perhaps because we respect them as persons, as human beings), the French must reserve the right to combine that respect with “vigorous criticism of opinions that seem to be false” (52). At the moment, we in the West live more and more in a society in which any opinion is tolerated but persons are routinely subject to vituperation and contempt. We would do better to reverse that practice, and better still to meet the opinions with reasoned argumentation. On this point Manent takes gentle issue with Pope Francis, whom he catches equating respect for one’s mother with respect for one’s religion. The figure of the Mother Church notwithstanding, my mother is mine in a way my religion is not, inasmuch as Christians are adjured to share their religion but not their mothers with the rest of the world, and are additionally commanded to turn the other cheek in response to insults to their persons and opinions but not necessarily to insults to their mothers. “Precisely because the freedom to judge, and thus to criticize, has such a strong tendency to provoke passions… it is so important to obey the law that commands us to respond to critical speech, if one is to respond to it, only by critical speech” (53). Bombing the office of a vulgar and irreligious publication will not do. Why so? Because criticism of opinion “demands reasons” and reasoning is the distinctive characteristic of the political relationship, the reciprocal rule of one another by discussion and compromise (54).  Today, our postmodern, post-rationalist (and therefore post-Western) attitude causes us to demand “a freedom without reason, a freedom that does not need to give reasons since it always has a ‘right’ or a ‘value’ at its disposal; so marvelous are these claims that they are established just by being stated” (54). But even Nietzsche—especially and above all Nietzsche—would scorn this democratizing, leveling assumption that Everyman can be his own Superman. Such democratized and therefore individualized or privatized self-assertion feels like strength but ends in weakness, as it spoils our ability to organize ourselves into groups strong enough to offer prudent resistance to groups that organize themselves spiritedly around spiritual claims.

    The twelfth and culminating chapter in this second ‘wave’ of Manent’s essay considers the European way of life in its relation to the self-confident Muslim way of life. Although in Aristotle a ‘way of life’ referred to one dimension of the regime of the polis or self-ruling city, the spread of religions—themselves requiring adherence to God’s way for His creatures—gives a regime-like dimension to populations that cut across many sovereign states. Europe, once the heart of Christendom, has a “physiognomy,” too. In Europe, the way of life shared by citizens has an internal or regime dimension strictly speaking (limited to one’s country) along with an external or civilizational dimension that extends across the continent, reaching its limits on the borders with Russia and the Balkans. “Islam presents a question to each nation, and at the same time to our civilization, or to European history” (57). Unlike Europe, “Islam was never able to abandon the imperial form that Christianity was never lastingly to assume” (58).

    By “political form” Manent means something different from “regime.” Aristotle classifies political communities in terms of regime, with their four dimensions: quantitative (a community is ruled by one, a few, or many); qualitative (those rulers are good or bad); teleological (the purposes or aims of the community); and finally the Bios ti or way of life, what Tocqueville later calls the habits of mind and heart. Another way of classifying political communities (and Aristotle knew this, too, although he doesn’t dwell on it) is in terms of their geographical and demographic size on the one hand and their degree of political centralization on the other. Manent contrasts the city (‘city-state,’ as it is usually called)—small and centralized—with the sprawling and perforce less centralized empire. In the city we find “the purest political form” (59), the community in which who rules, what their purposes are, and the way of life they foster matter a lot to every resident; in such a small place, rulers can really rule. “The city has no other raison d’être than to produce the association, or the community, whose material and moral resources are sufficient to allow citizens to lead the ‘good life'” (59) But “the moral character of the empire is more uncertain, even suspect, insofar as the pride of domination flourishes there in an expansive movement that has no natural limits”; even if “very well and very humanely governed,” the empire “is subject to a principle of boundlessness that prevents or hinders the mind’s self-reflection” (59). And in more gritty terms, the empire often simply lacks the means effectively to control its own periphery; its boundlessness thus may lead from rapid expansion to sudden shrinkage, as seen in the Soviet Empire in the past century, and as seen throughout the long history of China. Ancient Israel managed to be universalist in its mission, the light unto the nations, while (usually) preserving “its knowledge of the meaning of humanity” by resisting imperial boundlessness (59).

    By contrast, the Muslim prophet Muhammad founded an empire, thus subjecting Islam to “what might be called the curse of extension, which brings about the fragmentation of imperial territory and often the tendency towards independence of distant provinces, which do not, however, really achieve a true independence that would remove them from the imperial form of Islam” (60). Imperialist expansions and contraction have plagued it, as the contemporary example of the ‘Islamic State’ demonstrates for our generation.

    What made Western Europe differ from the equally Christian but perennially imperial Eastern-European ‘Byzantium’? What made it, if not a realm of city-states, a realm of nation-states? Manent doubts the argument that the Catholic (and later partly Protestant) civilization of Western Europe took Jesus command to separate the things of God from the things of Caesar more seriously than the Orthodox world did. The early Church did not emphasize this distinction. What is more, the distinction between Church and State, which made so much of Jesus’s aphorism, “was in fact clearly set forth only after Europeans had re-founded their political order by entirely emancipating their political principles from all dependence in relation to the Christian proposition, and even from any direct connection with it” (61). The notion that there is an entity called ‘the State’ that can be considered entirely apart from the individuals who compose ‘civil society,’ and that moreover those individuals have rights the State should secure, but quite independently of whether the State actually does what it should do: that notion does not suggest the existing of a dispute between the claims of rulers (God and Caesar). Further, “what the declarations of the rights of man say of humanity and to humanity has nothing to do with what Christian preaching says of and to humanity”; to say that man is “born free and that he can and must govern himself according to his freedom” differs sharply from “tell[ing] him that he is born a slave of sin and that he can only be freed by the grace of Christ” (61-62).

    In addition to this historical critique of the ‘God-and-Caesar’ origin story of Europe’s civilizational distinctiveness, Manent offers a political one. In order to separate Church and State, citizens need to think and act as citizens capable (by the fact of their citizenship or membership the ruling body of the regime) to do any such thing. This includes Christians, citizens of both this ‘city’ and God’s ‘city.’ What caused this unity of purpose in Europe? Europeans “strove to bring this collaboration [of their religious and their political purposes] to fruition in a new political form, a political form ignored by the ancients,” a form combining “the pride of the citizen, or more generally of the acting human being, and the humility of the Christian” by leaving to the Church the spiritual formation of citizens while reserving self-governing political action to the State (64-65). This meant that Christians, their souls decisively inflected by the Holy Spirit, would take actions consensually guided by Church teachings but not directed by Church officials. “The object of Europe’s ceaseless quest can be defined, in theological terms, as the common action of grace and of freedom and, in political terms, as the covenant between communion and freedom” (65). This in turn enabled Christians to participate as citizens of the city of God, in a catholic or universal religion, while simultaneously exercising citizenship in particular, limited human communities. Europe became a community of spiritual education that wove together self-government and a relation to the Christian proposition, a two-fold intention that opens a plural and indefinite history, the history of the European nations” (66). In Western Europe, the Catholic Church remained Roman—a body that recalled, even in its centuries of empire, the political and republican origins of that empire: “There was always the city as a living, even if almost smothered, principle; beneath the princeps or imperator, there was the populus romanus” (65).

    Once the unity of purpose that separated Church and State disappeared into the mono-atheism of secularism, once the union beneath the division was removed, Europe lost any coherent purpose. It became spiritually and morally weak, therefore politically weak because lacking a way of life that inspires the moral strength needed to defend itself against devotees of Islam, who are not at all lacking in purpose, and in the strength that goes with it.

    In the third wave of his argument, Manent returns to France  without forgetting Europe. He begins by considering the way Muslim citizens of France should be addressed by the non-Muslim majority. The argument culminates in an appeal for a special role for the French Catholic Church in this civil-social crisis. He first clears away the ideological debris blocking the initiation of such discussion. If French secularism precludes religion from discussion in the public square, why does this apply to Christians and Jews but not to Muslims? That is, if critiques of Muslims by non-Muslims deserve to be dismissed as ‘Islamophobic,’ why are Muslim (and secularist) critiques of Christians not condemned as ‘Christophobic,’ and critiques of Jews condemned as ‘Judeophobic’? If secularism requires us to ignore religions as associations or communities and make moral and political judgments solely on the basis of individual rights abstracted from their sociopolitical context, does not the “unhindered presence of Islam” mark a not only a “spiritual evisceration” of Christianity and Judaism not required of Muslims, but also a denial of the obvious reality of religions as social entities? “If have one ambition, it is that the analysis I propose of the European experience might be adequate to allow us to see Islam as an objective reality, instead of its remaining in the reflection of our self-misunderstanding” (69). This self-misunderstanding stems from Europeans’ loss of “faith in the primacy of the Good” (69), a faith powerfully reinforced by religion but not necessarily requiring religiosity in every citizen. Because “every action, and especially civic or political action, is carried out in view of some good, especially in view of the common good” (70), loss of faith in the Good paralyzes both thought and action. In Christianity and Judaism, faith in the primacy of the Good rested on faith in the God Who is the ultimate Good, and Who works through His Providence to coordinate events so as to serve His purposes. For seventy years, the Shoah has been deployed as evidence against Providence. “The Judge seems to be under judgment: Where was He?” (70). But to judge God not only entangles us in arguments answered impressively in the Book of Job; it also forces us into either Epicureanism, the so-called religion of the philosophers, or to a sort of Manichean or at least pagan claim that God or the gods must be evil. Avoiding theological disputation, Manent simply observes that neither Epicureanism nor a theology of despair can possibly support “the desire to govern ourselves and the confidence in or own powers that alone can nourish this desire”(70)—precisely what a firm defense of abstract human rights requires. Our semi-politicized Epicureanism actually replaces divine Providence with the Invisible Hand of the marketplace; “we have constructed a system of action that can best be described as an artificial Providence” (71). The marketplace valorizes in the material realm what individualized, depoliticized human rights valorize ideologically: satisfaction for everyone. But this valorization undermines the civil framework within which markets can be protected and human rights can be secured.

    Islam can enter and remain in Europe only if Europeans move from ‘rights talk’ to purposeful action. “Islam can only be received within a community of action that engages it and essentially obliges it to participate what is common,” a shared understanding of the Good (73). As a civilization, Europe forms the geographical and moral ground for that understanding, but politically this can be done only through self-governing nations and not through that combination of market and bureaucratic forces that ‘Europe’ consists of. Here the governments of those nations have failed, preferring obfuscation to real discussion by refusing to acknowledge Christianity, Judaism, and Islam as social realities and condemning those who dare to discuss Muslims as Muslims. European governments command their nations to close their eyes in the hope that this will make the world go away. “By their determination to lay down the law concerning social perceptions and the words that translate them, our governments are increasingly abandoning the domain of actual political action” (75). In the name of human rights defined as equality, governments turn out the lights in the hope that all cows will become black.

    This being so, “What does equality mean for the Muslim citizens of France?” (78). At present, “we have only a very vague and incomplete knowledge of the extent of their claims” because they do not elaborate them (78). And even if they did articulate their claims more fully, the current French tendency to filter all claims through the sieve of individual rights may distort them. If these circumstances persist, Muslims “will tend more and more to be a distinctly solid and compact element, while neither they nor their fellow citizens will be capable of giving meaning to a coexistence between heterogeneous ways of life” (80). Each side will stay in its own box, hermetically sealed, breached only by explosions. This results from separating “the rights of man… from man” (81)—that is, from the social and political nature of man; “the rights of man have been separated radically from the rights of the citizen” (85). This cannot actually happen, if only because it would require Muslims to stop being Muslims and to become beings attentive only to human rights as defined by non-Muslims. But any transformation of Muslims (or any other group) can only come in a social and political setting—in France, and in the rest of Europe country by country.

    To bring Muslims more fully into the French republic no such a priori transformation is feasible. This is especially true, given that “the political and spiritual weakening of the nation in Europe is doubtless the major fact of our time” (82) and that there has been no corresponding political or spiritual strengthening of Europe to compensate for this weakness. “If Islam spreads and consolidates in a space deprived of a political form, or in which all forms of common life are delivered over to gnawing criticism from the standpoint of individual rights, now the source of all legitimacy, then there hardly remains any future for Europe but that of an Islamization by default” (82). Why would Muslims feel the slightest need to adapt, particularly in light of the global reach and imperialist bent of their religion? Since the modern state “tends to deny the relevance or importance of the question of the regime or political form because, by guaranteeing members of society the enjoyment of their rights, it seems to dispense them from having governed themselves” (86), why would a religiously serious people view such tame but undisciplined persons with anything other than distaste and contempt? And why would a religiously serious people regard persons in the thrall of secularism as anything better than fools, if not scoundrels? In contemporary Europe what is called ‘governance’ “is really only government by the State alone“—government by administration (87). But government by administration (as Tocqueville observed in Democracy in America) amounts to soft despotism over human beings reduced to the status of timid and industrious herd animals. Despite its net of rules and regulations, the administrative state really wants to issue only one core requirement for its subjects to obey: “to relax” (96).

    Returning to the topics of regime and religion, Manent defends republicanism or representative government, beginning with the observation that representation “presupposes a people to represent” but Europeans are not one people but many. Therefore, they must turn to their own countries if republicanism will survive; at most, a European parliament could only represent the constituent nation-states in a federal structure. If the people are to govern themselves, they must do it at home. In so doing, they can discover if Muslims in France and elsewhere really want to participate in a republican government with their fellow citizens or instead “see themselves as on the margins and so to speak in secession” (89). More than this (and here Manent shows a citizen’s toughness) the French must test French Muslims by “commanding [them] to establish the independence from the various Muslim countries that send out imams, and that finance and sometimes administer or guide the mosques” (89). “The point is for each party to the debate to show that it is serious and to this end to take certain actions that cost something and that show a commitment” (89). The imperial ambition blurs the distinction between internal and external, citizen and foreigner; ruling many from afar, it prefers an attenuation of self-government. Manent demurs. In this defensive war, France’s republic must determine whose side each citizen is on. If it refuses this elementary responsibility, the French will see “whether we still have a government” (92) at all. Forced to show their hand, to decide, French Muslims will relinquish their passivity: no more deceptive waiting game. In return, they would be afforded their own “place in the French public square,” liberated from “all slavish dependence on the powers that dominate the rest of the Muslim world” (93). “If we fail, that will mean both that our regime has entirely lost the representative virtue that had defined and animated it since it founding, and that France’s Muslims are incapable of moving beyond the immobility of their moral practices in order to nourish a political desire, that is, in order to experience effectual freedom as Muslims” (94).

    Manent brings these currents together in chapter 18, the third crest of the three waves of his argument. Today, “when we are asked to adhere to the values of the Republic, nothing is asked of us” (96) as rational and civil beings. “The new citizenship consists in demobilizing the affects of citizenship”; the so-called identity politics of human-rights assertion looks to the state and not to civic friendship for validation (96). “The ‘I’ imagines that it can identify itself with all things as it pleases, and identify all things with itself” (96), unconcerned about ‘otherness’ because ‘difference’ can be dismissed in a cloud of verbiage. Against this, Manent calls upon French Muslims “to become truly citizens” as Muslims. “If the nation in a certain sense detaches them from their religion, since they share it with non-Muslims, it immediately gives it back to them, and they receive it now in a way from the nation in which they have finally found, not only a place, but their place”(97). No secularism, and no sectarian enclaves governed by religious law instead of French law: “It is up to Muslims to find a place in a place in a Christian country, or a country of a Christian mark” (99). This is no dhimmitude in reverse, no subservience to Christianity. “Christians, or particularly Catholics, do not rule in France” (101) because of course Catholic made exactly the same transition, balancing citizenship in their native city as well as in the Kingdom of God, in the past century. To demand this adaptation by Muslims will have the salutary effect of reminding French Catholics that they are the Catholics of France. Recalling that Manent had remarked the Catholic-Christian assertion of supersession regarding Judaism, Manent effectually recommends that French Catholics now live up to that claim. Given that the West now features “five great spiritual masses”—Judaism, Islam, Evangelical Protestantism the Catholic Church, and human-rights secularism—”what characterizes and distinguishes the Catholic Church within this configuration is, if I may say, its calmness and equilibrium” (103). The other groups “wish to know only their own rights and their own reasons,” but the Catholic Church, having undergone a true crisis of conscience in reaction to the Shoah and in response to “its responsibility for anti-Judaism and anti-Semitism” seen in the Dreyfus Affair at the beginning of the century and the anti-republican Vichyism of substantial elements of its clergy at mid-century (103), now reaches out to “each of the other great spiritual forces” (105). “Alone capable of nourishing a meaningful and substantial relationship with all the other spiritual forces,” “at the center or the pivot of a configuration in which we have to lie and the think,” the Church can become “the mediator par excellence” (105)—exactly the role Manent earlier ascribed to ancient Israel. Roman Catholics have long claimed that Christianity has superseded Judaism; now we will see if they really can do so. France needs it to do so, and maybe other countries also do. After all, France and the Church themselves have exemplified the genuinely political relationship of ruling and being ruled: “If the Church has played an axial role in the history of France, France has often played a determining role in the history of the Church” (106). Pope Francis, do not forget Cardinal Richelieu.

    In his parting words to Catholics, who have often felt ‘marginalized’ in contemporary France, Manent wonders, “How can one leave this quasi-clandestine state without joining the prideful competition of claims and counter-claims that is the scourge of our whining age?” (107). He addresses this question in his two final chapters, widening it to Muslims, as well. On the periphery of today’s “public life,” Catholics remain at the spiritual center of the West; they will return to the center of the public domain if, imitating the traditional role of Jews but now in the modern world, undertake “the task of holding together the configuration that joins her with Judaism, Islam, evangelical Protestantism, and the doctrine of human rights” (108). For their part, Muslims must answer the Catholic and simply French invitation (if it comes) and assume the role “not simply… as rights-bearing citizens, accepting other bearers of the same rights, but as an association marked by Christianity granting a place with which it has never before mixed on an equal footing” (108). It is further “necessary that they accept this nation as the site of their civic activity, and more generally of their education”—not, to be sure, to accept a secularism as repellant to them as it is to Catholics, observant Jews, and evangelical Protestants—but to ensure their status as “a distinct community in a nation in which they are citizens like others (109). That nation will remain “a nation of a Christian mark in which Jews play an eminent role” (109). Can this aspiration be realized? “While our failure would signify the dislocation of the nation and the inglorious end of an enduring hope, success would resonate well beyond the narrow limits of our country, since the man spiritual forces of the Atlantic and Mediterranean worlds would be concerned” (110). I am reminded of President Charles de Gaulle’s invocations of “Latinity”—Roman republicanism with a Christian mark—an appeal to both moderation and grandeur with France as its originator in the modern world, but with all nations with the heritage of Rome as its audience. “This should motivate our desire for glory, if we have any left” (110); de Gaulle might nod in approval.

    Each in its own way, Europe and Islam have denigrated the measured limits of political life. Europe has done so in the name of markets, “the free movement of capital, of goods, of services, of people, just as no law must circumscribe the unlimited right of individual particularity” (111). Islam has done so in a religio-imperial attempt to win the world for the rule of the laws of Allah. Whereas Europe has abandoned politics, Islam has never found it. When well understood and powerfully felt, Christianity (with Islam?) rejects immanence, the notion that ‘god’ is in everything, the Hegelian claim that ‘god’ is the Absolute Spirit instead of the Holy Spirit. Holiness means separation; the God of the Bible creates the world out of nothing; He does not extrude a part of himself (dialectically or otherwise) to make the world. The God of the Bible is the God of Providence, not of ‘History.’ “The collapse into violent immanence that characterized the twentieth century”—seen in such historicist movements as communism and fascism, less malignly in progressivism—”derived from the weakening of Christian mediation” (112). The God of the Bible sets loving limits on human action; historicism does not, cannot. But historicism does not even explain the history it claims to know. “The history of Europe… is unintelligible if one does not take into account a very different notion a notion elaborated by ancient Israel, reconfigured by Christianity and lost when the European arc was broken” (113). European history only becomes intelligible if understood as Christians understand Christianity, and this holds true whether one is himself a Christian or not.

    The holiness of God, His separation from man, finds its political bridge in the Covenant. With that, God permitted freedom to man while setting humanly knowable limits to that freedom. Man can ‘talk back’ to God, and God might even change His mind, depending upon what the man has to say. “As great as man is in his pride as a free agent, his action is inscribed in an order of the good that he does not produce an order of grace upon which he ultimately depends” (114). Manent acknowledges that “an important part of contemporary Judaism” no longer trusts the Covenant, asking, Where was God during the Shoah? “This is a natural and so to speak irresistible movement of the soul” (114), but to give in to it entirely would be to fail to recognize the limits of even the several vast genocides of the last century. One of those limits was the Muslim world (despite, one should never forget, the sympathy Hitler found in some elements of it, most infamously exemplified by the Mufti of Jerusalem). “Islam, for its part, does not know how to enter into a moral world that makes no sense to it for two reasons: on the one hand, its relation to God, consisting wholly in obedience, ignores the Covenant; on the other, having nothing to do with the destruction of European Jews, Muslims are hardly able to be sensitive to the infinitely poignant drama playing out between Europe and the Jewish people” (114). Even so, is it not possible that Muslims, also children of Abraham, begin to consider the Covenant he accepted, the relationship to God that the Covenant embodies, if Christians renew “the meaning and credibility of the human association that bore the Covenant until the European arc as broken, that is, the nation” (114-115)? Christians will lose, and Muslims will never gain, the civic life that the God of the Book of Genesis wanted for them unless they act together to rebuild the nation, which is the only viable form for a life of ruling and being ruled within the modern human condition.

    The question then must be: Do Muslims as Muslims want a civil life? Does the Allah-imposed shari’a brought by Muhammad preclude in principle any genuinely political life, any rule by consent? If the right human relationship to God is God-determined obedience to God’s will, with no rational element in it, then Muslims will reject the offer of a common civil life within the nation with repugnance. Manent seems to say: Let us find out. We are at war. We should offer terms for a peace, which may or may not be rejected. And then we will know.

     

     

     

     

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Nations

    Election 2016: Where Are We Headed?

    September 19, 2016 by Will Morrisey

    This lecture was delivered at two Hillsdale College Symposium events in Kerrville, Texas and Georgetown, Texas in September 2016.

     

    In assigning the title “Where Are We Headed?” to a talk on this year’s presidential election, the organizers of this Hillsdale Symposium may have given you the impression that I’ll be predicting the outcome of the November vote. That would be a fool’s errand—which of course may be the reason it was offered to me. But I learned a long time ago that there are far too many variables in most presidential elections to make accurate predictions two months in advance. I don’t pretend to know what will happen. What is more, all of us hear such predictions every time we turn on the television or open a newspaper. We already have more than enough pundits in this country. What could I possibly add to their mountain of a million molehills?

    Besides, when it comes to political predictions generally, I agree with George Orwell. If anything, Orwell was a better journalist than he was a novelist, and in one of his essays he observed that if you ask a man what he foresees you won’t get a reasoned analysis founded on careful observation of the way things are. You will much more likely get an expression of his hopes or his fears. He will tell you not what he thinks but what he feels. You will hear an expression of wishful or woeful thinking. Any sense of the realities of the matter as they exist outside his own head will not trouble him.

    So, no election prediction from me. But the question, “Where are we headed?” can have a broader meaning. There is a kind of political prediction that does make sense to attempt. This being an event sponsored by Hillsdale College, it’s quite possible that when the organizers devised the title they had in mind the opening sentence of a famous speech by Abraham Lincoln delivered to the Illinois Republican State Convention in June of 1858. Now known as the “House Divided” speech, it begins, “If we could first know where we are, and whither we are tending, we could better judge what to do, and how to do it.” Americans had reached the crisis of the house divided because the question of whether or not to extend slavery into the territories had so sharply split American public opinion that it threatened the Union itself. Lincoln argued, “Either the opponents of slavery will arrest the further spread of it, and place it where the public mind shall rest in the belief that it is in the course of ultimate extinction, or its advocates will push it forward till it shall become alike lawful in all the States old as well as new—North as well as South.” Lincoln based this conditional prediction squarely on what men like Senator Stephen Douglas and U. S. Supreme Court Chief Justice Roger Taney were saying at the time.

    So today, in 2016, where are we, and whither are we tending, in the larger sense that Lincoln meant? Today, where does American liberty, our natural and Constitutional right to govern ourselves, where does it stand, a century and a half after Lincoln issued his warning and fought a war to preserve the Union on the foundation of that natural right? In answering that question, I begin by promising you that I will show why it is that Orwell’s observation—that people so often think wishfully or fearfully, not reasonably, with little reference to reality—has become so generally true that it endangers our capacity for self-government, for liberty—the very thing that Hillsdale College “educates for,” and which we’re all here to exercise and support.

    The results of many presidential elections have been hard to predict, but so far this one has been even less predictable than most. In the Democratic Party, United States Senator Bernie Sanders—a socialist who never ran as a Democrat before—ran a campaign in the primary elections against a former First Lady, United States Senator, and Secretary of State that proved embarrassing-all-too-embarrassing to Mrs. Clinton and the Party regulars. And in the Republican Party, real estate developer and television entertainer Donald Trump—who had never seriously run for office at all, on any level—defeated an array of seasoned governors and senators, all of whom began the campaign assuming that `the Donald’ was more tabloid king than presidential prospect. What is going on, here?

    Many commentators point to economic causes, as many commentators so often do. Income inequality is rising, due to the effects of economic globalization. To identify a material or economic cause for any event is the very summit of their wisdom. This would explain a move toward populism and nationalism, all right, but American has seen populism before, and it was very different from what Mr. Trump and Mr. Sanders have had on offer. The 1890s saw depression on he farms and a flood of immigrants to our shores, but William Jennings Bryan stood firmly on the principles of the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution—neither of which has figured prominently in the speeches of Trump or Sanders, let alone Clinton. Populism and nationalism against globalization and economic inequality may explain part of what we’re seeing, but there’s more to it than that. We have the sense that none of these candidates understands where we are, or where we are going, although they are quite eager to lead us there.

    This political tremor, like those in nature, was very long in building. The tectonic plates have been under increasing pressure for more than a century. We need to go farther back than the past couple of decades to see what really is `going on here.’

    I aim to take you back not to any recent presidential election, but to 1840 and the second volume of Democracy in America, the famous book by the French traveler, Alexis de Tocqueville. Tocqueville had arrived here in 1830, commissioned by the French government to report on the American penal system. But his main personal interest in visiting was to come to a better understanding of the political implications of democracy.

    By democracy Tocqueville did not mean the American system of government. Having read James Madison’s tenth Federalist paper, he was well aware that Americans had a republic—a representative government—not a democracy in the ancient Greek sense of a regime in which all the citizens met together to vote laws up or down. Only the New England municipal governments featured such democracy, not the state or national governments. In Tocqueville’s vocabulary, democracy referred not to the government but to the society of America. In America, almost alone in the world at that time, much of society was egalitarian—not, obviously, in the sense that economic equality prevailed here, but because (with two important exceptions) no American could make the monarchic or aristocratic claim, `I am entitled to rule you by right of my birth into the ruling class.’ All Americans were in the ruling class; the people were sovereign. The only aristocrats left in America by the 1830s were the Indians—proud, warlike, and, in Tocqueville’s estimation, doomed to extinction—and the Southern planters—equally proud, almost as warlike, and quite as likely to fight a losing battle against the prolific commercial population of the North.

    In Tocqueville’s view, older societies had an aristocratic class that served as a buffer between the central government and the people, a class with the pride and courage to fight back against the encroachments of centralized power. Modern societies, increasingly without such a class, could see one of two regimes: federal republicanism, in which the states and the innumerable self-governing civil associations, organized by equal citizens, could resist the political center; or statist despotism, in which the state, probably controlled by one man, would abolish citizenship itself and rule without effective resistance. France had already seen despotism in the person of Emperor Napoleon I, and it would see it again in the decades-long rule of Napoleon III. In choosing between these two regimes, Tocqueville favored republicanism, in American and in France; he intended in his book to show Europeans how Americans governed themselves, under democratic social conditions, without an aristocracy to defend them from the central government.

    But the overt military despotism of a Napoleon was not the only kind of despotism Tocqueville feared. There was another, a kind more likely to overtake even Americans. Now, when giving a speech, one general rule is not to do what I am about to do, namely, to read a fairly long passage by some other writer. But this is a Hillsdale College event, and it’s in Texas, so let’s just go ahead and do it, anyway. And besides, this is easily the most intelligent thing I’ll be saying to you today. Even better, my eminent colleague, the political historian Professor Paul Rahe, is wont to read this same passage in some of his lectures. Here is Tocqueville writing in 1840, issuing a warning in the form of a prediction:

    “I want to imagine with what new features despotism could be produced in the world. I see an innumerable crowd of like and equal men who revolve on themselves without repose, procuring the small and vulgar pleasures with which they fill their souls. Each of them, withdrawn and apart, is like a stranger to the destiny of all the others: his children and his particular friends form the whole human species for him; as for dwelling with his fellow citizens, he is beside them, but he does not se them; he touches them and does not feel them; he exists only in himself and for himself alone, and if a family still remains for him, one can at least say that he no longer has a country.

    “Above all these an immense tutelary power is elevated, which alone takes charge of assuring their enjoyments and watching over their fate. It is absolute, detailed, regular, far-seeing, and mild. It would resemble paternal power if, like that, it had for its object to prepare men for manhood; but on the contrary, it seeks only to keep them fixed irrevocably in childhood; it likes citizens to enjoy themselves provided that they think only of enjoying themselves. It willingly works for their happiness; but it wants to be the only agent and sole arbiter of that; it provides for their security, foresees and procures their needs, facilitates their pleasures, conducts their principal affairs, directs their industry regulates their estates, divides their inheritances; can it not take away from them entirely the trouble of thinking and the pain of living?

    “So it is that every day it renders the employment of free will less useful and more rare; it confines the action of the will in a smaller space and little by little steals the very use of it from each citizens. Equality has prepared men for all those things: it has disposed them to tolerate them and often even to regard them as a benefit.

    “Thus… the sovereign extends its arms over society as a whole; it covers its surface with a network of small, complicated, painstaking, uniform rules through which the most original minds and the most vigorous souls cannot clear a way to surpass the crowd; it does not break wills, but it softens them, bends them, and directs them; it rarely forces one to act, but it constantly opposes itself to one’s acting; it does not destroy, it prevents things from being born; it does not tyrannize, it hinders, compromises, enervates, extinguishes, dazes, and finally reduces each nation to being nothing more than a herd of timid and industrious animals of which the government is the shepherd.

    “I have always believed that this sort of regulated, mild, and peaceful servitude, whose picture I have just painted, could be combined better than one imagines with some of the external forms of freedom, and that it would not be impossible for it to be established in the very shadow of the sovereignty of the people”

    To prevent this, as I mentioned, Tocqueville recommended the kind of political society he saw in America: democratic, yes, but federal in its governmental structure, with four levels of government: national, state, county, and municipal, each with its own sources of revenue and its own legal duties and prerogatives. And while the society was not hierarchical the way aristocratic societies are, American had instituted civil associations—voluntary organizations of equal citizens (from fire companies to churches to ethnic self-help societies). A republican regime with a federal state, both underpinned by an egalitarian (that is to say democratic) society full of self-governing civil associations: this was how the Americans had solved the problem of democracy. Americans did not need to succumb to the supine stupidity of soft despotism in the centralized, administrative state because they had arranged their society and their government in a way that preserved and strengthened what Tocqueville calls “the spirit of the city.”

    What does he mean by “the spirit of the city”? He means what Aristotle means by “politics.” Aristotle begins his book, The Politics, by describing the three kinds of rule seen not first of all in the city but in the family. In a family there is the rule of parents over children, the kind Tocqueville mentioned when he said that the aim of fatherly rule is to prepare men for manhood; there is also the rule of masters over slaves. (which, Aristotle says, could be lessened or eliminated if machines were invented that could move themselves). These are both one-way, command-and-obey forms of rule. But there is also the mutual rule of the married couple. This is a two-way relationship, rule by discussion not command; Aristotle describes it as “ruling and being ruled, in turn.” He also says—and this is crucial to understanding “the spirit of the city”—it is the only genuinely political form of rule in the family. It resembles the rule of free, self-governing citizens who deliberate and choose what actions to take in common. Only human beings can govern themselves this way because we are the only species capable of speech and reason. To govern ourselves politically, animated by this “spirit of the city,” is the very opposite of being a timid and industrious animal, herded by our shepherds or leaders.

    Self-government or genuinely political rule consists of a moral dimension and a social one. Morally, it means that the self-governing individual is ruled by his or her distinctively human characteristic: reason. Socially, it means the discussion, the consent, the give-and-take life of ruling and being ruled.

    In the America Tocqueville saw, two elements of the regime lent themselves to self-government: the structure of government and the civil associational character of our society. With respect to structure, and to bring things back to presidential elections, the Framers of 1787 had designed the path to the presidency to bring men of good character into the office of Chief Executive. The Electoral College meets as a body entirely independent of Congress or the Supreme Court. In Federalist #68, Alexander Hamilton sets down the reasoning behind this. As originally designed, the Electoral College “Afford[ed] as little opportunity as possible to tumult and disorder” in the election itself. By voting for electors and not a presidential candidate, voters were “much less apt to convulse the community with any extraordinary or violent movements than the choice of one who was himself to be the final object of the public wishes.” As we know, the Electoral College stopped working as planned—that is, as a deliberative body—as soon as George Washington left office and the Jeffersonians organized against John Adams and the Federalist Party. From then on, Americans were electing persons pledged to a party candidate, not persons prepared to consider and choose a candidate in consultation with delegates from the other states. Nonetheless, to this day the Electoral College does reinforce federalism by ensuring that our presidential elections are conducted as state-by-state campaigns.

    Fortunately, in place of the Constitutional system as intended, Americans found a solution based not on governmental structure but on the other part of Tocqueville’s political equation—civil society organized into civil associations. One of the most important political inventions of the generation following that of the Framers was already established by the time Tocqueville arrived here. Professor James Ceaser of the University of Virginia has written about the American system of political parties, designed by a future president, Martin Van Buren, in the 1820s. A political party is a civil association not mentioned in the Constitution but consistent with the democratic-republic regime of the Founders. It is a civil association designed to organize political vote-getting in a democratic society. In order to moderate the “personal factionalism” and “demagogy” seen in the 1820s, especially during the early years of Andrew Jackson’s political career, Van Buren proposed parties that would require candidates to win support not only from the people, but from “seasoned politicians”—party organizers or `bosses.’ The party bosses had every incentive to win because by winning an election for their party they controlled political patronage in the form of government jobs; would-be officeholders had every reason to listen to the bosses because officeholders needed the bosses’ organizational expertise in order to win election and re-election. The prospect of government jobs also meant the nineteenth century saw very high voter turnouts and strong enthusiasm for party candidates. After all, in every presidential election, each local postmaster’s job was up for grabs. There was no civil-service tenure until much later in the century.

    There’s an old article by a University of Chicago political scientist named Edward Banfield that describes what happened to the old party system; the article dates back to 1961. Almost alone in the reformist atmosphere of the early Sixties and the Kennedy Administration, Banfield stood for unreconstructed political parties. “Anyone who reflects on recent history must be struck by the following paradox: those party systems that have been most democratic in structure and purpose have been least able to maintain democracy.” He would have been thinking of Weimar Germany and the Third and Fourth Republics in France as prime examples of this. “Those that have been most undemocratic in structure and procedure—conspicuously those of the United States and Britain—have proved to be the bulwarks of democracy and civilization.”

    Banfield predicted increased voter manipulation by television news programmers and ideologues if party patronage declined further. A pessimist in Camelot, he predicted that egalitarian reforms would reduce the organized power of the American political system, its ability to get things done. “For as we become a better and more democratic society, our very goodness and democracy may lead us to destroy goodness and democracy in the effort to increase and perfect them.” Twenty years later, after the party reforms of the 1970s, Banfield wrote another article saying in effect, `I told you so.’ “During the Bicentennial period in which we celebrate the achievement of the Founders, we also complete the undoing of it.” The American founding had been undone because the attempt to establish direct democracy within the parties and in our elections—coupled with, I should add, the establishment of the centralized bureaucracy or administrative state Tocqueville had warned of—in practice leads to the ruin of those political authorities who once stood between the people and its most powerful rulers. By the 1980s, the non-aristocratic but not purely democratic bosses who headed the old civil-associational political parties were just about finished. I their place, a centralized by divided elite that attempts to rule a somewhat bewildered, restless people by holding up idols called images and extolling quasi-ideas called `values’ has led us away from Jeffersonian enlightenment and self-government. This has fostered the decline of political experience among ordinary citizens, who no longer understand the spirit of the city, the give-and-take, the ruling-and-being-ruled that only actual civic participation can give.

    The new `insiders,’ journalists and bureaucrats, lack this genuinely political experience. More, they also lack the political responsibility that the Founders prized and that the old bosses and their candidates had shouldered. If a party boss and his candidates lost too many elections, they would be turned out of work. But journalists and bureaucrats have no elections to lose.

    From Woodrow Wilson to George McGovern and down to today, party reformers have disliked the routine politics of getting things done, with its hierarchies and its limited capacity for rapid and radical change. The `open’ system of presidential primaries, which today does not even require that primary voters belong to the party for whose candidate they vote, resembles the factionalized and demagogic system of the 1820s, which Van Buren’s party system was designed to correct.

    But is it not true that the old party system lent itself to corruption? It did. But what is the modern, centralized, welfare, crony-capitalist state but a system of legal corruption that wants to think of itself as progressive, high-minded, and scientific? And, with tenure for civil servants, does this not give us a new aristocracy—hardly a humble `service class’ at all? But this aristocracy does not ‘buffer’ us from the centralized state; it is the centralized state. As the journalist Jonathan Rauch remarks in a recent issue of The Atlantic, in the days of party reform “it was easy… to see that there was dirty water in the tub. What was not so evident was the reason the water was dirty, which was the baby.” The baby was political life itself—messy, impure, inefficient, but also socially democratic and politically republican. Rauch calls the hostility toward American self-government ‘politiphobia,’ and right he is: as bureaucracy and the democratization of candidate selection advance together, we look for the `charismatic’ leader who will solve our problems for us, presumably by the copious use of executive orders.

    Fundamentally, there have been two ways to organize modern states, two ways to connect the central government to the people. One is the political way: by parties whose bosses control the distribution of government jobs but who also depend on keeping in touch with the citizens who will vote their candidates in or out of office. The other is the anti-political way, rule by professional bureaucrats whose claim to command-and-obey authority is based upon supposedly scientific expertise while democratized, de-bossified elections become competitions for media time and a battle of attention-getting ‘tweets.’ The candidates twitter while Rome churns.

    Both political parties have democratized themselves into near-obsolescence, further reducing Americans’ opportunities for real political experience. We often hear it said that regime change or ‘democratization’ won’t work in societies that have no experience in self-government. Well, what about us?

    Americans simply govern themselves less than they once did. This fact is easily obscured by the civil-rights victories of women and African-Americans, but it is no less true for that. And the spirit of the city that Tocqueville esteemed has been transformed by mixing the soft-despotic bureaucracy he described with the new technologies of information and entertainment the spectacularly democratic Internet brings. Today, many of us live large portions of our lives in ‘virtual’ reality, an entirely artificial and almost infinitely manipulable alternative world. Aristotle writes that partisans of democracy define freedom badly, conceiving of it as doing what one likes. The Internet is democratic not only in the usual sense that it erects very low ‘barriers to entry’ but also because it feeds this fantasy of false freedom. Virtual reality disconnects us from the natural reality that surrounds us. The problem is that the disconnection is only in our minds; we still sit and move in actual reality. In virtual reality, if I encounter anything or anyone I dislike, I simply hit the ‘delete’ button. But in actual or natural reality it’s not that easy. In political life, for example, I can easily delete Mr. Putin from my computer screen, but I can’t delete his tanks from Georgia just by hitting a button.

    Insofar as we funnel our minds into virtual reality, we lose patience with one another much more easily. We hit the delete button or change the channel, instead of talking things out, face to face. We cease to be practical. We cease to face reality, and the virtues that had steeled us to face harsh realities soften from disuse. Even as we rebel against the administrative state, we lose our ability to do anything but disrupt it with projects like WikiLeaks and cyberattacks. Those efforts can damage or maybe destroy, but what can they really build, other than websites—that is, more augmentations of virtual reality?

    The ‘social media’ dimension of virtual reality exaggerates another feature of democratic society described by Tocqueville. In aristocratic society, the social pressure to emulate others or to draw back from thoughts and actions others deprecate comes ‘from above’—from our social superiors, those who have established their claim to have been born to rule us. In democratic society, social pressure from above dissipates, replaced by social pressure that comes at us from all around us. We all remember ‘peer pressure’ in school, but the experience of being swarmed by nasty and often anonymous tweets can cause us to draw back even further from saying what we think—unless we too put on the mask of the avatar, which amounts to shedding responsibility for what we say to one another. Madisonian responsibility disappears under this hyper-democratization of public opinion.

    All right. That was the introduction to my talk. Now a word about this year’s election.

    How has this affected the 2016 election. This year, once again the Constitution is at issue, although in some ways less obviously so than in 1912, 1932, or 1964. The one candidate who based his campaign squarely on the hope of restoring the original understanding of American constitutionalism, Senator Ted Cruz, didn’t survive the primaries. Moving into virtual reality, then, what do the campaign websites of the two nominees tell us about how they understand American constitutionalism?

    Senator Clinton’s website has been entirely redone since she won the nomination. The last time I looked at it, the old website featured “112 reasons (and counting!) Hillary Clinton should be our next president.” One of them was that the next president will likely nominate several Supreme Court justices, a remark implying that Senator Clinton would surely make wiser choices than her opponent. Overall, however, the Constitution did not loom large on the list. Solar panels, background checks for gun purchases, student loans, health care, abolition of “sentence disparity between crack and powder cocaine” all got a shout-out. And perhaps above all, Senator Clinton is “a progressive who gets things done”—that being a slap at Senator Sanders, a socialist whose record of legislative achievement had not furnished him with any major talking points.

    It’s fair, then, to say that on Clinton-for-President website 1.0 the candidate self-identified with Progressivism and therefore with the notion of an “elastic” or “living” Constitution, whereby we go from law made by legislators to law made by judges, bureaucrats, and presidents via executive orders. Her list of legislative proposals did not say, but merely assumed, that they are constitutional, for the evident reason that under a living Constitution any ‘live law’ or law-like edict is constitutional. In the immortal words of Senator Clinton’s Progressive ally in the House of Representatives, Congressman Nancy Pelosi, upon being asked if nationalized health insurance is constitutional, “Are you kidding?” Or, as Ring Lardner chronicles the reply of an impatient father to his inquiring boy, “Shut up, he explained.”

    Clinton-for-President website 2.0 is quite different. It still gives us a substantial list of policy proposals. But it never mentions the Constitution or even the Supreme Court at all.

    In 2013 Senator Clinton became the proud recipient of the Liberty Medal, awarded annually by the National Constitution Center in Philadelphia. The Center selected her “in recognition of her lifelong career”—maybe she was baking Cookies for Peace with her mother at the age of two—”in public service and her ongoing advocacy effort on behalf of women and girls around the globe.” That is, the Constitution Center honored her for nothing specifically constitutional. Nor is the award intended for anyone necessarily national, that is to say, American. Last year, it went to the Dalai Lama—an estimable man, but a Tibetan or, if you prefer, a ‘citizen of the world’—a sort of virtual citizenship, inasmuch as the world doesn’t really offer citizenship in itself, having none to offer. Judging from this pattern, globalism trumps both nationhood and constitutionalism at the National Constitution Center. Globalization, however, does suggest a new way of organizing the world, one that vaguely resembles the old international society of aristocrats. Aristocrats married across national borders, forming a sort of interlocking network of birthright rulers. The new international aristocracy consists of a non-titled but exceedingly wealthy elite of similarly cosmopolitan orientation. Such personages do not need constitutionalism; they transcend it.

    Speaking of trumping, the website of the Republican Party nominee turns out to be an interesting mixed bag, so far as the Constitution is concerned. The good news is, it actually mentions the Constitution—or, at least, one part of it, the Second Amendment. And it doesn’t merely assert the right to bear arms. It goes further, saying where the right does not come from: “The Constitution doesn’t create that right—it ensures that the government can’t take it away.” The right to bear arms “is about self-defense, plain and simple.” If we already have a right to defend ourselves, prior to our Constitution—and indeed we were defending ourselves when we fought for our independence from the British Empire—then where does the right come from? Mr. Trump’s website does not say, but at least it doesn’t contradict the fundamental principle of the Founders, that rights exist by nature.

    Similarly, the website is consistent with, without clearly enunciating, the idea that the American union rests on a social contract among its members. “A nation without borders is not a nation” is a sentence implying that human beings come together to form nations, and not that nations arise from ‘blood and soil’—a European notion that has caused no end of trouble in the past two centuries. The call to “end birthright citizenship” also suggests a contractual rather than a biological bond uniting Americans. And it suggests that the widespread interpretation of the Fourteenth Amendment as establishing birthright citizenship is mistaken.

    Extending the search beyond the website itself, we learn that Trump is no Progressive when it comes to his understanding of the Constitution. In a televised interview, Anderson Cooper asked, “Do you see the Constitution as a living, breathing document, or do you see it as something set in stone a long time ago?” A college professor might object that the dichotomy is false and prejudicially stated. The Constitution isn’t “set in stone”; it has been amended 27 times. And the phrase “a long time ago” implies that in its original intent is somehow irrelevant to this day, outmoded. But true to his tendency to go ahead and gulp down his interrogator’s bait, then dare him to try to reel him in, Trump went right ahead and replied, “I see the Constitution as set in stone.”

    His critics are not so sure that he does. For example, when challenged on his stated intention to expand the libel laws to protect public figures such as himself, he cited not the U. S. Constitution but English common law, which does indeed put the burden of proof of libel on the alleged libeler and not the libeled. The obvious problem (as a patriot like Trump should see) is that this isn’t England. Critics have also pointed to Mr. Trump’s apparent enthusiasm for a rather expansive definition of eminent domain, one that seems to include takings of property not merely for clear-cut public goods—a highway, for example—but for the benefit of private developers (such as himself) whose acquisitions would lead to increased revenues or the municipality, and therefor (so his argument goes) serve the public good. That strikes many of us as a bit of a stretch.

    Probably the most intense unease about Mr. Trump’s constitutional bona fides arises in considering the general tone of his campaign. Entertaining and unforgettable it has been. But even his most devoted supporters find it hard to claim that he has elevated the tone of American political discourse. A candidate who takes pride in refusing to keep a civil tongue in his head raises understandable worries about his respect for the framework of civil society itself. The rule of law, including constitutional law, requires an underlying tone of law-abidingness and civility if we are to sustain it.

    On this 240th anniversary of our Declaration of Independence, a year away from the 230th anniversary of the Constitutional Convention, we see a presidential election contest between two candidates who give constitutionally-minded Americans cause for worry. The Democratic Party candidate gives every sign of continuing the longstanding Progressive effort to replace American moral and political principles, in part by treating the Constitution as malleable. To Progressives, the Constitution doesn’t really constitute anything. The Republican Party candidate articulates a reasonably sound basic understanding o the character of American constitutionalism, but also veers off that foundation in ways that do not build confidence in his civility, what might be called his constitutional temper.

    In this, Americans have reaped what academia has sown. Whether we consider the original, university-bred Progressivism of Wilson’s generation, with its elastic or living constitution, or the state-building, centralizing, ‘Brains-Trust’ New-Deal liberalism of FDR and LBJ, or the denigration of civility seen in the New-Left campus politics that has ensconced itself in academia and in the realms of entertainment and the news media in the past half-century, American educator have poorly served their fellow citizens. Although Hillsdale College teaches students in many ways as they were taught when the College began in 1844, when its curriculum was typical of small, liberal-arts colleges, it has since become (to borrow a term from current political debates) an ‘exceptional’ place, mostly because the other colleges and universities have turned away from their original missions. Had the universities continued to follow the path laid down by the Founders in the Northwest Ordinance, and by Jefferson in his plans for the University of Virginia, and by Franklin in his plans for the University of Pennsylvania—or the original intentions of the service academies at West Point and Annapolis—American constitutionalism and American statesmanship would have a very different tone, and our candidates for high office would be different kinds of men and women. Hillsdale would not be ‘exceptional’ in the least.

    The older kind of education was founded on the classics. Far from matters of merely antiquarian interest, the classics always make us look at real things—real human nature, real politics, and the need to live within those realities, not in fantasy worlds of infinite progress or wish-fulfillment. For the Greeks and the Romans, even the gods are human-all-too-human, and in the Bible there is only one perfect Man.


     

    Filed Under: American Politics

    Plato’s Gorgias: The Recovery of Socratic Virtue

    September 15, 2016 by Will Morrisey

    Nalin Ranasinghe: Socrates in the Underworld: On Plato’s Gorgias. South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2009.

     

    If a political man might identify the love of fame as the ruling passion of the noblest minds, what is the ruling passion of the best minds? It is `philo-sophia,’ the love of wisdom, Socrates maintained. But unless defined carefully, neither the love of fame nor the love of wisdom encompasses goodness in the moral sense of the word, virtue or strength of soul. (And even virtue might be redefined immorally, as Machiavelli does with his virtù).

    Nalin Ranasinghe argues for an understanding of Socrates as a man whose love of wisdom reinforced virtue. Contemplating the cosmos, its nature, need not result in amoral estheticism or scientism, let alone immorality. The philosopher who considers the nature of human beings and the human place in nature as a whole will find that the wisdom he loves strengthens his courage, moderation, and justice. The Gorgias, Plato’s account of Socrates’ dialogues with the most eminent Sophist of his day, the Sophist’s disciple, and an impassioned, highly intelligent immoralist, highlights the virtue of Socratic philosophy by plunging Socrates into an underworld of political intrigue and educational corruption.

    Ranasinghe begins by remarking that “many close readings of the Gorgias suggest that Plato uses his text’s many moral impasses to indicate the impotence and inadequacy of Socratic ethics” (1). The “backdrop” of the dialogue—”the long and brutal Peloponnesian War”—itself lends itself to nihilism, even as the First World War and the Holocaust would do, centuries later. But on the contrary: “I will contend that the true focus of the Gorgias is the instrumental perversion of speech introduced by its namesake. Although the trajectory of the dialogue moves away from the sophist himself, Socrates’ extended debate with Callicles employs indirect communication and reductio ad absurdum argumentation to show the itinerant Gorgias the long-germ result of his manipulative technique and moral irresponsibility—effects extending into our own times” (4). Good as his word, Ranasinghe illustrates many points in the dialogue with parallels between Gorgian sophistry and what has come to be called ‘postmodernism,” with its claim that human beings either manipulate or are manipulated by the verbal tropes they invent.
    Against this, “more than any other [Platonic] dialogue, the Gorgias vividly depicts the great value that Socrates and Plato attached to the soul’s freedom and integrity” (4). And even this isn’t strong enough; Ranasinghe’s interpretation finds Socrates and Plato discovering that freedom and attachment, not merely `attaching value’ to it. “The passionately written Gorgias militates against the separation of moral from intellectual virtue and requires that its readers souls be integrated and fully engaged by the labyrinthine work before it” (5). By this act of intellectually erotic integration, our souls re-enact and recover “the Socratic vision of a morally governed cosmos that eventually provided both the language and concepts by which the sublime message of Christianity spread throughout the Hellenized world and gave birth to Western Civilization” (6).

    Socratic philosophy counteracts the nihilism that finds its most courageous expression in Nietzsche, its most democratized expression in the writings of our contemporary disciples of Derrida. But unlike Leo Strauss, who also praised Socrates as the philosopher who stands at the core of the West, Ranasinghe points to the Gorgias, not the Republic, as the Socratic-Platonic dialogue we most need now. In Strauss’s lifetime, the crisis of the West consisted first and foremost of the attack on human nature seen in modern tyranny, usually called (but not by Strauss) ‘totalitarianism.’ As Strauss understood it, the Republic gives its careful reader a devastatingly ironic account of the evil and folly of a political regime that attempts to order human lives as if they were ideas. Today, however, “nihilism replaces totalitarianism as the main challenge facing humans” (7). Ideas in the Platonic sense are not abused; they are dismissed, rejected as nonsense, as `mere rhetoric.’ With its unmasking of the blandishments of sophistic rhetoric, the Gorgias becomes the Platonic dialogue to study now. Strauss was right to recover Platonic political philosophy, but as the political circumstances under which we live differ from those Strauss faced, our ‘point of entry’ into that philosophy should change.

    The dialogue is anything but a history, an account of a series of events that really happened. Even Socrates’ most vehement interlocutor, Callicles, may well be an invention of Plato. But the diplomatic mission of Gorgias to Athens, his successful persuasion of the Athenians to make war on Syracuse on the side of his own embattled city, Leontini, did indeed occur, and the Gorgias “has to do with Socrates’ efforts to heal the effects visited by the plague of rhetoric on the city. In other words, while the Republic warns us against tyrants trying to supplant politics, the Gorgias depicts the contrary danger of a demagogic political regime that would transcend gods and nature and eventually leave everyone alienated from reality” (8). Wars don’t make nihilism; nihilists and their sophistries do. “Gorgias, [who] valued victory over truth, answers over questions, and satisfaction over learning,” who taught men “to use language in an opportunistic or instrumental way,” thereby “corrupted Greek culture and denied humanity the interrelated experiences of participation in the logos and the cosmos,” a severance that “slowly poisons the soul itself” wherever it becomes the regnant “attitude toward life” (8).

    Although not a history, the dialogue has its own order or “interior proportions” (9). These are geometrically exact: four sections of equal length: Socrates’ interrogation of Gorgias; Socrates’ victory over Polus; Socrates “spirited discussion” with Callicles; Socrates’ speech about the underworld. The number 4 parallels the four principles that order the cosmos: earth, air, fire, water. Socrates’ art imitates nature. The imitation of nature by the philosophic artist contrasts sharply with an interpretation of the Platonic dialogues Strauss himself unearthed, namely, the claim by medieval Islamic theologians that “all philosophers are atheists and that ethics merely serves as an exoteric pretext for helping friends and harming enemies” (11). In this, the theologians opposed religious bellecism to philosophic eroticism. But this charge should have been directed at the sophists, not the philosophers; in Plato’s Philebus “Protarchus claims to have heard Gorgias insist that persuasion is superior to all the other arts because it enslaves all of them by their own consent” (12)—just the sort of thing an enterprising immoralist would want to do. Gorgias also anticipates postmodernism by claiming “that in the absence, inaccessibility, or inexpressibility of Truth our reality is held together by a worldwide web of persuasive words” (13). Far from strengthening democracy, sophistry ancient, modern, and postmodern warps the soul into a being incapable of self-knowledge, forgetting its natural place in the cosmos and viewing itself instead “as the measure of reality” (14). Severing the souls of citizens from reality causes democracies to choose their wars foolishly and fight them blindly, sending ignorant armies to clash by night.

    As previous commentators have observed, the word polemou—”war” or “battle”—begins the dialogue. Ranasinghe provides the account of the Leontine embassy to Athens written by Diodorus Siculus, who says that the Athenians were susceptible to Gorgias’ eloquence for two reasons: they “are by nature clever and fond of dialectic,” and so Gorgias’ speech filled them with “wonder”; they had long “been covetous of Sicily because of the fertility of its land” (16). This puts an important limit on Ranasinghe’s gloss—”the gods deluded the Athenians into exchanging much gold (and priceless blood) for a few brazen words of flattery” (17)—because it indicates what really happened: Gorgias was telling them what they wanted to hear, giving them an excuse for their land hunger, rather in the manner that some American orators told their fellow citizens that a continental empire was their “Manifest Destiny.” While the corruptive power of sophistic rhetoric must not be underestimated, it works best with those already somewhat corrupt, given to wishful thinking and even fantasy because their desires are so strong.

    Ranasinghe is especially alert to Platonic play with Greek legends. “Gorgias” sounds a bit like “Gorgon,” and sure enough, Socrates parodies Odysseus’s “deadly fear of the Gorgon’s deadly beauty” (held to turn men into stone) by arriving late to Gorgias’ display-speech. Indeed, Callicles, the host, effectively calls Socrates a coward for arriving late to the battle, a jab he will come to regret having made. Far from cowardly, Socrates will soon put Gorgias himself on display, and not in the most flattering light. But Gorgias begins the battle with supreme confidence, rather as the Athenians will invade Sicily. Socrates’ friend, Chaerephon, had once asked the Delphic Oracle whether there existed any man wiser than Socrates; here “it is Gorgias himself who plays the role of the eminent Oracle,” who promises to answer any question put to him (19). Gorgias supplants a god. “With his feigned omniscience, Gorgias—an intellectual molehill—has made the oracles, and indeed the gods, redundant” (19). Socrates “is not responsible for bringing this strange new god or post-theological phenomenon into the Agora,” but he will meet the invader in battle.

    But Gorgias first sends out an expeditionary force, his student Polus, to test the mettle of the challenger. “It seems that Gorgias is not merely omniscient, [but] also capable of transferring his wisdom to anyone” (20); “it is striking that Socrates was never known to have claimed Chaerephon was his student” (24). This can only occur because to Gorgias and his students ‘omniscience’ derives from their nihilism, their very belief that there is nothing that can be known. If so, omniscience consists in the ability to say anything others can be brought to believe, and no real “religious and moral bonds” to restrain them (20). “For Gorgias the questioning process ends not with truth, or zetetic insight, but in the termination of the wonder that gave rise to the question and its replacement by the satisfaction or pleasure of the questioner. To this way of thinking democratic citizens were but a herd of auditory animals ruled by desire, ignorance, and passion.” (20) By contrast, “Socrates will oppose this bid to draw nihilistic conclusions from what must be seen as conditions for the possibility of human freedom and excellence” (21). Gorgias “bases his claims to omniscience on his power to reduce human diversity to a generic uniformity of need and desire through flattery and obfuscation” (23); he “creat[es] democratic truth, by saying whatever he believes his audience needs and wishes to hear” (25). To Gorgias’ self-deluding delusiveness, Socrates will oppose self-knowledge, the foundation of self-government. To democracy’s tendency toward political arithmetic—counting heads without regard to what is in them, identifying the good with majority opinion, and in our day taking polls the way an invalide imaginaire takes his own temperature—Socrates will oppose geometry, “the art dealing with ratios between naturally unequal entities” (21). He will oppose human freedom to the sophistic/democratic inclination to treat human beings as “free to be bought, sold, and counted like money” (21). In this sense he anticipates philosophically what Abraham Lincoln expressed politically in his debate with Stephen Douglas: natural right against undiluted popular sovereignty.

    For his part, Gorgias enters the fray with such supreme confidence that he agrees to answer Socrates’ questions briefly, not with the long, winding speeches for which he is famous. After all, His Omniscience surely masters discourses long and short. More, he “is so much in love with his cleverness that he displays the naked truth of his art—in the hope of gaining greater acclaim” (26). ‘I am so good at what I do, I can tell you what I am doing to you and still do it.’ And why not, if one conceives of learning not as the noetic perception of reality, of nature, of being, but as an experience of word alone? “The rhetorician only learns from experience to speak eloquently on these very subjects through the experience of speaking frequently on them” (28). “For Gorgias the art of rhetoric is not embodied in or related to nature but rather represents the power of the eloquent will to create a realm of meaning that is independent of elusive or hostile nature” (28-29). Although a Leontine on a mission for his home city, as a sophist Gorgias is a traveling man. Here today and gone tomorrow, scouring the cities of Greece for new audiences and especially clients, he “will inevitably experience and portray reality as thoroughly fickle and changeable” (29). If modern science aims at conquering nature, in manipulating it for human advantage, at least it assumes that nature is really ‘there’ and knowable, even if scientists need to ‘torture’ nature with their ‘experiments’ so as to force her to reveal her secrets. But sophistic rhetoric, ancient and post-modern, operates through language alone, exercising “a pseudo-scientific power that seems to order or conquer nature” with words alone (29), a power to rule in one’s own city or in any city one passes through. “However, as Socrates soon points out, Gorgias and his students do not see that rule of the temperate man over himself, as opposed to the power to rule over others—even if this is limited to the populace of one’s own city—is the greatest human action” (29). Without that, the rhetorician catches himself in the self-contradiction seen in Gorgias’ own way of life: this cosmopolitan undertakes a mission in the service of his own city because even a cosmopolitan needs some physical and political platform upon which to speak. To put it in current-day terms, as I sit peacefully typing these letters onto a computer screen, I may imagine myself as free of nearly all constraints, physical and political. Am I not now entirely a ‘citizen of the world,’ preparing my thoughts for presentation to any reader who happens by, whether next door or in Myanmar? The answer is ‘no.’ I am in fact sitting in a chair, safely at home in a building that does not collapse, protected by police and fire departments, in a country that defends my right to freedom of speech and the press. I am firmly located in nature and in political life, whether I think about it or not. But if I don’t think about those realities, they may well change, and not to my advantage. The apolitical politics of sophist rhetoricians will otherwise deceive me, and them. Or, as Ranasinghe puts it (more forcefully), “a freedom that is created by speech alone tends to threaten to supplement and annihilate the ethos that gives it meaning” (31). The God of the Bible can create something out of nothing by the power of His Word, but I cannot, and even Gorgias cannot. There is “a subtle difference between rule over oneself and self-persuasion”; to ignore it is to engage in “the very delusory act of persuading [one]self that he is engaged in self-creation”  (32). The attempt at self-creation ends in self-destruction. Even God does not create Himself.

    Sophists can manipulate a political community, but they cannot establish one. Ranasinghe asks “how sophists can genuinely interact with each other” (32). As he has learned from Augustine, even robber gangs need to maintain honor amongst themselves. But like the three Gorgons, the three sophists in the Gorgias do not “persuade or converse with one another”; “genuine interaction between avowed relativists and flatterers is impossible” (32-33). They may form alliances, but the friendships upon which social and political life depends cannot exist among them. Socratic philosophy, which openly admits that it know that it doesn’t know, “does not necessarily hurl us to the depths of non-being” or nihilism, the night in which all cows are black and no friends can be found; “prudentially mediated human truth is available in the metaxy or in-between realm, where we ‘participate’ in reality without having creative mastery over it” (33-34). To say that reality or nature is not fully transparent, that full ‘Enlightenment’ is impossible, is not to say that we do not glimpse nature and come to some understanding of it, even if that understanding is limited. Self-knowledge and knowledge of other persons is also limited, but sufficient for strengthening the virtue of souls and friendships among those souls. Sophistic rhetoric blocks these things from happening because it prevents self-correction and shields us from correction by our friends. Socrates can feel gratitude to the one who refutes his argument, but a sophist can feel only resentment, “growing in thumos rather than eros” (37).

    Gorgias does exhibit a sort of prudence; he wants to bail out of his sinking rhetorical ship. Having been forced to choose “between being exposed as a knave or as a fool”—an untrustworthy nihilist who doesn’t believe in the justice to which he must appeal or an incompetent speaker who pretends to supreme technical mastery of speech— he decides that when the going gets tough, the tough get going—right out of town. Or at least out of the conversation. He is rescued from continued embarrassment by his disciple, Polus, who intervenes by attempting to shame Socrates into a like silence. But Socrates proves difficult to shame, inasmuch as he has nothing to be ashamed of.

    Polus attempts a more open defense of rhetoric. Eschewing the appearance of justice, he thinks that “the inherent weakness of human nature makes it possible and necessary that rhetorical power should rule openly over man, nature, and the arts” (45). Socrates slows him down by asking what he thinks rhetoric is. Socrates challenges him to defend himself from the charge that rhetoricians qua rhetoricians do not understand politics at all; they have mastered only “a semblance of a branch of the art of politics” (46). The distinction between what is real and what only seems to be real begins to put rhetoric in its place. Socrates then gets Polus to admit two particular instances of that distinction: the real and only ‘seeming’ health of the soul and the real and only ‘seeming’ health of the body. But if so, Polus owes his interlocutors, and indeed himself, an account of why “the power and glory” that rhetoric brings to the rhetorician is good for anyone, first of all himself. Socrates then names four “false” arts—cookery, cosmetics, sophistry, and rhetoric—false because “they guess at the pleasant without concern or regard for what is best” (48). Cooking with lard results in a tasty cake, but the cook evidently doesn’t care much about my cholesterol count. Similarly, sophistry and rhetoric produce “phantasms” which “supplant natural phenomena and blind us to reality” (48).

    Ranasinghe observes that although victory-loving Polus takes all of this sourly, his mentor Gorgias gets interested in Socrates’ argument, to the extent of breaking his self-imposed silence and asking a question or two. He is at least open to learning. This raises a very good question: “The absence of clear and definite knowledge, especially with regard to nature and the gods, is partly responsible for the prevalence and proliferation of flattery, but this being the case, how can we account for one man becoming a Socrates”—who never flatters without irony—”and another a Gorgias”—who flatters with an eye to power and profit? (49). This directs us to considering “the soul and the foundational moral experiences constituting it” (49). What is good for the soul, that thing sophists, rhetoricians, and philosophers alike must attend to?

    What Ranasinghe considers the second quarter of the Gorgias “begins with Polus indignantly asking Socrates whether he thinks that rhetoric is but flattery” (50). Socrates deflects what he rightly considers a ‘rhetorical question,’ then denies Polus’ assertion that rhetoricians enjoy great power in the city. In so doing, he does points the young man to a more careful understanding of what power is; “the word translated power, dunamis, means ‘potential’ and is not considered something desirable in itself… Raw potential needs to be realized and actualized as energeia; otherwise happiness (eudaimonia) will not result” (51). Rhetoricians may or may not succeed in manipulating public opinion, but they lack real power because they depend upon their audience. And even when they succeed, they fail, because “tyrannical acts of this kind defeat the purposes inherent in human action itself to desire and do what is best” (52). Power exists for a purpose; it is not an end in itself. To treat power as if it were a purpose “only destroys the deliberative capacity essential to making something turn out for the best” (53). “Power should not be purchased at the cost of self-knowledge” (54), as the Delphic oracle might say.

    Socrates goes on to make his celebrated, radical argument that suffering evil is better than doing evil. “To Polus’s way of thinking, the interior (the intellect) is a calculating infrastructure that exists purely for the greater glories of one’s image and passions” (58). The tyrant Archelaus is his hero—Archelaus, who not only sustained his tyranny but burnished his reputation by patronizing Euripides, thus doing “all he could to ensure that his legacy was spun to the best extent possible” (58). But Socrates is the last person to allow himself to be swayed by image-makers and the favorable public opinion they inspire. “This Archimedean Point of personal integrity”—this refusal to ‘go along to get along,’ much less to warp one’s perceptions in order to bring oneself into accord with what ‘everybody else says’—”represents an understated reference to what is surely terra incognita to Polus: the human soul” (59). Socrates found in himself the strength of soul to resist public opinion up to and including its verdict of death upon Socrates. “While Polus regards the soul egotistically as a power capable of triumphing in the shadow games played out on the wall of the cave, Socrates’ soul exists in another dimension of reality—one where moral principles are not created by necessity but rather guide the actions of free men” (59). “Socrates does not claim that unjust or excessive punishment is good; it would not be good for a minor offender to be delivered into the hands of sadistic and vicious judges. We may well contrast the strikingly different manner in which Jesus and Socrates were executed. It is also significant that Socrates viewed the relatively mild manner of his death as a sign of great divine favor” (61). It is also significant that Socrates never implied that he was God; he was charged with the impiety of denying the existence of the gods, not of claiming to be God.

    Socrates undermines Polus’ self-assurance by inducing him to admit that although “it is worse to suffer injustice than to inflict it,” it is also “more shameful or ugly (aiskion) to do injustice than to suffer it” (63). But if so, then there must be some way to define the noble and the shameful, to distinguish them, and thus to account for our feelings of shame at doing injustice. Committing a shameful act is not physically painful, as suffering injustice often is, but then our discomfort must stem from some sense that injustice is bad for us. The soul has something in it that feels bad when it does bad things. “Doing injustice is worse than suffering it” (64) because doing injustice troubles the soul, whereas suffering injustice pains the body.

    Although Polus concedes the truth of this, Ranasinghe remarks that a man “ruled by shame” might still commit injustice if he knew his crimes would go undetected. If Polus could make himself invisible, would he still avoid wrongdoing? To truly come around to Socrates’ view, Polus would need to see “why what is shameful and bad, is bad for him” (64), whether or not others knew his crimes. This is the weakness of the rhetorician’s soul, dependent upon public opinion, partly resentful of its sway and attempting to manipulate it, but finally bowing to it. This is why Socrates next suggests that of the three kinds of baseness—poverty, disease, and “defects of the soul”—the latter is worst because it alone brings “moral repugnance” in its train (66). This “psychic account of evil,” this understanding of evil as damaging to the soul of the evildoer, stands as “one of the deepest insights provided by the Gorgias” (66). If the remedy for poverty is money-making and remedy for disease is medicine, the remedy for defects of soul is “the art of justice” (67). The demi-art of rhetoric won’t cure a defective soul. “The true arts… connect the self to reality, rather than knack-like methods for excessive material accumulation or thumotic display without any moderating form or limiting principle” (68). The tyrant Archelaus terrorizes and image-builds adroitly, but why should one envy him his soul? “Human flourishing or happiness occurs in a setting requiring the individual soul to interact with others in the world through speeches and deeds…. [T]his is precisely what an unjust life cannot allow since it seeks to make itself the center or omphalos of being. Accordingly it sets out to warp everything, including the perception of other humans, around its singular and diseased perspective on reality” (70). Nor should we admire the democrat. “The chronic democratic temptation to pursue ‘freedom for oneself and hegemony over others’ ignores the crucial Archimedean point of self-rule” (70).

    Socrates seldom speaks in public. He practices his dialectic on individuals in private. This comports with his insistence on the importance of the souls of his interlocutors. He does not seek to shame them in public, although he may cause them to blush in shame in front of a small circle of friends and relatives. Public shaming does not reach into the individual soul. Shaming by public rhetoric will not cure the soul so shamed. Shaming by private dialectic leads the individual soul to convict itself, and thus to desire to cure itself. “Our ignorance about what is positively just is unavoidable as long as the state, rather than the soul is viewed as the origin of virtue”; “a true regime of virtue can only be founded in the soul; it can never be imposed on [or, in any thoroughgoing way, by?—WM] any larger unit” (75). “Socrates teaches Polus, a professional rhetorician, to see the limitations of this outlook by helping him to understand that speech and truth, rather than being derivative from manipulated appearances, were founded on the moral quality of the soul and the reality of the world. In other words, Polus is shown the intentional structure immanent in speech itself; he also sees how this order reflected the self-evident teleology of the human desire for what was truly noble and good” (76). “Rhetoric works through breaking down the unity of the human soul into a great many unruly and needy desires”; this is to say that rhetoric ‘democratizes’ the soul, persuades it to imitate the desirous clamor of assembly and marketplace (76). “Conversely, Socrates’ art sets out to restoratively recollect the integrity of the individual and the genuine plurality of the citizenry,” while also “restor[ing] the self-knowledge of the soul and the self-evidence of the kalon [the noble]”—a restoration indispensable to both man and citizen.

    Seeing that Polus began to lose the argument when he admitted to the experience of shame, Callicles jumps into the dialogue with an assertion of his own proud shamelessness. “Far more of a hedonist and nihilist” than Gorgias or Polus, Callicles proves “far harder to educate than either of the other two men” (77). He speaks “for the blinded and speechless desires” (78). Socrates accordingly replies by describing the two loves in the souls of the two men: Socrates loves Philosophy and Alcibiades, Callicles the Athenian people and Demos, son of Cleinias. But this means that Socrates loves the intelligent, Callicles the unintelligent. And Callicles confuses himself by claiming that his twin loves are really expressions of his own version of natural aristocracy, namely, the strength of his soul needed to pursue one’s desires without moderation. “Unlike Polus, who prefers to be one of the manipulators of shadows in the cave, Callicles desires to be powerful and shameless enough to charge into the cave like a rampaging lion and terrorize its hapless denizens” (84). To him “philosophy is the earliest and lowest stage on the intellectual ladder that culminates in tyranny” (85); he advises the aged Socrates to quit acting like a child. Anticipating the advice of the ‘postmoderns,’ Callicles would make philosophy into “a language game that future leaders must learn to play so that they may lie fluently to the masses when it’s time to go down to the cave and preside over the shadows” (87). “According to Callicles’ upside-down realism, men can only grow up when they become just as unjust, irrational, and power-driven as reality itself” (88).

    How can Socrates reply to such a man? In the dialogue’s third part, “the obstacles Socrates faces in his agon with Callicles are quite unlike those he encountered with Gorgias and Polus? (94). Recalling the tripartite division of the soul outlined in the Republic, Ranasinghe finds the dialogue with Gorgias to have been “abstract and cerebral”—a battle fought by reasoning “on the chessboard of ideas” (94). The dialogue with Polus centered on thumos or spiritedness, with Socrates showing him that the very nature of logos or speech, the rhetoricians’ stock in trade, did not lend itself to the satisfaction of the “personal pursuit of political power and glory” (94). But Callicles valorizes the third ‘part’ of the soul, the desires; his “cultivated shallowness ensures that his pursuit of hedonism cannot be interrupted either by pure intellectual speculation or by practical reflections within himself concerning the compatibility between his methods and his long-term goals” (94). “Libido ergo sum is his intemperate motto,” as he “aspires to be the strongest beast amid chaos” (94-95). More, “Callicles’ shameless words, once acted on, will help to create the chaos in which he expects to thrive” (95). Callicles combines the teachings of Callicles with the lawless and tyrannical ethos of wartime Athens, the Athens of the Thirty Tyrants.

    But this combination cannot sustain itself, any more than the Athenian empire could. If Callicles would dominate chaos, he himself must remain resolute, not chaotic. But if the chaotic ‘many’ who rule in democracy are the stronger, and they legislate for equality, then must they not be the truly natural men, not Callicles? Socrates thus shames the shameless Callicles, “making [him] feel an interior dimension that he most manifestly cannot control through violent power, a cave whence he cannot storm out like an unchained young lion” (98). “Callicles’ chaotic reality is much like ours; peopled by ungrateful freedmen, it is like Plato’s Cave without anyone in charge of the shadows” (101). Once again, in a way Socrates himself does not win the argument; logos does. Socrates “starts to triumph over Callicles the moment he forces his adversary to describe his infinite desire in words” (105).  Callicles tries to escape into silence, but it is too late. Returning the favor that Callicles had done him when he had tried gracefully to bow out of his own dialogue with Socrates, Gorgias intervenes to urge Callicles on—for his, Gorgias’, sake and for the sake of the argument. Gorgias understands that in refuting the arguments and assertions of his students, Socrates embarrasses the master rhetorician himself, the man whose career depends upon never being ‘shown up.’

    Radical hedonism requires its devotee to refuse “solidarity with the rest of reality” but instead to use it as if the cosmos were a peach to be sucked dry by the hedonist (112). Ranasinghe criticizes Devin Stauffer for regarding Callicles’ hedonism as inconsistent because he praises prudence and courage, arguing that for Callicles these virtues are merely instrumental to his pursuit of pleasures. Similarly, he criticizes Stauffer for claiming that Callicles’ professed admiration for certain prominent Athenian statesmen bespeaks a “commitment to something beyond glory and hedonism” (114 n. 25). Callicles is more likely to (mis)understand such statesmen in the manner characteristic of Callicles’ assumptions: as instances of Athenian glory and dominance. “Conversely, a Socratic would attach great value to the Athenian discovery of the connection between logos and the cosmos” (114 n. 25). It might have been better to have written “discover great value in” rather than “attach great value to.” However that may be, “Callicles’ problems stem from knowing too much about his desires and too little about his soul” (115); “one who lives by desire cannot see his soul as anything but a nexus for the continued enjoyment of pleasure” (116). Gorgias, who is not nearly so far gone in mindlessness, watches and listens, and maybe learns. But Ranasinghe does not contend, as Stauffer does, that Gorgias will ever truly befriend Socrates because “there is a fundamental difference between rhetoric and philosophy”: “Dialectical speech is ruled by its ends and cannot proceed by the sophistical devices of exploiting ignorance and creating false certainty. While Gorgias pushes ignorance, Socrates’ eloquence comes from his being pulled towards a cosmic order that he will soon describe” (118 no. 29).

    In politics, Callicleanism plays out as a quest for Athenian glory by means of the cultivation of the strong amidst the chaos of the weak. The shameless, hedonic master spirits will thrive in the democratic chaos of Athens, rule the stupid and spineless many, and thereby turn Athens among the cities into the kind of ravening lions they are, among the Athenians. Like themselves, Athens will prove voracious, rapacious, and dominant. Socrates opposes his ‘theory of the ideas’ to this because the ideas or forms are “not simply creatively imposed from above” but “discovered” as the self-definitions of nature. Reasoned speech, guided by the principle of non-contradiction, describes the nature of which it is a part; to be governed by reason is the soul’s true nature. Just as “physicians generally allow healthy people to satisfy their desires, but do not extend such freedoms to the sick—presumably because their desires are in disarray,” so the soul, when “filled with vices… must not be permitted to indulge its desires and perform actions other than those which will improve it” (119). This is “why just punishment—even including death—may be preferred to living on with a diseased and untreated soul” (119). Socratic ‘idealism’ is “more realistic” than Calliclean ‘realism’ (122).

    The final part of the Gorgias consists of Socrates’ own speech, his own rhetorical performance, as he tells a myth that illustrates what he has argued dialectically in the first three parts. Ranasinghe observes that Socrates, having defeated each of his three would-be conquerors, has left himself to deliver a “sort of internal dialogue” (123) in fact, he does not call this a myth at all, but a logos, clearly implying that he regards his speech as an extension of his reasoned argument. Unlike the sophistical rhetoricians, “the philosopher will emphasizes causes and ends rather than effects and means; he also privileges the recovery o erotic being over the sophistical aim of creative dominion over godforsaken becoming” (124).

    Socrates has argued that the good is superior to pleasure, that the good means the presence of virtue in the soul, and that virtue means right order. Right order in the soul is by nature, but this natural order can be improved or deranged. Philosophy improves it, sophistry deranges it. “The very nature of the incomplete but erotic human soul seems to necessitate that it choose and actualize its own virtue from within itself, albeit in circumstances that inspire it toward transcendence with a vision of the nobility and beauty of the cosmos” (124). Happiness “is an internal state of flourish that is not dependent on external events” (125); eudaimonia “literally means having a happy guiding spirit” (125). Old, henpecked, poor, ugly Socrates is a happy man because he loves wisdom, opens his soul to the order of the cosmos and orders his soul so as better to understand the cosmic order. His reason rules him, and so his soul does not oscillate between prickly, honor loving thumos and self-contradictory physical desires. By contrast, the tyrant’s deranged, badly ordered, soul cannot trust others because it cannot trust itself; it cannot trust itself because it whipsaws from one tormenting desire or fear to another (128).

    This rightly-ordered soul comports with the well-ordered cosmos. In perceiving, partially understanding, and teaching others about the cosmos the man of this always limited, but always growing wisdom serves as a kind of daimon or messenger from the cosmic order to his fellow-men; the order of his soul, conveyed by his speaking and reasoning, his logos, improves the orderliness of their souls. In so doing, he adds a bit to the good order of the cosmos of which all human beings form a part. “This cosmic flourishing is neither a divinely granted revelatory dispensation… nor is it a wholly human creation” (130). It is an act of “non-coercive erotic authority” (131). “God is neither dead to the world nor a double-predestining, doom-dealing puppeteer”; to believe so is to reject the metaxy, that in-between position “where participation [in the cosmic order] occurs,” which “cannot be over-determined” (131). “What Socrates has described is a partnership between the human and the divine that allows god to be god and man to be man” (131). There cannot be “perfect knowledge of all that ever will be,” nor can there be “perfect technical knowledge over human souls” (133). And this is good news for human beings and for the cosmos itself. The modern-philosophic promises to achieve such mastery over nature “through the existence of technical power” (133) are both impossible and bad. “Socrates’ point is that instead of being based on selfish calculations regarding probable events in the future quite beyond man’s (or god’s) control, human beings should instead be ruled by the ideas of justice and temperance,” a condition of the soul that puts it “into harmony with the cosmic order” (134). The philosopher is the daimon who brings this message (or, to use another Socratic metaphor, the midwife who delivers), this modestly improved orderliness to human souls by bringing them to imitate the cosmos instead of trying vainly (in both senses of the word) to master it. Friendship can then replace manipulative rhetoric and tyranny. In his final comment to Socrates, Callicles indicates that he “now knows what Socrates was talking about, even though his body is un-persuaded by this non-rhetorical reasoning” (141). He will never philosophize, but he can be brought to think, a little. This is one modest achievement of Socrates’ “true political art” (142), and the limitations of the achievement underline Socrates’ ready insistence that human speech can only go so far in its effects. When a radio quiz show host asked witty Dorothy Parker to use the word ‘horticulture’ in a sentence, she famously replied, “You can lead a whore to culture, but you can’t make her think.” Socrates would say you might be able to, but just barely. Both the ugly old man and the beautiful young men and women will discover that limits to their erotic attractiveness. If Socrates goes before a jury in Athens, he already knows what the likely verdict will be.

    Socrates final logos describes the cosmic order in terms of the god Kronos and his sons Zeus (a god of the sky, the air), Poseidon (a god of the earth and the sea), and Pluto or Hades (a god of the underworld). The “underworld” of Ranasinghe’s title refers to Hades, and the actual underworld Socrates is “in” is the city, the Cave of the Republic and specifically the city of Athens; in each of these three underworlds, the “denizens have ‘no-idea’ (a-eidos) of who they are, but see and know themselves only as shadows,” manipulated by “orators, poets, and politicians” (149). Although Zeus is the god of the sky, he is not the sky itself. “The mysterious distinction between the sky and the gods is better understood when we take the sky to represent a realm of eternal unchanging ideas to which even the gods are subject; this issue was notably examined in the Euthyphro—where the virtues are recognized by the gods and cannot be whatever the arbitrary deities happen to fancy. The further implication of this is that the gods themselves are but time-bound representatives of the Platonic forms or ideas” (150).

    Similarly, human beings come from the earth, but are not the earth. They are down-to-earth political animals, but also capable of navigating by the stars in the sky. Socrates, the messenger who mediates between sky and earth, gods and men, is guiltless of the charge the Athenians bring against him, the charge of impiety. He did not introduce “strange deities” to replace the gods of Homer; “rather, he is upholding the higher timeless principles that the sky represents in his model of the four-fold [cosmos]” (151). In the Gorgias he “provides a logos of psychic interiority to support its after-worldly mythos (152). In so doing, he would replace the warrior-gods of Homer (who have misled Athenians into believing they can fight the Peloponnesian War as if they were Achilles and Odysseus at Troy) while resisting the blandishments of Dionysus, “the demi-god of drunken democracy” (158), at whose shrine ambitious young Athenians like Callicles are inclined to burn the candles of their souls. “Socrates overthrows the blood-stained Olympian tyrant and replaces him with a regime of virtue” (156), a regime strong enough to resist the insurgent Dionysians, as well.

    The Socratic regime or “way of life” rests on five tenets: “fear doing injustice more than suffering it”; “value being good in private and public over seeming good”; “see that goodness comes first with just punishment next”; “flee all flattery”; “take care that rhetoric should be used only to serve justice” (160). The “true political art” or statecraft founds this new regime of the soul’s self-knowledge, against the bad regime of a soul corrupted by those who “pander pleasure and pain” (161). In the larger realm of city politics, Athens must “disgorge her vast imperial acquisitions,” the winnings “of the grandiose imperialism of Cimon and Pericles” (161). “The future of the School of Hellas must be found in thought rather than deed,” as “the torch of Prometheus is passed from Pericles to Plato,” from whom it will eventually “blaze open a path that will carry the imperishable logos from Jerusalem, through the Hellenized World, all the way to Rome” (161). Ranasinghe thus modestly points the reader toward his own Catholicism, often held to combine Athens and Jerusalem, reason and revelation.

    In his epilogue, Ranasinghe recalls Gorgias’ “triple denial of Truth’s existence, its know-ability, and its speak-ability” (162). Socrates rejects both Gorgias’ claims about nature and (consequently) his “way out of the abyss by persuasive manipulation of democratic opinion” (162). “Like the Gorgon’s head, seductive sophistry has the power to kill souls by placing them in a this-worldly Hades” (162). Socratic dialectic liberates souls from this cave or underworld. “Since Christianity has altered Socrates’ model by externalizing good and evil and placing the complementary concepts of an omnipotent merciful God and original sin, like a good and bad angel, on either side of us, the resultant synthesis is unequal to the task of confronting the problem of evil unless the soul’s power to choose between good and evil is taken very seriously” (163). One does so by seeing the parallel between the natural order of the soul and the order of nature itself, the homology of man and cosmos which the daimon/philosopher can show us by his dialectical arguments. “Socrates suggests that it is within the power of the human soul to deliberate well and prudently when confronted with the many dyadic categories (freedom and necessity, good and evil, nobility and vice) that operate on it” (164). Socrates proved this to be possible by living the philosophic way of life, embodying the self-knowing, soul-ordering regime of philosophy.  Contra Machiavelli, who teaches that men must learn not to be good in order to survive in a dangerous world, Socrates shows that “good humans do their polity a priceless service by constantly proving that virtue is immune to the false necessity of vice” (167). Such humans can be true friends, and true friendships strengthen the political community. “Socrates’ inspiring example suggests that true happiness is gained neither through ‘spinning’ vain fabrications in the void nor by being envied in the cave-like abyss of non-being”; eudaimonia can only be earned by using the `enduring power’ of the human soul to participate in the beauty of the cosmos” (168).

    In considering the interpretations of Devon Stauffer and Nalin Ranasinghe, one sees that both scholars recover the Socratic understanding of the philosopher as a man of both intellectual and moral virtue. Stauffer emphasizes Socrates’ efforts at reforming rhetoric, at teaching Gorgias how his art might be put to better use if it observed the virtues of justice and moderation. Ranasinghe pays more attention to Socrates’ use and understanding of Greek myths as a way of showing the connection between the distinctive feature of human nature, logos, and the larger nature or cosmos which our logos perceives and attempts to describe. In rightly delineating the limits nature sets on human beings, the philosopher’s way of life finds its home in the cosmos. But this ‘cosmopolitanism’ respects the political order that human speech and reason also generate, by arts that can do a better job of aligning that order with nature than sophists and rhetoricians have been inclined to do, then and now. Both of these studies prove to be good companions in the sociable, political philosophy Socrates inaugurated.

     

     

     

     

     

     

     

     

     

    Filed Under: Philosophers